14.02.2013 Views

Gruber P. Convex and Discrete Geometry

Gruber P. Convex and Discrete Geometry

Gruber P. Convex and Discrete Geometry

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

134 <strong>Convex</strong> Bodies<br />

Mean Width <strong>and</strong> the (d-1)st Quermassintegral<br />

As a simple consequence of Hadwiger’s functional theorem we derive the following<br />

identity:<br />

Corollary 7.1. Wd−1(C) = κd<br />

w(C) for C ∈ C, where w(C) is the mean width<br />

2<br />

of C,<br />

w(C) = 2<br />

�<br />

hC(u) dσ(u).<br />

d κd<br />

S d−1<br />

Proof. The main step of the proof is to show that<br />

(20) w(·) is a valuation.<br />

To see this, let C, D ∈ C be such that C∪D ∈ C. In the second proof of Theorem 6.10<br />

we showed the following equalities for the support functions of C ∩ D <strong>and</strong> C ∪ D:<br />

(21) hC∩D = min{hC, h D} <strong>and</strong> hC∪D = max{hC, h D}.<br />

Proposition (20) can now be obtained as follows:<br />

w(C) + w(D)<br />

= 2<br />

�<br />

(hC(u) + h D(u)) dσ(u)<br />

d κd<br />

= 2<br />

d κd<br />

S d−1<br />

�<br />

S d−1<br />

min{hC(u), h D(u)} dσ(u) + 2<br />

d κd<br />

= w(C ∩ D) + w(C ∪ D)<br />

�<br />

S d−1<br />

max{hC(u), h D(u)} dσ(u)<br />

by (21), concluding the proof of (20).<br />

w is a valuation by (20). It is easy to see that it is continuous, rigid motion<br />

invariant <strong>and</strong> positive homogeneous of degree 1. Hadwiger’s functional theorem then<br />

shows that w is a multiple of Wd−1. NowletC = B d <strong>and</strong> note that dWd−1(B d ) =<br />

d κd by Steiner’s formula <strong>and</strong> w(B d ) = 2 to determine the factor. ⊓⊔<br />

7.4 The Principal Kinematic Formula of Integral <strong>Geometry</strong><br />

The following quote from Santaló [879], preface, gives an idea of what integral<br />

geometry is all about:<br />

To apply the idea of probability to r<strong>and</strong>om elements that are geometric objects (such<br />

as points, lines, geodesics, congruent sets, motions, or affinities), it is necessary, first,<br />

to define a measure for such sets of elements. Then, the evaluation of this measure<br />

for specific sets sometimes leads to remarkable consequences of a purely geometric<br />

character, in which the idea of probability turns out to be accidental. The definition<br />

of such a measure depends on the geometry with which we are dealing. According<br />

to Klein’s famous Erlangen Program (1872), the criterion that distinguishes one

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!