17.01.2013 Views

Charisma Reconsidered

Charisma Reconsidered

Charisma Reconsidered

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

nothing prior to itself other than more taboos, such as the taboo on the body of<br />

the chief. But here we face a familiar trouble. The mana of the imposer is the<br />

source of the power of interdiction. But mana is as unhelpful a concept as<br />

charisma, in the sense that it too is a dead end. In these societies, power is the<br />

power to interdict, and mana is a name for this power, not an explanation<br />

(Steiner, 1967 [1956]: 110). This is a difficult notion to grasp, but the point can<br />

be made with a simple example. As a child I lived in a Catholic neighborhood,<br />

where the Monsignor of the local parish church routinely imposed interdictions –<br />

on forms of behavior and dress, on membership in organizations, even on what<br />

bars to patronize. What was the religious ‘authority’ for this? There was no literal<br />

authority, though there was the notion that he possessed delegated powers from<br />

the Pope, who had them delegated from Jesus through Peter – hardly an active<br />

consideration for those choosing what bar to patronize. Yet the uncertainty<br />

surrounding the dangerous powers of the Monsignor himself meant that to<br />

violate them was to act dangerously. Similarly for the imposition of taboo: what<br />

enables the imposition of taboo is not a power of an imposer, like magic, or<br />

charisma, which is a term like mana, but the effect of the act of interdiction, the<br />

localization of danger itself. It is tempting to say that it is a vaguely felt fear of<br />

the interdictor that enables the interdiction to have force, or that the reason a<br />

given interdiction has force is fear of the imposer. But it is doubtful, in a situation<br />

of generalized danger, that saying this amounts to anything more than the<br />

interdictor is part of ‘the dangerous’ and that any interdiction from this source<br />

serves to localize danger. This in turn is all that Steiner is saying. But it has the<br />

uncomfortable Nietzschean implication that the root of morality is fear of<br />

the other.<br />

When we consider the broader question of the establishment of perceptions<br />

of risk, it is evident that the actions of individuals – whether Madonna or a<br />

political leader – serve to define risks just as the pronouncing of interdictions does.<br />

Indeed, one may wonder whether the alteration of risk perceptions through action<br />

is a more fundamental mechanism than interdiction. The power to interdict may<br />

be the province of those who have mana, and this may be what mana consists in.<br />

But it is also plausible to say that this power is itself rooted in fear – in taboo, as<br />

Steiner says – which is in the end no more than a localization of the non-specific<br />

dangerousness of those who may bring harm to one and thus must be obeyed.<br />

The magical properties we attribute to the powerful (and which Weber takes to be<br />

the concomitant of charisma), on this account, are no more than an aspect of the<br />

localization of danger itself. If this is reasonable, there is no mystery about<br />

primitive charisma: it is a by-product of the localization of danger that individuals<br />

can, through their own actions, influence, and the fact that they can increase the<br />

sense of their dangerousness or sacredness through their own actions.<br />

The case that was puzzling for Weber himself was the idea of charismatic<br />

law-givers who were assigned a particular historical role in the origins of legal<br />

orders. The traditional puzzle of the philosophy of law of which Weber was well<br />

TURNER CHARISMA RECONSIDERED 19

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!