09.01.2013 Views

In 1926: living at the edge of time - Monoskop

In 1926: living at the edge of time - Monoskop

In 1926: living at the edge of time - Monoskop

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

xii USER'S MANUAL<br />

Theses<br />

Since we do not know wh<strong>at</strong> to do with our vast and rapidly accumul<strong>at</strong>ing<br />

knowl<strong>edge</strong> about <strong>the</strong> past (history no longer having any obvious<br />

pragm<strong>at</strong>ic function), we should examine <strong>the</strong> more or less preconscious<br />

impulses th<strong>at</strong> may motiv<strong>at</strong>e our fascin<strong>at</strong>ion with history. This<br />

book presupposes th<strong>at</strong> a specific desire is <strong>at</strong> work here: a desire "to<br />

speak to <strong>the</strong> dead"-in o<strong>the</strong>r words, a desire for first-hand experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> worlds th<strong>at</strong> existed before our birth. <strong>In</strong> c<strong>at</strong>ering to this desire,<br />

<strong>the</strong> book brings forth-more implicitly than explicitly-certain fe<strong>at</strong>ures<br />

<strong>of</strong> wh<strong>at</strong> "we" (educ<strong>at</strong>ed people within <strong>the</strong> Western culture <strong>of</strong><br />

1997) imagine "history" to be. We all seem to agree th<strong>at</strong> we no<br />

longer think history as a "unilinear" and "totalizing" dynamic <strong>of</strong><br />

"development." Beyond this neg<strong>at</strong>ion, however, <strong>the</strong>re is no single<br />

dominant form <strong>of</strong> imagining and representing history. If we imagine<br />

and represent it synchronically, as this book does, we realize th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

elements <strong>of</strong> such a synchrony do not converge into a coherent and<br />

homogeneous picture. Never<strong>the</strong>less, and perhaps paradoxically, this<br />

book suggests <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a "web" or "field" <strong>of</strong> (not only<br />

discursive) realities th<strong>at</strong> strongly shaped <strong>the</strong> behavior and interactions<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>1926</strong>. So strong indeed is this impression th<strong>at</strong>, <strong>at</strong> least<br />

implicitly, this book makes a plea against any claims for subjective<br />

or collective agency. And how could a book concerned with historical<br />

simultaneity not arrive <strong>at</strong> this very conclusion? After all, <strong>the</strong>re are no<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> action and agency th<strong>at</strong> do not require sequentiality as<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir frame <strong>of</strong> reference. Yet this is exactly <strong>the</strong> one form <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

history with which <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> historical simultaneity is incomp<strong>at</strong>ible.<br />

Context<br />

We cannot avoid <strong>the</strong> impression th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong> current intellectual situ<strong>at</strong>ion<br />

in <strong>the</strong> humanities-<strong>at</strong> least when seen from <strong>the</strong> present-marks a<br />

compar<strong>at</strong>ively weak moment. (Of course, such an impression may

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!