11.09.2023 Views

Bodmer_Publication

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Notes

1 Sears (1996: 60 – 61) quite typically says that

the quality of Bodmer’s work “owes much

to the picturesque mode of depicting

landscapes in which Bodmer was trained,”

but that it also “reflects Bodmer’s service

to Maximilian’s scientific purposes.” His

subtle analysis of those Bodmer prints that

represent Eastern material results on the

whole from his precise knowledge of

artistic conventions, rather than a

conclu sive argument regarding the relation

between art and science. This analysis is

not provided by Ruud (2004) either,

though the relation is a recurrent theme

in his essay.

2 See in this context, for example,

Lorraine Daston’s works on the formation

of scientific objectivity and particularly

Stafford (1984).

3 The introduction to the

“Querschnittsbereich ‘Bild und

Bildlichkeit’” in the 2006/2007 annual

report of the Thyssen Foundation does,

however, show that to think in images

is frequently seen very differently:

when it says “that alongside the culture

of the image that we find in the arts

instrumental imageries have established

themselves in the sciences,” (Thyssen 2007:

190) the opposition art / science remains

alive or it is even reinforced.

4 Cf. Tyler, who opposes “objectivity” and

Maximilian’s “neoclassical instincts”

to “the romantic interpretations that were

then in fashion.” (Tyler 2004: 21; cf. 15, 17,

40, in what on the whole is a well-informed

discussion.) His earlier quotation from

Humboldt does not support his reading.

Ruud (2004a: 50 – 51), on the other hand,

is a special case: he presents a very

com petent sketch of Humboldt’s views

on the union of art and science, and

he recognizes their immense importance

for Bodmer and Wied. But in his ensuing

discussion of individual plates, the conflict

between the two sides becomes promi -

nent, so that his perspective on the

whole remains uncertain.

5 Cf. Hunt (2002: 99) who ascribes to

the artists of the American West a

general “accuracy of observation,” but

also reproaches them with “a romantic

preoccupation with the exotic and

the picturesque.” In Bodmer, he finds

less of this “romantic” tendency than

with others (104). Altogether, American

critics employ so general a notion of

romanticism / Romanticism that it is not

very useful as an analytical instrument.

6 Porter 2002: 34

7 Wied 1862: 6

8 Wied 1825: vii

9 The phrase alludes, of course, to

Words worth’s formula that poetry

“takes its origin from emotion

recollected in tranquillity.”

10 Ruud 2004

11 This is true, at least, of the

published sources.

12 Humboldt 1845

13 Ruud momentarily discusses the importan

ce of this work for Wied in enlightening

ways, but he cannot bring himself to

take Humboldt’s “Byronic waxings”

seriously (Ruud 2004a: 51). Kosmos,

therefore, remains one of many sources

mentioned, of unclear significance.

14 It seems to me, however, that the litera -

ture on Wied/Bodmer overstresses and

in part over-simplifies this context.

15 Humboldt 1845: 49. In the following

discussion of the work I only reference

the page numbers in the text. – The topic

turns up already in the Introduction

(“Vorrede”, pp. 4 – 5) and in the first section

of the text proper (“Delimitation and

scientific discourse on [the project of]

a physical description of the world”),

both times in quite a prominent position.

16 This is a question that cannot have a single,

ahistorical answer, in Humboldt’s view,

but only a historical series of answers;

this follows from the historicity of

knowledge and its forms, as well as of the

resulting pleasure. Humboldt does not

say so explicitly, but it is self-evident in

his contexts. Also, because there emerges

the further question from such reflections

how the different historical answers

should be evaluated, a historical perspective

is inscribed in them from the beginning

and at every point. It, in turn,

ultimately leads to the problem of

progress (see below).

17 DeVoto (1947: 402) comes close to this

observation as early as 1947, but is not

quite able to detach himself from the

tendency to privilege precision over beauty.

18 From what is basically an enlightenment

position, he at one point turns against

common sense in an interesting manner,

labeling it “a system of unverified, in part

completely misunderstood cognitions

derived from experience […:] Taking only

few details into account, such a form of

empiricism is simply pretentious, not least

because it is completely ignorant of the

facts that again shatter it.” He criticizes

this pretentiousness from the position of

“good” knowledge that is founded on

skepticism (17), and distinguishes the

hectic, even sensationalist search for

118

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!