24.12.2012 Views

Raw Reading Times (ms) - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Raw Reading Times (ms) - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Raw Reading Times (ms) - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

GLOW NEWSLETTER GLOW BUREAU<br />

GLOW Newsletter #68, Spr<strong>in</strong>g 2012<br />

Edited by Marc Richards<br />

Addresses:<br />

Marc Richards Utrecht Institute of <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> OTS<br />

Institut für L<strong>in</strong>guistik Utrecht University<br />

Goe<strong>the</strong>-Universität Frankfurt PO Box 85253<br />

Grüneburgplatz 1 3508 AG Utrecht<br />

60629 Frankfurt The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands<br />

Germany Phone + 31 30 253 9163<br />

richards@em.uni-frankfurt.de Fax + 31 30 253 6406<br />

glow@let.uu.nl<br />

http://www.glow-l<strong>in</strong>guistics.org/


GLOW Newsletter & Conference Handbook<br />

CONTENTS<br />

Introduction ...................................................................................................................... 2<br />

Changes to <strong>the</strong> Board ....................................................................................................... 3<br />

GLOW 35, Potsdam: Practical <strong>in</strong>formation ....................................................................... 4<br />

Conference Site ............................................................................................................. 4<br />

Campus Map ................................................................................................................. 5<br />

Registration .................................................................................................................. 5<br />

Registration Fees and Payment .................................................................................... 5<br />

Reimbursement and Waivers ....................................................................................... 6<br />

Travel Information ........................................................................................................ 6<br />

Accommodation ............................................................................................................ 8<br />

Conference D<strong>in</strong>ner and Party ...................................................................................... 10<br />

Day Care...................................................................................................................... 10<br />

Contact Information ................................................................................................... 10<br />

Selection Procedure........................................................................................................ 10<br />

Statistics by Country ....................................................................................................... 11<br />

GLOW 35 Program .......................................................................................................... 12<br />

Colloquium: Context <strong>in</strong> Grammar: A frequent visitor or a regular <strong>in</strong>habitant?,<br />

March 28-30 ............................................................................................................... 12<br />

Workshop 1: The tim<strong>in</strong>g of grammar: experimental and <strong>the</strong>oretical considerations,<br />

March 27 ..................................................................................................................... 15<br />

Workshop 2: Production and perception of prosodically-encoded <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

structure, March 27 .................................................................................................... 17<br />

Workshop 3: Empty categories <strong>in</strong> syntax, March 31 .................................................. 18<br />

Workshop 4: Association with focus, March 31 ......................................................... 19<br />

Abstracts <strong>in</strong> alphabetical order (unnumbered pages) ………………………………………………. 20<br />

1


INTRODUCTION<br />

Welcome to <strong>the</strong> 68 th GLOW Newsletter and Conference Handbook, and to <strong>the</strong> 35 th GLOW<br />

Conference, be<strong>in</strong>g held this year <strong>in</strong> Potsdam from <strong>the</strong> 27th to <strong>the</strong> 31st of March.<br />

As discussed and agreed at last year’s Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Vienna, <strong>the</strong> Spr<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Newsletter has jo<strong>in</strong>ed its Fall sibl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> becom<strong>in</strong>g an electronic-only publication. This is<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> first edition of <strong>the</strong> Spr<strong>in</strong>g newsletter which you will not be receiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ted<br />

booklet form. Content-wise, you will f<strong>in</strong>d that noth<strong>in</strong>g has changed: <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g pages<br />

conta<strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong> usual essential <strong>in</strong>formation for attend<strong>in</strong>g this year’s conference, with practical<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation start<strong>in</strong>g on page 4, details of <strong>the</strong> selection procedure on pp. 10-11, <strong>the</strong> full<br />

progra<strong>ms</strong> for <strong>the</strong> Colloquium (March 28-30) and all four surround<strong>in</strong>g workshops (March 27 and<br />

31) from page 12 onwards, and f<strong>in</strong>ally all <strong>the</strong> abstracts for this year’s talks and poster<br />

presentations. All that’s changed is that, if you want to carry any of this <strong>in</strong>formation around<br />

with you <strong>in</strong> hard copy, you’ll have to pr<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>the</strong> relevant pages yourselves! We hope that<br />

this move to electronic form will enable GLOW to make considerable sav<strong>in</strong>gs on both pr<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and mail<strong>in</strong>g costs, allow<strong>in</strong>g this money to be better spent elsewhere. One immediate benefit is<br />

that <strong>the</strong> newsletter is now less limited by space and length restrictions, so that we have been<br />

able to <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong> this issue <strong>the</strong> abstracts for <strong>the</strong> various poster sessions tak<strong>in</strong>g place dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

Colloquium and workshops, <strong>in</strong> addition to <strong>the</strong> oral presentations.<br />

We appreciate, of course, that some of you may f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> need to pr<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>the</strong><br />

newsletter to be an <strong>in</strong>convenience which detracts from its usefulness as a conference guide.<br />

Any such comments on <strong>the</strong> new format, positive or negative, would be gratefully received, as<br />

would feedback on <strong>the</strong> legibility of <strong>the</strong> newsletter on <strong>the</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds of e-readers that you<br />

might be us<strong>in</strong>g to read it on. You can email your concerns and suggestions to me at<br />

richards@em.uni-frankfurt.de; alternatively, <strong>the</strong>y can be raised at this year’s Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Meet<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> Potsdam on Thursday March 29th (from 17:30: after <strong>the</strong> day’s talks and before <strong>the</strong><br />

conference d<strong>in</strong>ner-party). Indeed, on a more general note, we would encourage as many of<br />

you as possible to attend <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess meet<strong>in</strong>g, as this is your chance to have your say <strong>in</strong> how<br />

GLOW is run, its organization and activities, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g how your membership fees are spent.<br />

Last year’s bus<strong>in</strong>ess meet<strong>in</strong>g was particularly poorly attended, so don’t forget to stay on for a<br />

wee bit after <strong>the</strong> talks on Thursday if you’re <strong>in</strong>terested. Consider it a warm-up for <strong>the</strong> party…<br />

Marc Richards<br />

2


CHANGES TO THE BOARD<br />

The current composition of <strong>the</strong> GLOW Board is given <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> table below.<br />

Congress President Gisbert Fanselow 2011-2012<br />

Chairperson Sjef Barbiers 2011-2013<br />

Secretary Jeroen van Craenenbroeck 2011-2013<br />

Treasurer Maaike Schoorlemmer 2011-2013<br />

Newsletter Editor Marc Richards 2010-2012<br />

Journal Editor Harry van der Hulst<br />

Website Manager Pavel Iosad 2011-2013<br />

Member A Anna Card<strong>in</strong>aletti 2010-2012<br />

Member B Lida Veselovska 2011-2013<br />

Member C Viola Schmitt 2011-2013<br />

Member D Maria-Rosa Lloret 2010-2012<br />

Advisory member 1 Henk van Rie<strong>ms</strong>dijk<br />

Advisory member 2 Mart<strong>in</strong> Everaert<br />

Co-opted member Tobias Scheer 2011-2013<br />

(Phonology)<br />

Every year, several positions come up for renewal. Nom<strong>in</strong>ations are normally sent directly to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Chair, who accepts until January 1st. The GLOW Board wishes to rem<strong>in</strong>d GLOW members<br />

to be th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about who <strong>the</strong>y would like to represent <strong>the</strong>m on <strong>the</strong> board <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> future, and to<br />

nom<strong>in</strong>ate those people <strong>in</strong> good time.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g year, <strong>the</strong> Board has made or received <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g nom<strong>in</strong>ations:<br />

� Halldόr Sigurðsson (Congress President)<br />

� Marc Richards (re-election for Newsletter Editor)<br />

� Roberta D’Alessandro (Member A)<br />

� Maria-Rosa Lloret (re-election for Member D)<br />

3


WELCOME TO GLOW 35, POTSDAM!<br />

The 35th GLOW Colloquium is tak<strong>in</strong>g place <strong>in</strong> Potsdam, Germany, from 28th to 30th<br />

March 2012, hosted by <strong>the</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> Department of <strong>the</strong> University of Potsdam and<br />

<strong>the</strong> Collaborative Research Center SFB 632 "Information Structure". The topic of this<br />

year's Colloquium is Context <strong>in</strong> grammar: a frequent visitor or a regular <strong>in</strong>habitant?. In<br />

addition to <strong>the</strong> Colloquium, <strong>the</strong>re will be four <strong>the</strong>matic workshops tak<strong>in</strong>g place on<br />

Tuesday 27th March and Saturday 31st March: The tim<strong>in</strong>g of grammar: experimental<br />

and <strong>the</strong>oretical considerations (27th March; organized by Harald Clahsen and Claudia<br />

Felser), Production and perception of prosodically-encoded <strong>in</strong>formation structure (27th<br />

March; organized by Frank Kügler and Sab<strong>in</strong>e Zerbian), Empty categories <strong>in</strong> syntax: are<br />

<strong>the</strong>re any? (31st March; organized by Gisbert Fanselow and Gereon Müller), and<br />

Association with focus (31st March; organized by Malte Zimmermann and Mira<br />

Grubic).<br />

PRACTICAL INFORMATION<br />

CONFERENCE SITE<br />

The Colloquium and <strong>the</strong> workshops will take place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Griebnitzsee Campus of <strong>the</strong><br />

University of Potsdam, located right next to <strong>the</strong> Griebnitzsee tra<strong>in</strong> station (Griebnitzsee<br />

Hbf). All <strong>the</strong> talks will take place <strong>in</strong> Haus 6 (‘build<strong>in</strong>g’ 6; please see campus map below).<br />

The Griebnitzsee campus is accessible from both Potsdam and Berl<strong>in</strong>. The<br />

transportation options are listed below. Full schedules for all <strong>the</strong> buses and tra<strong>in</strong>s are<br />

downloadable from <strong>the</strong> conference website (http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.unipotsdam.de/~glow/venue.html).<br />

� Com<strong>in</strong>g from Potsdam:<br />

o Bus 694 towards Drewitz/Stern Center: leaves from Potsdam<br />

Hauptbahnhof every 20 m<strong>in</strong>utes.<br />

o Tra<strong>in</strong> RB22 towards Griebnitzsee: goes through Potsdam Hauptbahnhof<br />

(platform 4) every 30 m<strong>in</strong>utes.<br />

o Tra<strong>in</strong> S7 towards Ahrensfelde: leaves from Potsdam Hauptbahnhof<br />

every 10 m<strong>in</strong>utes.<br />

� Com<strong>in</strong>g from Berl<strong>in</strong>:<br />

o Tra<strong>in</strong> S7 towards Potsdam Hbf: leaves every 10 m<strong>in</strong>utes from several<br />

stations <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Alexanderplatz, Friedrichstraße,<br />

Hauptbahnhof, Zoologischer Garten, and Charlottenburg.<br />

Depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> location of your hotel, you may need to take additional<br />

transportation to reach one of <strong>the</strong> stations above. If so, we recommend you consult<br />

<strong>the</strong> trip planner at http://www.bvg.de.<br />

4


CAMPUS MAP<br />

REGISTRATION<br />

Everybody attend<strong>in</strong>g GLOW 35 (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g presenters) must be a paid-up member of<br />

GLOW. Information on how to jo<strong>in</strong> is available on <strong>the</strong> GLOW homepage<br />

(http://www.glow-l<strong>in</strong>guistics.org/). We will also provide an option to jo<strong>in</strong> at <strong>the</strong> on-site<br />

registration desk dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Colloquium.<br />

Additionally, attendants are also required to register for <strong>the</strong> conference. There will be<br />

an on-site registration desk, but we encourage everybody to register onl<strong>in</strong>e (see<br />

below) to take advantage of a lower registration fee. Early registration will f<strong>in</strong>ish on<br />

Thursday, March 15. Onl<strong>in</strong>e registration can be completed at http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.unipotsdam.de/%7Eglow/register.html#onl<strong>in</strong>e-registration.<br />

REGISTRATION FEES AND PAYMENT<br />

early registration<br />

(until March 15)<br />

5<br />

late registration<br />

(on site)<br />

d<strong>in</strong>ner/party<br />

Faculty €60 €70 €25<br />

Students €40 €50 €25<br />

Colloquium speakers free free €25


Attendants register<strong>in</strong>g before March 15 are strongly encouraged to transfer <strong>the</strong><br />

required amount of money to <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g bank account before <strong>the</strong> start of <strong>the</strong><br />

conference (March 27). Please write GLOW 35 registration: [your name] <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

reference field, so that we can match <strong>the</strong> money to your name.<br />

� Bank: WestLB Düsseldorf<br />

� Account holder: Landeshauptkasse<br />

� Account no.: 7110402844<br />

� IBAN: DE 09 3005 0000 7110 402844<br />

� BIC/SWIFT: WELADEDDXXX<br />

� Bankleitzahl: (for transfers with<strong>in</strong> Germany only) 300 500 00<br />

Late and on-site payments are possible but dispreferred. Attendants register<strong>in</strong>g after<br />

March 15 will be able to pay (cash only) at <strong>the</strong> on-site registration desk.<br />

REIMBURSEMENT AND WAIVERS<br />

The registration fee is waived for Colloquium speakers only; this doesn't <strong>in</strong>clude<br />

workshop speakers or poster presenters.<br />

Colloquium speakers will also be partially reimbursed for travel and accommodation<br />

expenses, to <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g amounts:<br />

reimbursement<br />

Europe, Faculty € 200<br />

Europe, Students € 250<br />

Overseas, Faculty € 350<br />

Overseas, Students € 450<br />

TRAVEL INFORMATION<br />

Gett<strong>in</strong>g to Potsdam<br />

Potsdam is a relatively small town located <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> southwestern part of <strong>the</strong><br />

Berl<strong>in</strong>/Brandenburg Metropolitan Region. Therefore, <strong>the</strong> best option for <strong>the</strong> majority<br />

of attendants will be to travel to Berl<strong>in</strong> and <strong>the</strong>n use local transportation to reach<br />

Potsdam.<br />

Berl<strong>in</strong> is serviced by two airports: Tegel (TXL) for major flag carriers, and Schönefeld<br />

(SFX) for low-fare airl<strong>in</strong>es. The common website for both is www.berl<strong>in</strong>-airport.de. As<br />

an alternative to fly<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> tra<strong>in</strong> station <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> (Berl<strong>in</strong> Hauptbahnhof) has<br />

connections with several major cities <strong>in</strong> both Germany and Central/Eastern Europe.<br />

Once <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong>re are two options for reach<strong>in</strong>g your hotel:<br />

6


� Public transportation: a number of bus, subway and tra<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es connect both<br />

airports and Berl<strong>in</strong> Hauptbahnhof (Berl<strong>in</strong> Hbf) to locations <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> and<br />

Potsdam. If you plan on tak<strong>in</strong>g public transportation to your f<strong>in</strong>al dest<strong>in</strong>ation,<br />

please refer to <strong>the</strong> Public transit sub-section below.<br />

� Taxi: you will f<strong>in</strong>d taxi stops outside both airports and major tra<strong>in</strong> stations. The<br />

official base fare is €3.20, plus €1.65/km for <strong>the</strong> first 7 km, and €1.28/km<br />

<strong>the</strong>reafter.<br />

Public transit <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> and Potsdam<br />

Both Berl<strong>in</strong> and Potsdam have dense public transportation networks. We recommend<br />

you consult <strong>the</strong> route planner at www.bvg.de to plan your trips. Smartphone users can<br />

access this functionality through mobil.bvg.de, or alternatively download <strong>the</strong> free apps<br />

FahrInfo Berl<strong>in</strong> (iPhone) or Öffi (Android).<br />

Berl<strong>in</strong> and Potsdam both have <strong>the</strong>ir own zone-based network (full-size maps available<br />

on <strong>the</strong> conference website), parts of which overlap. Specifically, <strong>the</strong> station next to <strong>the</strong><br />

conference venue (Griebnitzsee) is located <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> Zone C and Potsdam Zone B.<br />

Note that nei<strong>the</strong>r network offers a s<strong>in</strong>gle-zone ticket. Therefore, if you are com<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from Potsdam, you will need an AB ticket; if you are com<strong>in</strong>g from Berl<strong>in</strong>, you will need<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r a BC ticket or an ABC ticket. Current prices for some ticket options are as<br />

follows:<br />

Berl<strong>in</strong><br />

BC ABC<br />

Short trip €1.40<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gle trip €2.70 €3.00<br />

Day ticket €6.60 €6.80<br />

7-day ticket €27.20 €28.00<br />

Potsdam<br />

The short trip (Kurzstrecke) option only allows a trip of up to three tra<strong>in</strong> stations (on<br />

<strong>the</strong> S-Bahn and U-Bahn l<strong>in</strong>es) or up to six bus/tram stops; <strong>the</strong>refore, it is not an option<br />

unless your accommodation is relatively close to <strong>the</strong> conference venue. S<strong>in</strong>gle trip<br />

tickets are valid for 60 m<strong>in</strong>utes (Potsdam) and 2 hours (Berl<strong>in</strong>) after validation, and<br />

with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se time w<strong>in</strong>dows <strong>the</strong>y allow unlimited transfers between <strong>the</strong> bus, tram, and<br />

tra<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>the</strong>ir respective networks. Day tickets and 7-day tickets allow unlimited<br />

travel dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir validity period.<br />

7<br />

AB<br />

Short trip €1.30<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gle trip €1.80<br />

Day ticket €3.90<br />

7-day ticket €11.90


ACCOMMODATION<br />

The Berl<strong>in</strong>/Potsdam area offers ample accommodation options, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g both hotels<br />

and <strong>in</strong>expensive hostels (please see <strong>the</strong> conference website for l<strong>in</strong>ks). Additionally,<br />

reduced conference rates were secured at <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g places, as published on our<br />

website. Note, however, that many of <strong>the</strong> special offers will have already expired by<br />

<strong>the</strong> time of publication of this newsletter.<br />

� Gästehaus Bass<strong>in</strong> (Potsdam)<br />

Brandenburger Straße 37 (corner with Am Bass<strong>in</strong>)<br />

14476 Potsdam.<br />

Tel: +49 331 581 3222<br />

Fax: +49 331 581 3223<br />

<strong>in</strong>fo@hochdrei.org<br />

The guesthouse offers four double roo<strong>ms</strong>, two 3-bed roo<strong>ms</strong>, and one 4-bed<br />

room (no s<strong>in</strong>gle roo<strong>ms</strong>). The price per person/night is significantly lower than<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r accommodation options. To book a bed, please contact <strong>the</strong> guesthouse<br />

management directly.<br />

� Motel One (Berl<strong>in</strong>)<br />

Kantstraße 10<br />

10623 Berl<strong>in</strong><br />

Tel: +49 30 315 1736-0<br />

Fax: +49 30 315 1736-10<br />

berl<strong>in</strong>-kudamm@motel-one.com<br />

We have made a reservation for 50 s<strong>in</strong>gle roo<strong>ms</strong>. The room price person/night<br />

is €59 from March 26 to March 29, and €79 from March 30 to April 1. These<br />

prices do not <strong>in</strong>clude breakfast (€7.50). Although this hotel is located <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong>,<br />

<strong>the</strong> journey time to <strong>the</strong> conference venue is only 25 m<strong>in</strong>utes, us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> S7 tra<strong>in</strong><br />

l<strong>in</strong>e from <strong>the</strong> adjacent Zoologischer Garten station.<br />

To book a room, pr<strong>in</strong>t and fill out <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g form and return it to <strong>the</strong> hotel<br />

by email or fax before February 13, 2012:<br />

http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.uni-potsdam.de/~glow/motel-one-book<strong>in</strong>g.pdf<br />

� Best Western Grand City Parkhotel (Potsdam)<br />

Fortstraße 80<br />

14471 Potsdam<br />

Tel: +49 331 98120<br />

Fax: +49 331 9812100<br />

<strong>in</strong>fo@parkhotel-potsdam.bestwestern.de<br />

We have made a reservation for 40 s<strong>in</strong>gle roo<strong>ms</strong>. The room price per<br />

8


person/night is €78, breakfast <strong>in</strong>cluded. This hotel is located <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vic<strong>in</strong>ity of<br />

Schloss Sanssouci <strong>in</strong> Potsdam, and <strong>the</strong> journey time to <strong>the</strong> conference site is<br />

about 25-30 m<strong>in</strong>utes us<strong>in</strong>g public transportation.<br />

To book a room, contact <strong>the</strong> hotel directly and cite "GLOW". Reservations have<br />

to be made before February 20, 2012.<br />

� Steigenberger Hotel Sanssouci (Potsdam)<br />

Allee nach Sanssouci 1<br />

14471 Potsdam<br />

Tel: +49 331 9091-0<br />

Fax: +49 331 9091-903/909<br />

potsdam@steigenberger.de<br />

The special GLOW rates are €85 p.p.p.n. (s<strong>in</strong>gle room) and €115 p.p.p.n.<br />

(double room), both options <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g buffet breakfast. To make a reservation,<br />

fill <strong>in</strong> a registration form (<strong>in</strong> German or English) and send it to <strong>the</strong> hotel no later<br />

than February 17.<br />

English form: http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.unipotsdam.de/%7Eglow/images/steigenberger-en.pdf<br />

German form: http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.unipotsdam.de/%7Eglow/images/steigenberger-de.pdf<br />

� Filmhotel "Lili Marleen" (Potsdam)<br />

Großbeerenstraße 75 (corner with Walter-Klausch-Str.)<br />

14482 Potsdam-Babelsberg<br />

Tel: +49 331 743 200<br />

Fax: +49 331 743 2018<br />

filmhotel@potsdam.de<br />

We have reserved 30 s<strong>in</strong>gle roo<strong>ms</strong> at a €45 p.p.p.n. rate. To make your<br />

reservation, contact <strong>the</strong> hotel management directly before February 13.<br />

� Altstadt Hotel (Potsdam)<br />

Dortustraße 9-10<br />

14467 Potsdam<br />

Tel: +49 331 284 990<br />

Fax: +49 331 284 9903<br />

altstadthotel@tnp-onl<strong>in</strong>e.de<br />

We have reserved 20 s<strong>in</strong>gle roo<strong>ms</strong> at a rate of €58 p.p.p.n. To make a<br />

reservation, contact <strong>the</strong> hotel management directly before February 15.<br />

9


CONFERENCE DINNER AND PARTY<br />

This year’s conference d<strong>in</strong>ner and party will take place after <strong>the</strong> talks on Thursday 29th<br />

March at <strong>the</strong> club Die Fabrik, located at Schiffbauergasse 10, Potsdam. The price,<br />

which <strong>in</strong>cludes a buffet-style d<strong>in</strong>ner, is €25. If you plan to attend, please <strong>in</strong>dicate this <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> onl<strong>in</strong>e registration form on <strong>the</strong> conference website.<br />

The club can be reached by tak<strong>in</strong>g Tram 99 (for a timetable, please see <strong>the</strong> conference<br />

website) from Potsdam Hauptbahnhof and gett<strong>in</strong>g off at Schiffbauergasse/Uferweg.<br />

DAY CARE<br />

In collaboration with <strong>the</strong> Studentenwerk of <strong>the</strong> University of Potsdam, we will offer a<br />

day-care center from Tuesday to Saturday for <strong>the</strong> children of conference participants.<br />

Children must be registered for day care before March 5. Please contact<br />

boethke@googlemail.com and <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong> age and language (English/German) of <strong>the</strong><br />

children you wish to register.<br />

CONTACT INFORMATION<br />

For fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>formation, please consult <strong>the</strong> GLOW 35 Potsdam website<br />

(http://www.l<strong>in</strong>g.uni-potsdam.de/~glow/), or contact <strong>the</strong> local organizers at:<br />

GLOW 35<br />

Department L<strong>in</strong>guistik<br />

Universität Potsdam<br />

Karl Liebknechtstraße 24-25<br />

14476 Golm<br />

Germany<br />

glow.35.potsdam@gmail.com<br />

SELECTION PROCEDURE<br />

A total of 102 abstracts were submitted for <strong>the</strong> Ma<strong>in</strong> Colloquium (not count<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

workshops). From <strong>the</strong>se, 19 were selected for oral presentation, with two alternates<br />

(one of <strong>the</strong> alternates was upgraded to oral presentation before <strong>the</strong> publication of <strong>the</strong><br />

program). The acceptance rate for oral presentations and alternates is thus 20.6%.<br />

However, given that this year’s Colloquium also features two poster sessions, <strong>the</strong><br />

overall acceptance rate is substantially higher than for previous GLOWs (34.3%).<br />

Each of <strong>the</strong> 102 abstracts was sent to three external reviewers (who did not <strong>in</strong>clude<br />

local organizers or GLOW Board members), and <strong>the</strong> reviews were returned before <strong>the</strong><br />

10


w<strong>in</strong>ter holidays. The 102 abstracts were ranked by <strong>the</strong> mean of <strong>the</strong> grades given by <strong>the</strong><br />

reviewers. A selection committee of three representatives of <strong>the</strong> GLOW Board and<br />

three representatives of <strong>the</strong> local organizers considered and discussed <strong>in</strong> detail (a) <strong>the</strong><br />

best fifty abstracts, (b) those abstracts for which <strong>the</strong> grades given by <strong>the</strong> reviewers<br />

diverged substantially and, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, (c) any abstract a selection committee<br />

member wanted to be discussed. The abstracts were discussed one by one. On <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of <strong>the</strong> reviewers’ comments and <strong>the</strong> assessments by <strong>the</strong> six committee members,<br />

19 abstracts were identified for presentation at <strong>the</strong> Colloquium, and 19 abstracts were<br />

selected for poster presentations. Of <strong>the</strong> latter, two were selected as alternate<br />

presentations for <strong>the</strong> Colloquium.<br />

STATISTICS BY COUNTRY<br />

country authors submitted accepted acceptance Committee<br />

rate members<br />

Belgium 4 2.50 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Canada 11 9.00 1.00 0.11 –<br />

France 4 3.00 0.00 0.00 1<br />

Germany 27 16.50 4.00 0.24 4<br />

Greece 1 0.50 0.50 1.00 –<br />

Israel 1 0.33 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Italy 6 3.50 1.00 0.29 –<br />

Japan 2 1.33 0.33 0.25 –<br />

Korea, Republic 1 1.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

of<br />

Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands 12 8.50 2.00 0.24 1<br />

Norway 5 4.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Poland 2 2.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Romania 1 1.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Russian 3 2.50 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Federation<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gapore 1 1.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Spa<strong>in</strong> 4 2.50 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Sweden 1 1.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

Switzerland 1 1.00 0.00 0.00 –<br />

United K<strong>in</strong>gdom 5 5.00 1.00 0.20 –<br />

United States 47 35.83 9.17 0.26 –<br />

totals 139 102 19 – 6<br />

11


GLOW 35 COLLOQUIUM PROGRAM: MARCH 28-30, CAMPUS GRIEBNITZSEE, HAUS 6<br />

Wednesday, March 28<br />

08:00–09:00 Registration<br />

09:00–09:15 Welcome and announcements<br />

09:15–10:15 Uli Sauerland (ZAS) & Jonathan Bobaljik (UConn)<br />

Syncretism distribution model<strong>in</strong>g and person paradig<strong>ms</strong>.<br />

10:15–11:15 Ia<strong>in</strong> Gibl<strong>in</strong> (MIT)<br />

Long distance anaphora <strong>in</strong> Mandar<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> PCC, and Cyclic Agree.<br />

11:15–11:30 Coffee break<br />

11:30–12:30 Poster session<br />

Mohamed Lahrouchi (CNRS/Paris 8): Phasal spell out and <strong>the</strong> glide: high<br />

vowel alternation <strong>in</strong> Berber.<br />

Peter Svenonius (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø/CASTL): North Sámi pronouns.<br />

Jacopo Torregrossa (Verona): Encod<strong>in</strong>g contrast at PF.<br />

Bethany Lochbihler (McGill): F<strong>in</strong>al and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phase status.<br />

Krist<strong>in</strong>e Bentzen (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø/CASTL) & Merete Anderssen (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø):<br />

Discourse effects on <strong>the</strong> availability of Object Shift.<br />

Laura Kal<strong>in</strong> (UCLA) & Coppe van Urk (MIT): A novel aspect split <strong>in</strong><br />

Senaya.<br />

Ad Neeleman & Hans van de Koot (UCL): The l<strong>in</strong>guistic expression of<br />

causation.<br />

Ezra Keshet (Michigan): Scopal effects of embedded coherence<br />

relations.<br />

12:30–13:30 Lunch break<br />

13:30–14:30 Antje Lahne (Konstanz)<br />

Locality <strong>in</strong> agreement: a new approach.<br />

14:30–15:30 Yanyan Sui (NYU)<br />

Metrical structure prom<strong>in</strong>ence vs. perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> Standard<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese.<br />

15:30–15:45 Coffee break<br />

15:45–16:45 Ewan Dunbar (Maryland), Brian Dillon (UMass Amherst) & William<br />

Idsardi (Maryland)<br />

Learn<strong>in</strong>g phonetic categories by learn<strong>in</strong>g allophony and vice versa.<br />

15:00–15:30 Roberta D’Alessandro & Marc van Oostendorp (Leiden)<br />

Cyclic syntax mirrors cyclic morphology: Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italian vocatives <strong>in</strong><br />

context.<br />

12


Thursday, March 29<br />

09:00–10:00 Anke Assmann, Doreen Georgi, Fabian Heck, Gereon Müller & Philipp<br />

Weisser (Leipzig)<br />

Ergatives move too early.<br />

10:00–11:00 Ivona Kučerová (McMaster)<br />

Case <strong>in</strong>dependence and split ergativity: towards a unified account of<br />

Case assignment.<br />

11:00–11:15 Coffee break<br />

11:15–12:15 Poster session<br />

Marta Abrusan (Gött<strong>in</strong>gen) & Kriszta Szendrői (UCL): Experiment<strong>in</strong>g<br />

with <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g of France: topics, verifiability, and def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions.<br />

Timothy Leffel (NYU): Non-restrictive adjectives and <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of scalar<br />

implicature.<br />

Michael Freedman (Yale): Contextual disambiguation of havesentences.<br />

Stavroula Alexandropoulou & Bert le Bruyn (Utrecht): Inalienable<br />

possession: a semantic/pragmatic take.<br />

Francesca Foppolo (Milano-Bicocca), Marco Marelli (Milano-Bicocca),<br />

Luisa Meroni (Utrecht) & Andrea Gualm<strong>in</strong>i (Utrecht): Pars<strong>in</strong>g semantic<br />

ambiguity: strategies and commitments.<br />

Lucas Champollion (Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen): Temporal dependencies: anaphora vs.<br />

movement.<br />

Rebekah Bagl<strong>in</strong>i (Chicago): Reduced clausal structure <strong>in</strong> comparatives:<br />

evidence from Wolof.<br />

12:15–13:15 Lunch break<br />

13:15–14:15 Claire Halpert (MIT)<br />

Structural Case and <strong>the</strong> nature of vP <strong>in</strong> Zulu.<br />

14:15–15:15 Masaya Yoshida (Northwestern), Chizuru Nakao (Daito Bunka) & Iván<br />

Ortega-Santos (Memphis)<br />

On ellipsis structures <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a wh-remnant and a non-wh-remnant<br />

simultaneously.<br />

15:15–15:30 Coffee break<br />

15:30–16:30 Andreas Blümel (Frankfurt)<br />

Successive-cyclic movement as <strong>in</strong>termediate labell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acies.<br />

16:30–17:30 Hadas Kotek (MIT)<br />

Wh-front<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a two-probe system.<br />

17:30–18:30 Bus<strong>in</strong>ess meet<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from 19:00 D<strong>in</strong>ner and party at “Die Fabrik”<br />

13


Friday, March 30<br />

09:00–10:00 Stephen Wechsler (Texas)<br />

Conjunct morphology marks property self-ascription.<br />

10:00–11:00 Artemis Alexiadou (Stuttgart) & Elena Anagnostopoulou (Crete)<br />

Verb mean<strong>in</strong>g, local context, and <strong>the</strong> syntax of roots <strong>in</strong> alternations.<br />

11:00–11:15 Coffee break<br />

11:15–12:15 Kriszta Szendrői (UCL)<br />

Block<strong>in</strong>g quantifier rais<strong>in</strong>g by passives.<br />

12:15–13:15 Lunch break<br />

13:15–14:15 Valent<strong>in</strong>a Bianchi (Siena) & Mara Frascarelli (Roma III)<br />

On how to be rooted <strong>in</strong> a context.<br />

14:15–15:15 Bronwyn M. Bjorkman (Northwestern) & Claire Halpert (MIT)<br />

In search of (im)perfection: <strong>the</strong> illusion of counterfactual aspect.<br />

15:15–15:45 Coffee break<br />

15:45–16:45 Luisa Meroni & Andrea Gualm<strong>in</strong>i (Utrecht)<br />

Do you know all SI? I know some. Context-dependence of children’s<br />

computation of SIs.<br />

16:45–17:45 Kai von F<strong>in</strong>tel (MIT), Danny Fox (Hebrew U./MIT) & Sab<strong>in</strong>e Iatridou<br />

(MIT)<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>iteness as maximal <strong>in</strong>formativeness.<br />

17:45–18:00 Thanks and goodbye<br />

14


GLOW 33 WORKSHOP PROGRAMS I<br />

Workshop 1:<br />

The tim<strong>in</strong>g of grammar: experimental and <strong>the</strong>oretical considerations<br />

Tuesday 27th March<br />

Campus Griebnitzsee, Haus 6<br />

08:50–09:00 Welcome and announcements<br />

09:00–10:00 Invited speaker: Patrick Sturt (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh)<br />

The tim<strong>in</strong>g of dependency formation: state of <strong>the</strong> art and future<br />

challenges.<br />

10:00–10:30 Coffee break<br />

10:30–11:00 Arnout Koornneef & Eric Reuland (Utrecht)<br />

Grammar and process<strong>in</strong>g economy.<br />

11:00–11:30 Dave Kush (Maryland)<br />

On-l<strong>in</strong>e use of relational structural <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g anaphora:<br />

evidence from English and H<strong>in</strong>di.<br />

11:30–12:00 Kaili Clackson (Essex), Vera Heyer (Potsdam) & Harald Clahsen<br />

(Potsdam)<br />

Onl<strong>in</strong>e application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples A and B: evidence from eye<br />

movements dur<strong>in</strong>g listen<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

12:00–13:00 Lunch break<br />

14:00–15:00 Poster session<br />

Sofiana Chiriacescu (Stuttgart): Focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases <strong>in</strong><br />

German and English: consequences of reference form on subsequent<br />

discourse.<br />

Charles L<strong>in</strong> (Indiana): Typological perspectives on relative clause<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g: <strong>the</strong>matic mapp<strong>in</strong>g, case markedness, filler-gap <strong>in</strong>tegrations,<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ir relative tim<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Sophia Manika, Sergey Avrut<strong>in</strong> & Eric Reuland (Utrecht): The bits of<br />

dependencies.<br />

Bart Hollebrandse, Petra Hendriks & Jacolien van Rij (Gron<strong>in</strong>gen): Eye<br />

gaze patterns reveal subtle discourse effects on object pronoun<br />

resolution.<br />

Laura Kertz (Brown): Referential process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>the</strong> resolution of<br />

verbal anaphors.<br />

Megan Sutton, Michael Fetters & Jeffrey Lidz (Maryland): Pars<strong>in</strong>g for<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C at 30 months.<br />

15


Jana Häussler (Potsdam) & Markus Bader (Frankfurt): When Maria is<br />

considered to be he. Gender mismatch effects dur<strong>in</strong>g pronoun<br />

resolution.<br />

14:00–14:30 Umesh Patil (Potsdam), Shravan Vasishth (Potsdam) & Richard Lewis<br />

(Michigan)<br />

Early effect of retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference on reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

14:30–15:00 Ian Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs & Patrick Sturt (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh)<br />

The time-course of reference resolution <strong>in</strong> picture noun phrases:<br />

evidence from eye movements dur<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

15:00–15:30 Clare Patterson & Claudia Felser (Potsdam)<br />

Syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of pronouns.<br />

15:30–16:00 Coffee break<br />

16:00–16:30 Shevaun Lewis & W<strong>in</strong>g Yee Chow (Maryland)<br />

Structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on pronoun resolution: dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g early and<br />

late sensitivity to illicit antecedents.<br />

16:30–17:00 Daniel Parker & Sol Lago (Maryland)<br />

Retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> resolution of anaphoric PRO.<br />

17:00–17:30 Leticia Pablos, Bobby Ruijgrok, Jenny Doetjes & Lisa Cheng (Leiden)<br />

Process<strong>in</strong>g cataphoric pronouns <strong>in</strong> Dutch: an ERP study.<br />

17:30–18:00 Tea break<br />

18:00–18:30 Mat<strong>the</strong>w Wagers (UC Santa Cruz), Manuel Borja (Inetnon Amot yan<br />

Kutturan Natibu) & Sandra Chung (UC Santa Cruz)<br />

Wh-agreement and <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g of unbounded dependency formation: a<br />

Chamorro perspective on <strong>in</strong>crementality and accuracy <strong>in</strong> language<br />

comprehension.<br />

18:30–19:00 Bruno Nicemboim (Potsdam)<br />

Process<strong>in</strong>g Complex NP Islands <strong>in</strong> Hebrew.<br />

19:00 End of workshop<br />

16


GLOW 33 WORKSHOP PROGRAMS II<br />

Workshop 2:<br />

Production and perception of prosodically-encoded Information<br />

Structure<br />

Tuesday 27th March<br />

Campus Griebnitzsee, Haus 6<br />

09:00–09:15 Welcome and announcements<br />

09:15–10:00 Stefan Baumann (Köln)<br />

Types of secondary prom<strong>in</strong>ence and <strong>the</strong>ir relation to Information<br />

Structure.<br />

10:00–10:30 Coffee break<br />

10:30–11:15 Jason Bishop (UCLA)<br />

Information structure, prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence, and <strong>in</strong>dividual differences:<br />

evidence from onl<strong>in</strong>e process<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

11:15–12:00 Peng Zhou, Stephen Cra<strong>in</strong> & Likan Zhan (Macquarie)<br />

Children’s pragmatic use of prosody <strong>in</strong> sentence process<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

12:00–13:00 Lunch break<br />

13:00–14:00 Poster session<br />

14:00–14:45 Alexandre Delf<strong>in</strong>o, Maria Luiza Cunha Lima & Pablo Arantes<br />

(Universidade Federal de M<strong>in</strong>as Gerais)<br />

Prosodic mark<strong>in</strong>g of referential status <strong>in</strong> Brazilian Portuguese.<br />

14:45–15:30 Tania Leal Méndez & Christ<strong>in</strong>e Shea (Iowa)<br />

L1 and L2 Mexican Spanish and Information Structure: P-movement or<br />

<strong>in</strong>-situ prosody?<br />

15:30–16:00 Coffee break<br />

16:00–16:45 Summary and discussion<br />

17


GLOW 33 WORKSHOP PROGRAMS III<br />

Workshop 3: Empty categories <strong>in</strong> syntax<br />

Saturday 31st March<br />

Campus Griebnitzsee, Haus 6<br />

08:50–09:00 Welcome and announcements<br />

09:00–10:00 Invited speaker: Ivan Sag (Stanford)<br />

t.b.a.<br />

10:00–11:00 Tim Hunter & Robert Frank (Yale)<br />

Elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g rightward movement: extraposition as flexible l<strong>in</strong>earization<br />

of adjuncts.<br />

11:00–11:15 Coffee break<br />

11:15–12:15 Anke Assmann & Fabian Heck (Leipzig)<br />

Opaque <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> German scrambl<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

12:15–13:45 Lunch break<br />

13:45–14:45 Invited speaker: Ad Neeleman (UCL)<br />

“e”<br />

14:45–15:45 Rita Manz<strong>in</strong>i (Firenze) & Anna Roussou (Patras)<br />

Empty categories: empty operators and variables at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

15:45–16:00 Coffee break<br />

16:00–17:00 Terje Lohndal (Maryland) & Bridget Samuels (CalTech)<br />

On how null elements and unpronounced copies are different.<br />

17:00–18:00 Hsu-Te Cheng (UConn)<br />

Ellipsis: its correlates with phase and movement.<br />

18:00–19:00 Artemis Alexiadou & Florian Schäfer (Stuttgart)<br />

Naturally reflexive verbs revisited.<br />

19:00 End of workshop<br />

Alternates:<br />

Chris Laterza (Maryland): Gaps with silence.<br />

Coppe van Urk (MIT): On <strong>the</strong> nature of control.<br />

18


GLOW 33 WORKSHOP PROGRAMS IV<br />

Workshop 4: Association with focus<br />

Saturday 31st March<br />

Campus Griebnitzsee, Haus 6<br />

09:00–09:15 Welcome and open<strong>in</strong>g remarks<br />

09:15–10:15 Keynote speaker: David Beaver (U. Texas, Aust<strong>in</strong>)<br />

t.b.a.<br />

10:15–11:00 Elizabeth Coppock (Lund) & David Beaver (U. Texas, Aust<strong>in</strong>)<br />

NPI licens<strong>in</strong>g by exceptives: just scope could expla<strong>in</strong> it.<br />

11:00–11:15 Coffee break<br />

11:15–12:00 Michael Yoshitaka Erlew<strong>in</strong>e (MIT)<br />

Association with traces and <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory of movement.<br />

12:00–13:30 Lunch break<br />

13:30–14:15 Satoshi Tomioka (Delaware)<br />

Focus matters <strong>in</strong> Neo-Hambl<strong>in</strong> semantics.<br />

14:15–15:00 Daniel Gutzmann (Frankfurt) & Kathar<strong>in</strong>a Hartmann (Humboldt)<br />

Dissociat<strong>in</strong>g verum from focus.<br />

15:00–15:45 Noah Constant (UMass Amherst)<br />

Topic abstraction as <strong>the</strong> source for nested alternatives: a conservative<br />

semantics for contrastive topic.<br />

15:45–16:00 Coffee break<br />

16:00–16:45 Luka Crnic (Hebrew University)<br />

Scalar particles and competition.<br />

16:45–17:30 Yael Greenberg & Keren Khrizman (Bar Ilan)<br />

Bixlal: a general streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g operator <strong>in</strong> Hebrew.<br />

17:30–18:15 Barbara Tomaszewicz (USC)<br />

A family of exclusives <strong>in</strong> Polish.<br />

18:15–19:00 Clos<strong>in</strong>g remarks<br />

19:00 End of workshop<br />

19


Marta Abrusan (Gött<strong>in</strong>gen) & Kriszta Szendrői (UCL)<br />

Experiment<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g of France: topics, verifiability and def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions<br />

1. Theoretical situation The Fregean position is widely accepted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> semantics literature:<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions trigger an existential presupposition (Heim & Kratzer 1998). However, this<br />

existential presupposition see<strong>ms</strong> not to appear equally strongly <strong>in</strong> every sentence (Strawson 1969,<br />

Re<strong>in</strong>hart 1981, von F<strong>in</strong>tel 2004, etc.). E.g. accord<strong>in</strong>g to Strawson, <strong>in</strong> a context where it is known<br />

that France has no k<strong>in</strong>g, (1a) is felt as “nei<strong>the</strong>r false nor true”, but (1b) is judged as simply false.<br />

(1) a. The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is bald. b. The exhibition was visited yesterday by <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France.<br />

The solution of Strawson (1969) (also Re<strong>in</strong>hart 1981) was that def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions trigger an<br />

existential presupposition only <strong>in</strong> topic position. The NP ‘<strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France’ is <strong>in</strong> topic position<br />

<strong>in</strong> (1a) but not <strong>in</strong> (1b). Thus (1a) but not (1b) leads to a presupposition failure. Lasersohn (1993)<br />

and von F<strong>in</strong>tel (2004) dismissed <strong>the</strong> importance of topichood and argued that ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

topicality, verifiability is important: If a sentence conta<strong>in</strong>s an <strong>in</strong>dependent NP such that <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence could be verified based on <strong>the</strong> properties of this NP, speakers might have enough<br />

grounds to accept or reject <strong>the</strong> sentence whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> presupposition of <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

description is satisfied. This happens <strong>in</strong> The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is sitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this chair, where <strong>the</strong> sentence<br />

could be verified based on <strong>the</strong> properties of <strong>the</strong> chair. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, as von F<strong>in</strong>tel (2004) has shown, <strong>in</strong><br />

some cases even def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions that are uncontroversially topics do not seem to trigger <strong>the</strong><br />

“squeamishness” associated with presupposition failure: Let me tell you about my friend, <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

France. I had breakfast with him this morn<strong>in</strong>g. Thus accord<strong>in</strong>g to both Lasersohn and von F<strong>in</strong>tel,<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions always trigger an existential presupposition, hence all <strong>the</strong> above examples<br />

<strong>in</strong>volve a presupposition failure. But if <strong>the</strong> speaker has <strong>in</strong>dependent footholds for verification, he<br />

might judge <strong>the</strong> sentence as false.<br />

2. Summary of <strong>the</strong> experiment and results All <strong>the</strong> data <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> above papers are based on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitions of <strong>the</strong> authors. We designed an experiment to verify <strong>the</strong> alleged differences between <strong>the</strong><br />

various (local) l<strong>in</strong>guistic contexts and to test <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories. We found that <strong>the</strong><br />

situation is more complex than appears from any of <strong>the</strong> above papers. Both topicality and<br />

verifiability is a factor <strong>in</strong> its own right. We also discuss how to reconcile <strong>the</strong>se seem<strong>in</strong>gly divergent<br />

factors. We dist<strong>in</strong>guish two concepts: topic, what <strong>the</strong> sentence is pragmatically about, and what we<br />

call pivot, which is <strong>the</strong> constituent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence based on which <strong>the</strong> sentence is verified. We<br />

propose, follow<strong>in</strong>g Lasersohn (1993) and von F<strong>in</strong>tel (2004), that verifiability is <strong>the</strong> primary factor<br />

that <strong>in</strong>for<strong>ms</strong> pragmatic truth value <strong>in</strong>tuitions: <strong>in</strong> particular we suggest that sentences are verified<br />

based on <strong>the</strong>ir pivots. The topic-effect noticed by Strawson and Re<strong>in</strong>hart comes about because<br />

topics are default pivots. Overall, our data suggests <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g picture: We should comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

pragmatic <strong>in</strong>sights of <strong>the</strong> various Strawsonian <strong>the</strong>ories with a bivalent, but presuppositional<br />

approach to def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions, such as that of Stalnaker (1974, 1978).<br />

3. The experimental setup We tested 33 native speakers of English (mostly British English),<br />

aged 22-55. The participants first read <strong>in</strong>structions on <strong>the</strong> computer screen, reproduced <strong>in</strong> (2).<br />

(2) In this experiment, statements will appear on your screen. If you th<strong>in</strong>k a statement is true, you should click on<br />

<strong>the</strong> 'TRUE' button. If you th<strong>in</strong>k a statement is false, you should click on <strong>the</strong> 'FALSE' button. Sometimes,<br />

it may happen that you cannot decide. In those cases, you should click on <strong>the</strong> 'CAN'T SAY' button. Please<br />

do not dwell on your decision for too long. There is no right or wrong answer!<br />

After a short practice session, <strong>the</strong>y were left alone with a program which presented <strong>the</strong> ite<strong>ms</strong><br />

described below one by one <strong>in</strong> pseudo-random order, 253 <strong>in</strong> total. An example of an item:<br />

The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is bald.<br />

FALSE CAN’T SAY TRUE<br />

1


The test ite<strong>ms</strong> were created by plac<strong>in</strong>g 8 def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions that lack referents (listed <strong>in</strong> (3)) <strong>in</strong> 11<br />

sentential contexts, called test conditions, illustrated with ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France <strong>in</strong> (4).<br />

(3) <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France; <strong>the</strong> emperor of Canada; <strong>the</strong> Pope’s wife; Pr<strong>in</strong>cess Diana’s daughter; <strong>the</strong> beaches of<br />

Birm<strong>in</strong>gham; <strong>the</strong> Belgian ra<strong>in</strong>forest; <strong>the</strong> coral reefs of Brighton; <strong>the</strong> volcanoes of Kent.<br />

(4) C(ondition) 0 [ref. failure NP, no extra NP] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is bald.<br />

C1 [no presupposition] France has a k<strong>in</strong>g and he is bald.<br />

C2 [von F<strong>in</strong>tel, <strong>in</strong>dep. unknown NP] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is on a state visit to Australia this week.<br />

C3 [Lasersohn, <strong>in</strong>dep. known NP] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is married to Carla Bruni.<br />

C4 [ref. failure NP <strong>in</strong> topic] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France, he was <strong>in</strong>vited to have d<strong>in</strong>ner with Sarkozy.<br />

C5 [ref. failure NP not <strong>in</strong> topic] Sarkozy, he was <strong>in</strong>vited to have d<strong>in</strong>ner with <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France.<br />

C6 [negation of 0] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France isn't bald.<br />

C7 [negation of 2] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is not on a state visit to Australia this week.<br />

C8 [negation of 3] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is not married to Carla Bruni.<br />

C9 [negation of 4] The k<strong>in</strong>g of France, he wasn’t <strong>in</strong>vited to have d<strong>in</strong>ner with Sarkozy.<br />

C10 [negation of 5] Sarkozy, he wasn’t <strong>in</strong>vited to have d<strong>in</strong>ner with <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France.<br />

C(ondition) 1 was <strong>in</strong>cluded to test that <strong>the</strong> participants did know that our tested def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

descriptions were referentially challenged. The difference between C2 and C3 (and similarly<br />

between C7 and C8) was that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter <strong>the</strong> participants were expected to have knowledge about<br />

<strong>the</strong> relevant properties of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent NP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence (Carla Bruni, <strong>in</strong> C3 and C8 <strong>in</strong> (7)—<br />

this we call Lasersohn-effect), but <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> former <strong>the</strong>y were expected not to have such knowledge<br />

(Australia, <strong>in</strong> C2 and C7 <strong>in</strong> (7)—this we call <strong>the</strong> von F<strong>in</strong>tel-effect). The item list also conta<strong>in</strong>ed 165<br />

filler sentences, 8 of which were controls for <strong>the</strong> ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> C3 and C8, i.e. <strong>the</strong> conditions that tested<br />

for <strong>the</strong> Lasersohn-effect. E.g., for C8 <strong>in</strong> (7), <strong>the</strong> control item was Carla Bruni is married to Sarkozy.<br />

4. Results We compared <strong>the</strong> proportion (%) at which subjects replied ‘False’ to <strong>the</strong> test ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

Conditions 0-5 with ANOVA, and also compared <strong>the</strong> proportion (%) at which subjects replied<br />

‘True’ to <strong>the</strong> test ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> Conditions 6-10. We found only weak or nearly significant differences<br />

between any of <strong>the</strong> conditions 0-5, i.e. <strong>the</strong> positive conditions; our subjects said ‘False’ to most of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se most of <strong>the</strong> time. However, we found clear significant differences among <strong>the</strong> negative<br />

conditions: As Figure 1 shows, we found that speakers responded ‘True’ at a significantly higher<br />

proportion to <strong>the</strong> ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> C7, C8, C9 and C10 than to <strong>the</strong> ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> C6 (p


Stavroula Alexandropoulou & Bert le Bruyn (Utrecht)<br />

Inalienable possession: a semantic take<br />

In most analyses of <strong>in</strong>alienable possession <strong>in</strong> French (see 1) it is standard to assume that <strong>the</strong><br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite article is simply not <strong>the</strong>re (e.g. Vergnaud & Zubizarreta 1992) or that it is some k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

pronoun (e.g. Guéron 1985). We ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that expletive analyses should be a last resort option<br />

and that pronom<strong>in</strong>al analyses only make sense if we can show that <strong>the</strong>re is some k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

agreement between <strong>the</strong> anaphor and its antecedent. Given that this last condition is not met (see<br />

1) we propose an alternative semantic analysis under <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article is<br />

what it looks like: a def<strong>in</strong>ite article.<br />

(1) Je 1st person, masc/fem lève la fem ma<strong>in</strong>. (2) ??Jean lève sa ma<strong>in</strong>.<br />

I raise <strong>the</strong> hand Jean raises his hand<br />

‘I raise my hand’<br />

From a semantic viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, we face two challenges: (i) How come we can use a def<strong>in</strong>ite article <strong>in</strong><br />

this construction (despite <strong>the</strong> non-uniqueness of hands)?; (ii) Why don’t we use a possessive<br />

pronoun ra<strong>the</strong>r than a def<strong>in</strong>ite article (see 2) ? Given that <strong>the</strong> first challenge has been treated for<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r relational uses of <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article (see e.g. Barker <strong>in</strong> press) we focus on (ii). We propose an<br />

analysis with a m<strong>in</strong>imum of stipulations that derives <strong>the</strong> facts for French as well as for English.<br />

The key to understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>alienable possession is that <strong>the</strong> possessum <strong>in</strong> this construction<br />

presupposes possession: a hand e.g. is always someone’s hand. This has two important<br />

consequences that lead to partially conflict<strong>in</strong>g requirements on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>alienable possession<br />

construction. We will exploit <strong>the</strong>se as constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> an OT account. The first consequence is that<br />

an <strong>in</strong>alienable possessum is def<strong>in</strong>ed only if we know who <strong>the</strong> possessor is. We <strong>the</strong>n expect<br />

speakers to make sure that <strong>the</strong>re is no doubt about who <strong>the</strong> possessor is. The most<br />

straightforward way to do so is to use a possessive pronoun. This leads a speaker to prefer (2)<br />

over (1). The second consequence is that <strong>the</strong> overt mark<strong>in</strong>g of possession is superfluous: given<br />

that possession is presupposed, it is uneconomic to mark it explicitly with a possessive pronoun<br />

that – due to <strong>the</strong> fact that it imposes a b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g relation – is syntactically more complex than a<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite article. We consequently expect speakers to avoid us<strong>in</strong>g overt possessive pronouns and<br />

to prefer (1) over (2).<br />

In (3) we re<strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> two consequences we have <strong>in</strong>troduced as an OT faithfulness and an OT<br />

markedness constra<strong>in</strong>t.<br />

(3) FaithPoss(essor):Make sure an <strong>in</strong>alienable possessum has a determ<strong>in</strong>ed possessor.<br />

D(on’t)U(se)P(ossessive)P(ronouns): Don’t use possessive pronouns with <strong>in</strong>alienable<br />

possessum nouns<br />

The <strong>in</strong>terpretation of DUPP is unproblematic but FaithPoss does need fur<strong>the</strong>r explanation. We<br />

def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> notion of determ<strong>in</strong>ed possessor <strong>in</strong> DRT:<br />

(4) A possession relation have(x,y) conta<strong>in</strong>s a determ<strong>in</strong>ed possessor y iff for every f that<br />

embeds <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put DRS K, it holds that for every f’, f’’ that extend f, f’(y)=f’’(y) and<br />

have(f’(x),f’(y))=have(f’’(x),f’’(y)) (cf. Farkas 2002 on determ<strong>in</strong>ed reference).<br />

Above, we <strong>in</strong>dicated one way of satisfy<strong>in</strong>g FaithPoss, viz. to use possessive pronouns. Here, we<br />

discuss <strong>the</strong> two o<strong>the</strong>r ways we know of. Note that nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>volves explicit mark<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

possession. We <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> first on <strong>the</strong> basis of (5) and make <strong>the</strong> assumptions <strong>in</strong> (6):<br />

(5) Marie a frappé Jean sur la ma<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Marie has hit Jean on <strong>the</strong> hand<br />

(6) a. sur <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with frapper refers ei<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> location or specifies <strong>the</strong> goal of <strong>the</strong><br />

action of hitt<strong>in</strong>g (semantics of <strong>the</strong> preposition)<br />

b. if hitt<strong>in</strong>g an object A and hitt<strong>in</strong>g an object B form one and <strong>the</strong> same event, <strong>the</strong>n it has<br />

to be <strong>the</strong> case that ei<strong>the</strong>r A is part of/equal to B or B is part of/equal to A (semantics of<br />

<strong>the</strong> verb)<br />

c. hands are parts of humans (semantics of <strong>in</strong>alienable possession)<br />

From <strong>the</strong> assumptions <strong>in</strong> (6) it follows that <strong>the</strong> hand <strong>in</strong> (5) has to be John’s. More precisely, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> goal read<strong>in</strong>g of sur <strong>the</strong> hitt<strong>in</strong>g of John is associated with <strong>the</strong> hitt<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> hand, while, by b.


and c., it is ensured that <strong>the</strong>re is a part-of relation between <strong>the</strong> hand and John. Similar analyses<br />

can be presented for several preposition/verb/<strong>in</strong>alienable possessum noun triplets (see Koenig<br />

1999 for a similar yet less flexible analysis).<br />

The second way FaithPoss can be satisfied without an overt possessive pronoun is through <strong>the</strong><br />

use of datives that can and sometimes must undergo so-called possessor rais<strong>in</strong>g (see Szabolsci<br />

1983, Nicol 1997 and Landau 1999). This is illustrated <strong>in</strong> (7):<br />

(7) Le frère k de Jean l lui l a pris la ma<strong>in</strong> t l.<br />

The bro<strong>the</strong>r of John to_him has taken <strong>the</strong> hand<br />

‘John’s bro<strong>the</strong>r took his hand’<br />

The reason<strong>in</strong>g here is similar to <strong>the</strong> one we made on <strong>the</strong> basis of (6): tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> hand to someone<br />

entails that <strong>the</strong> hand <strong>in</strong> question has to belong to this someone.<br />

We are now ready to put our constra<strong>in</strong>ts to work <strong>in</strong> an OT analysis and to discuss its predictions.<br />

Note that <strong>the</strong> facts we discuss are <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> ones that have been discussed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

literature as basic evidence <strong>in</strong> favour of an analysis <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Given that we have two constra<strong>in</strong>ts, we expect to have two types of languages: one <strong>in</strong> which<br />

FaithPoss is ranked below DUPP and one <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> reverse is <strong>the</strong> case. In<br />

DUPP>>FaithPoss languages we expect <strong>in</strong>alienable possessum nouns – wherever possible – to<br />

occur <strong>in</strong> prepositional phrases or with a dative, satisfy<strong>in</strong>g FaithPoss without violat<strong>in</strong>g DUPP.<br />

Wherever this is impossible, we expect <strong>the</strong>m to occur with <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article, violat<strong>in</strong>g FaithPoss<br />

but satisfy<strong>in</strong>g DUPP. This derives <strong>the</strong> facts for French <strong>in</strong> (1), (7), (8), (9) and (10).<br />

(8) *Il se lève la ma<strong>in</strong>. (9) *Le frère k de Jean l a pris la ma<strong>in</strong> t l.<br />

He to_hi<strong>ms</strong>elf raises <strong>the</strong> hand The bro<strong>the</strong>r of John to_him has taken <strong>the</strong> hand<br />

(10) Le frère k de Jean l l l’a pris par la ma<strong>in</strong> l.<br />

The bro<strong>the</strong>r of John him has taken by <strong>the</strong> hand<br />

The acceptability of (1) follows from <strong>the</strong> unacceptability of (8) and <strong>the</strong> unavailability of a<br />

prepositional variant, <strong>the</strong> unacceptability of (9) follows from <strong>the</strong> availability of (7) and (10). The<br />

crucial <strong>in</strong>sight we propose here is that <strong>the</strong> acceptability of <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>alienable<br />

possession construction depends on <strong>the</strong> availability of o<strong>the</strong>r constructions. We don’t deny that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g generalizations that govern <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r constructions but we do<br />

claim that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricacies that come with <strong>the</strong>se should not be <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> analysis of<br />

<strong>in</strong>alienable possession as <strong>the</strong>y might ultimately reside <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lexicon. A clear argument <strong>in</strong> favour<br />

of this strategy comes from <strong>the</strong> fact that similar verbs <strong>in</strong> languages that generally allow for<br />

<strong>in</strong>alienable possession with <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article need not allow for similar constructions. Compare<br />

<strong>in</strong> this respect <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>ality of French la tête me fait mal (‘<strong>the</strong> head to me makes ache’) to <strong>the</strong> full<br />

productivity of Spanish me duele la cabeza (‘to me makes_ache <strong>the</strong> head’).<br />

In FaithPoss>>DUPP languages we expect <strong>in</strong>alienable possessum nouns – wherever possible –<br />

to occur <strong>in</strong> prepositional phrases or with a dative, satisfy<strong>in</strong>g FaithPoss without violat<strong>in</strong>g DUPP.<br />

Wherever this is impossible, we expect <strong>the</strong>m to take a possessive pronoun, violat<strong>in</strong>g DUPP but<br />

satisfy<strong>in</strong>g FaithPoss. This straightforwardly derives <strong>the</strong> facts for English:<br />

(11) Mary k hit John l on <strong>the</strong> hand l. (12) *John k raised <strong>the</strong> hand k.<br />

The acceptability of (11) follows from <strong>the</strong> fact that both FaithPoss and DUPP are satisfied, <strong>the</strong><br />

unacceptability of (12) follows from a violation of FaithPoss.<br />

In this paper, we have proposed an OT analysis that comb<strong>in</strong>es <strong>in</strong>sights about <strong>the</strong> semantics of<br />

verbs, prepositions, datives and <strong>in</strong>alienable possessum nouns with a straigthforward markedness<br />

(DUPP) and faithfulness (FaithPoss) constra<strong>in</strong>t. The result is an elegant analysis with a m<strong>in</strong>imum<br />

of stipulations and a maximum of data coverage. We <strong>in</strong> particular showed how we can avoid<br />

stipulat<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article functions as an expletive or a pronoun <strong>in</strong> disguise.<br />

References | Barker (<strong>in</strong> press) ‘Possessive weak def<strong>in</strong>ites’ | Farkas (2002), Journal of Semantics 19:<br />

213-243. | Guéron (1985), <strong>in</strong> Guéron et al. (eds.), Grammatical Representation, Dordrecht: Foris. |<br />

Koenig (1999), NLLT 17: 219-265. | Landau (1999), L<strong>in</strong>gua 107: 1-37. | Nicol (1997), PhD<br />

dissertation, Paris X. | Szabolcsi (1983), The L<strong>in</strong>guistic Review 3: 89-102. |Vergnaud & Zubizarreta<br />

(1992), LI 213: 595-652.


Artemis Alexiadou (Stuttgart) & Elena Anagnostopoulou (Crete)<br />

Verb mean<strong>in</strong>g, local context, and <strong>the</strong> syntax of roots <strong>in</strong> alternations<br />

1. While it is uncontroversial that extra-grammatical context (l<strong>in</strong>guistic and non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic)<br />

can <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> form and mean<strong>in</strong>g of sentences, research <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area of verbal alternations<br />

has revealed that <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r notion of context important for mean<strong>in</strong>g, which we call here<br />

local context. Mean<strong>in</strong>g of verbs is computed on <strong>the</strong> basis of a ‘core element’ (<strong>the</strong> ‘root’)<br />

which is <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong> a structural template (local context). On this view, verb classes are sets<br />

of verbs shar<strong>in</strong>g a local context while <strong>the</strong> idiosyncratic properties of a given root determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r and how this root can be <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong> a structural template. This basic approach has<br />

been advocated both <strong>in</strong> models of lexical semantic decomposition (e.g. Rappaport Hovav &<br />

Lev<strong>in</strong> RH&L 1998) and <strong>in</strong> models of morphological-syntactic decomposition (e.g. work <strong>in</strong><br />

Distributed Morphology (DM) follow<strong>in</strong>g Marantz 1997, 2001). From <strong>the</strong> DM perspective, a<br />

syntactic representation is <strong>the</strong>n <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> consultation with <strong>the</strong> encyclopedia. Crucially,<br />

encyclopedia entries <strong>in</strong>terpret structures <strong>in</strong> very specific contexts and <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ations. A<br />

question aris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> such models is to what extent <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ants of argument realization are<br />

part of <strong>the</strong> root <strong>in</strong>formation and to what extent <strong>the</strong>y are part of <strong>the</strong> event/syntactic template<br />

(see Borer 2005 for a radically exo-skeletal view). In this paper, we explore how <strong>the</strong>se two<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g components <strong>in</strong>teract on <strong>the</strong> basis of a case study, namely <strong>the</strong> clear-alternation. We<br />

argue that object alternations relate to whe<strong>the</strong>r verbs are classified as manner or result, which<br />

depends on <strong>the</strong> ontological types of <strong>the</strong> morphological roots <strong>the</strong>y are based on and <strong>the</strong> local<br />

contexts permissible for different ontological types of roots.<br />

2. In English, locative verbs of plac<strong>in</strong>g (spray, load) and detach<strong>in</strong>g (clear) alternate between<br />

two frames (1), illustrated <strong>in</strong> (2), see Lev<strong>in</strong> (1993), L& RH (1991):<br />

(1) a. Frame A: DPAgent V DPStuff PPLoc b. Frame B: DPAgent V DPLoc PPStuff<br />

(2) a. Lucy sprayed <strong>the</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t on <strong>the</strong> wall b. Lucy sprayed <strong>the</strong> wall with pa<strong>in</strong>t<br />

c. Henry cleared dishes from <strong>the</strong> table d. Henry cleared <strong>the</strong> table of dishes<br />

Many locative verbs do not allow <strong>the</strong> alternation, and choose ei<strong>the</strong>r only Frame A (e.g. steal<br />

Change of Location COL) or Frame B (e.g. cover, Change of State COS). The <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> two frames is given <strong>in</strong> (3):<br />

(3) a. COL <strong>in</strong>terpretation (Frame A): [X CAUSE [Y BECOME [AT Z/AWAY FROM Z]]]<br />

b. COS <strong>in</strong>terpretation (Frame B): [X CAUSE [Z BECOME [WITH Y/WITHOUT Y]]]<br />

The question thus is what underlies <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between alternat<strong>in</strong>g and non-alternat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verbs and why <strong>the</strong> latter choose <strong>the</strong> COL or <strong>the</strong> COS frame. In <strong>the</strong> recent literature, it has been<br />

proposed that <strong>the</strong> (un-)availability of object alternations can be understood <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

Manner vs. Result hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (RH&L 1998, 2008) accord<strong>in</strong>g to which: i) Verbs lexicalize<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r manner or result (manner or result, respectively, are entailed by all uses of verbs). ii)<br />

Verbs alternate when <strong>the</strong>y lexicalize manner and <strong>the</strong>y don’t when <strong>the</strong>y lexicalize result.<br />

3. Mavropoulou, Moschou, Tsikala & Anagnostopoulou (MMTA) (2011) show that Greek<br />

has both <strong>the</strong> spray- and <strong>the</strong> clear- alternation:<br />

(4) a. psekasa boja ston tiho b. psekasa ton tiho me boja<br />

sprayed-1sg pa<strong>in</strong>t to <strong>the</strong> wall sprayed-1sg <strong>the</strong> wall with pa<strong>in</strong>t<br />

c. katharisa ta psihula apo to trapezi d. katharisa to trapezi apo psihula<br />

cleaned-1sg <strong>the</strong> crumbles from <strong>the</strong> table cleaned-1sg <strong>the</strong> table from crumbles<br />

These authors provide lists of locative verbs that alternate <strong>in</strong> Greek, and establish <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g: i) <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>the</strong> alternation is more systematic with verbs of detach<strong>in</strong>g. This<br />

property is partially attributed to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> preposition used with this class is apo<br />

‘from’, which is clearly directional (unlike se ‘to’) and can easily comb<strong>in</strong>e with manner roots<br />

express<strong>in</strong>g COL (Frame A). ii) More verbs of detach<strong>in</strong>g alternate <strong>in</strong> Greek than <strong>in</strong> English,<br />

where accord<strong>in</strong>g to L&RH (1991) only four verbs alternate (but o<strong>the</strong>rs claim that several<br />

wipe- verbs may alternate as well; see Lev<strong>in</strong> 1993). In <strong>the</strong>se two respects, Greek is similar to<br />

Hebrew, as described by Segal & Landau (S&L 2009). S&L (2009) argue that alternat<strong>in</strong>g


clear verbs are not specified for <strong>the</strong> type of change <strong>in</strong>volved (<strong>the</strong>y entail nei<strong>the</strong>r COL nor<br />

COS), while those that do not alternate are specified ei<strong>the</strong>r entail<strong>in</strong>g COL and appear <strong>in</strong><br />

Frame A or COS (and appear <strong>in</strong> Frame B). MMTA (2011) show that this holds <strong>in</strong> Greek too.<br />

4. The morphological make-up of Greek verbs of detachment strongly suggests that a large<br />

class of alternat<strong>in</strong>g verbs (i.e. verbs not specified for COL/COS) are manner verbs and nonalternat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

ones (ei<strong>the</strong>r only COL or only COS) are result verbs, as expected by <strong>the</strong> Manner<br />

vs. Result Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Alternat<strong>in</strong>g verbs typically <strong>in</strong>volve manner/<strong>in</strong>strument roots and a<br />

verbalizer e.g. -on- <strong>in</strong> (5a) (<strong>the</strong>se correspond to <strong>the</strong> English wipe-class). Verbs only allow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

COL conta<strong>in</strong> prepositions/prefixes/particles that overtly encode location (5b); verbs only<br />

allow<strong>in</strong>g COS are based on an adjective, plus a verbalizer, thus overtly encod<strong>in</strong>g state (5c).<br />

(5) a. sider-on-o lit. iron-v-1sg ‘iron’ b. af-er-o lit. from-lift-1sg ‘remove’<br />

c. atho-on-o lit. <strong>in</strong>nocent-v-1sg ‘acquit’<br />

Apply<strong>in</strong>g a series of manner vs. result diagnostics (see Koontz Garboden & Beavers 2011)<br />

confir<strong>ms</strong> that (5a)-type verbs are manner verbs and (5b,c)-type verbs are result verbs. These<br />

can be morphologically decomposed by us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> tools of DM: verbs consist of categoryneutral,<br />

idiosyncratic roots which are merged with categoriz<strong>in</strong>g heads (Marantz 2001) ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

as <strong>the</strong>ir modifiers, direct Merge, or as <strong>the</strong>ir complements (Embick 2004; Harley 2005).<br />

(6) a. modifiers of v, direct Merge: [v v √ ] b. complements of v [v √ v]<br />

For Embick, direct merge specifies <strong>the</strong> means component of <strong>the</strong> complex predicate, and (6a)<br />

can feed secondary resultative predication. Thus <strong>the</strong> type of merge is sensitive to <strong>the</strong> manner<br />

vs. result/state classification of roots: manner roots merge as modifiers of v, state roots merge<br />

as complements of v. Comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g RH&L’s <strong>in</strong>sights with Embick’s structures, we propose that<br />

direct merge applies to manner/<strong>in</strong>strument roots with alternat<strong>in</strong>g verbs of <strong>the</strong> (5a)-type. S<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

<strong>the</strong>se roots merge as modifiers of v, <strong>the</strong>y can be <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> resultative secondary predication,<br />

yield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> COL and <strong>the</strong> COS frames. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Hale & Keyser (2002), S&L (2009) and<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs, we assume that <strong>in</strong> COL, a locative (source) PP is <strong>the</strong> sister of v and <strong>the</strong> stuff DP as <strong>the</strong><br />

specifier of P (7). In COS, a ResultP is <strong>the</strong> sister of v and <strong>the</strong> DPlocation is <strong>the</strong> specifier of v (8):<br />

(7) [v v � [PP DPstuff [P DPlocation ]]] (8) [vP DPlocation [v [ResultP]]]<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to non-alternat<strong>in</strong>g verbs, Greek verbs show<strong>in</strong>g only frame A conta<strong>in</strong> prefixes, drawn<br />

from <strong>the</strong> prepositional <strong>in</strong>ventory. Most of <strong>the</strong>m belong to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventory of Classical Greek and<br />

are no longer productive. They cannot be separated from <strong>the</strong> verbal stem, predom<strong>in</strong>antly have<br />

spatial mean<strong>in</strong>gs, and <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with <strong>the</strong> morphological root give <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of what<br />

L&RH label “root” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lexical semantic sense, e.g. ek- top- iz-o ‘from -place-verbalizer-<br />

1sg.’. We propose that <strong>the</strong> prefixes ‘lexicalize’ path and select a PlaceP complement<br />

(Svenonius 2008), lexicalized by �top <strong>in</strong> (9). The apo phrase is <strong>in</strong> Spec,Path, and <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

Spec-head Agreement relationship, <strong>in</strong> this case Source. Support for this analysis comes from<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that when Path = Goal, <strong>the</strong> verbal prefix is ‘eis’ (to) and <strong>the</strong> Goal-PP is a se-‘to’ PP.<br />

(9) [vP iz [PathP ek [PlaceP �top ]]]<br />

Greek non-alternat<strong>in</strong>g verbs show<strong>in</strong>g only COS are built on <strong>the</strong> basis of an adjectival base.<br />

The set of adjectives related to <strong>the</strong>se verbs can each take a complement expressed by means<br />

of an apo phrase <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> stuff argument (adio apo nero ‘empty from water’), which is<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>in</strong>herited by <strong>the</strong> verb derived from <strong>the</strong>se adjectives. Thus <strong>the</strong> verbs appear only <strong>in</strong> COS.<br />

5. We provided evidence that verbal alternations depend on both <strong>the</strong> ontological types of <strong>the</strong><br />

verbal roots <strong>in</strong>volved and on <strong>the</strong> local contexts permissible for <strong>the</strong>se different types. This <strong>in</strong><br />

turn suggests that a) roots do have some mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> isolation (contra e.g. Acquaviva 2009,<br />

Borer 2008, de Belder & van Craenenbroeck 2011) which consists of a limited number of<br />

contrastive properties (manner, state and place <strong>in</strong> our case), b) <strong>the</strong>se dist<strong>in</strong>ctions <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong><br />

syntactic merger possibilities of roots, c) <strong>the</strong> syntactic template roots are <strong>in</strong>serted <strong>in</strong> fully<br />

specifies <strong>the</strong> realization of verbal arguments, and d) mean<strong>in</strong>g is assigned by <strong>the</strong> encyclopedia<br />

that calculates both <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put of <strong>the</strong> root and that of <strong>the</strong> syntactic template.


Artemis Alexiadou & Florian Schäfer (Stuttgart)<br />

Naturally reflexive verbs revisited: relations between syntax, semantics, and <strong>the</strong> lexicon<br />

1. In <strong>the</strong> literature, naturally reflexive verbs ((NRVs) e.g. wash, Kemmer 1993) have been <strong>the</strong><br />

topic of much controversial discussion. Here we focus on one particular aspect of this debate,<br />

namely <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r or not NRVs <strong>in</strong>clude an empty category at some level of<br />

representation, ei<strong>the</strong>r a null reflexive or a trace/copy, <strong>in</strong> languages like English and Greek. In<br />

<strong>the</strong>se languages, NRVs are, at <strong>the</strong> surface, <strong>in</strong>transitive ei<strong>the</strong>r because no overt reflexive form<br />

is present (English: John washed) or because, <strong>in</strong> addition, de-transitiviz<strong>in</strong>g morphology is<br />

present (Greek: O Janis plithike 'John washed-non-active-3sg'). As <strong>the</strong> class of verbs that are<br />

treated as naturally reflexive see<strong>ms</strong> quite stable across languages, a uniform analysis has been<br />

argued to be desirable (see e.g. Alexiadou & Doron 2011). In this paper, we argue for a nonuniform<br />

analysis of NRVs across languages (cf. Re<strong>in</strong>hart & Siloni 's 2004 lexicon vs. syntax<br />

parameter; see Decha<strong>in</strong>e & Wiltschko 2011 for discussion of heterogeneous approaches to<br />

reflexives). We first show that under closer <strong>in</strong>spection, English NRVs are syntactically<br />

<strong>in</strong>transitive, provid<strong>in</strong>g thus fur<strong>the</strong>r support for <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong>se predicates lack a<br />

syntactically projected object (Re<strong>in</strong>hart & Siloni 2004). While an <strong>in</strong>transitive analysis is<br />

available for English, it cannot extend to German, Dutch and Greek. In <strong>the</strong> former case<br />

(German, Dutch), this is so because a syntactically projected object is overtly present, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

latter case (Greek) because NRVs, unlike ord<strong>in</strong>ary unergatives, show de-transitivization<br />

morphology. We thus propose a tri-partition of <strong>the</strong> way languages resolve <strong>the</strong> requirement<br />

that <strong>the</strong> two <strong>the</strong>matic roles associated with NRVs make reference to <strong>the</strong> same entity: a) <strong>in</strong><br />

English, this is done at <strong>the</strong> conceptual <strong>in</strong>terface, b) <strong>in</strong> German and Dutch, this is done via<br />

b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of an object anaphor, and c) <strong>in</strong> Greek, this is done via movement <strong>in</strong>to a <strong>the</strong>ta-position<br />

(syntactic bundl<strong>in</strong>g). This reflects <strong>the</strong> type of morphology we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> three language<br />

groups, zero/none, reflexive pronoun, and an affix, respectively. Our analysis correctly<br />

predicts <strong>the</strong> productivity of reflexivization noted for Greek, but not for e.g. English, which is<br />

not captured under <strong>the</strong> homogeneous approach.<br />

2. Some authors argued that NRVs are actually transitive, i.e. <strong>the</strong>y select a specific reflexive<br />

null morpheme, which is overt <strong>in</strong> languages like German (Hans wäscht sich ‘Hans washes<br />

hi<strong>ms</strong>elf’), see Safir (2004) and references <strong>the</strong>re<strong>in</strong>, Marantz (2009). Support for this comes<br />

from <strong>the</strong> observation that <strong>the</strong>se predicates do have transitive construals, e.g. John washed<br />

Mary/John didn't wash Mary but hi<strong>ms</strong>elf. O<strong>the</strong>rs proposed that NRVs are actually<br />

unaccusatives, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me argument is a derived subject and leaves a trace/copy <strong>in</strong> its <strong>the</strong>matic<br />

position (Marantz 1984, and subsequent work, McG<strong>in</strong>nis 1998, Embick 2004). Support for<br />

this analysis comes from languages such as Greek that mark <strong>the</strong>ir NRVs with <strong>the</strong> same nonactive<br />

morphology as <strong>the</strong>ir passives or uncontroversial unaccusatives. Both <strong>the</strong>se analyses are<br />

problematic for English. Sells, Zaenen & Zec (1987) showed that NRVs behave unlike<br />

predicates that take an overt reflexive with respect to ‘strict’ and ‘sloppy’ read<strong>in</strong>gs. (1), with<br />

an overt reflexive, is ambiguous between a strict and sloppy read<strong>in</strong>g. (2), an NRV, has only<br />

<strong>the</strong> sloppy read<strong>in</strong>g, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> predicate is semantically <strong>in</strong>transitive:<br />

(1) John defends hi<strong>ms</strong>elf better than Peter<br />

a. John defends hi<strong>ms</strong>elf better than Peter defends hi<strong>ms</strong>elf sloppy<br />

b. Johni defends hi<strong>ms</strong>elf better that Peter defends himi strict<br />

(2) John washes more than George.<br />

a. John washes hi<strong>ms</strong>elf more than George washes hi<strong>ms</strong>elf. sloppy<br />

b. John i washes hi<strong>ms</strong>elf more <strong>the</strong>n George washes him i *strict<br />

(1) has a fur<strong>the</strong>r read<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> so-called object comparison read<strong>in</strong>g (Johni defends hi<strong>ms</strong>elf<br />

better that he i defends Peter), which (2) lacks, as expected, see Dimitriadis & Que (2009).<br />

Re<strong>in</strong>hart & Siloni (2004) po<strong>in</strong>ted out that NRVs <strong>in</strong> English behave unlike one-place<br />

unaccusatives. As is well-known, agentive -er nom<strong>in</strong>als can only be derived from predicates<br />

with an external argument (Lev<strong>in</strong> & Rappaport Hovav 1992). Re<strong>in</strong>hart & Siloni show that


NRVs form agentive nom<strong>in</strong>als (3c), similar to unergatives (3a):<br />

(3) a. She runs so fast because she is an experienced runner.<br />

b. * She moves so gracefully because she is an experienced mover.<br />

c. She dresses slowly because she is an elegant dresser.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r support for an unergative analysis comes from <strong>the</strong> application of o<strong>the</strong>r transitivity<br />

tests (Bresnan 1982, Kratzer 2004, Lev<strong>in</strong> 1999, Rappaport Hovav and Lev<strong>in</strong> 1998, 2008).<br />

Reduplication to get an iterative read<strong>in</strong>g, out-prefixation and ‘fake’ reflexives are possible<br />

only with non-core transitive (and unergative) verbs (4), but not with core-transitives (5). (6),<br />

an NRV, behaves like (4), <strong>in</strong> both its read<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong> reflexive and <strong>the</strong> disjo<strong>in</strong>t one:<br />

(4) a. John run and run and run/John ate and ate. (5) a.*John broke and broke and broke<br />

b. John out-run/out-ate Mary. b. *John out-broke Mary.<br />

c. John run/ate hi<strong>ms</strong>elf dead. c. *John broke-hi<strong>ms</strong>elf dead.<br />

(6) a. John washed and washed and washed.<br />

b. John out-washed his sister.<br />

c. John washed hi<strong>ms</strong>elf raw.<br />

3. To expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> behavior of English NRVs, it has been proposed that <strong>the</strong>se have two lexical<br />

entries, a reflexive and a disjo<strong>in</strong>t one (see e.g. Moulton 2005). Assum<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> external<br />

argument is severed from <strong>the</strong> VP (Kratzer 1996), and is <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> Voice, it is not clear<br />

how to formally encode that such a lexical entry br<strong>in</strong>gs about a reflexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, such a move see<strong>ms</strong> undesirable, as it would lead to an explosion of <strong>the</strong> lexicon.<br />

We showed that NRVs are similar to o<strong>the</strong>r non-core transitive predicates like eat. An option<br />

that is available for <strong>the</strong>se predicates, under <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong>matic roles belong to <strong>the</strong><br />

conceptual level (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 1995), is to <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong>m as two-place predicates at <strong>the</strong> syntaxconceptual<br />

level <strong>in</strong>terface. This means that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is added post-syntactically.<br />

With verbs of consumption, <strong>the</strong> added argument is <strong>the</strong> most prototypical object for this<br />

predicate-class, an amount of food/fluid that one can consume. NRVs are def<strong>in</strong>ed as carry<strong>in</strong>g<br />

“<strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>g [...] <strong>the</strong> lack of expectation that <strong>the</strong> two semantic roles <strong>the</strong>y make<br />

reference to will refer to dist<strong>in</strong>ct entities” (Kemmer 1993:58). The most prototypical object is<br />

thus identical to <strong>the</strong> subject, and this is computed at <strong>the</strong> conceptual <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

4. Dutch and German have an overt object for <strong>the</strong> reflexive <strong>in</strong>terpretation, and allow only <strong>the</strong><br />

disjo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation to be resolved at <strong>the</strong> conceptual <strong>in</strong>terface. In <strong>the</strong>se languages, NRVs are<br />

syntactically transitive (e.g. Ste<strong>in</strong>bach 2002). As an <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is projected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

syntax to be bound by <strong>the</strong> external one, <strong>the</strong>se predicates lack disjo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>gs. We relate this<br />

to <strong>the</strong> special (light) reflexives for<strong>ms</strong> used, an option unavailable <strong>in</strong> English.<br />

5. Nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> unergative nor <strong>the</strong> transitive analysis is applicable to Greek due to <strong>the</strong> presence<br />

of non-active morphology with NRVs. Embick (2004) proposed that NRVs comb<strong>in</strong>e with a<br />

Voice that is agentive, but lacks a specifier, and this is realized via non-active morphology at<br />

morphological structure. This cannot expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of disjo<strong>in</strong>t reference with reflexives,<br />

but not with passives. Doron (2003) argued that NRVs comb<strong>in</strong>e with a special k<strong>in</strong>d of Voice<br />

(<strong>the</strong> host of non-active morphology), which does not trigger <strong>the</strong> disjo<strong>in</strong>t reference effect. But<br />

this raises <strong>the</strong> question what regulates <strong>the</strong> cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic distribution of this special Voice.<br />

We propose <strong>in</strong>stead that <strong>in</strong> Greek, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument moves to Spec,Voice, comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

two <strong>the</strong>matic roles (<strong>the</strong>me & agent). This expla<strong>in</strong>s Papangeli’s (2004) observation that <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are many newly formed reflexives <strong>in</strong> Greek (e.g. hapakonete = to give pills to hi<strong>ms</strong>elf,<br />

derived from <strong>the</strong> transitive verb via <strong>the</strong> addition of non-active morphology) that would be<br />

hard to expla<strong>in</strong>, if we assumed that only a closed set of verbs has a reflexive variant. We view<br />

non-active morphology as similar to be-selection <strong>in</strong> Romance (cf. Haider & R<strong>in</strong>dler-Schjerve<br />

1987): it is <strong>the</strong> morphological reflex of an agreement cha<strong>in</strong> between T and an element with<strong>in</strong><br />

VP, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of passives and unaccusatives. With reflexives, T agrees with <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

cha<strong>in</strong> between <strong>the</strong> object and <strong>the</strong> subject position, lead<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong> to non-active morphology.


Anke Assmann, Doreen Georgi, Fabian Heck, Gereon Müller & Philipp Weisser (Leipzig)<br />

Ergatives move too early<br />

Claim: We claim that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ability of ergative arguments (DPerg) to undergo Ā-movement<br />

(wh-movement, focuss<strong>in</strong>g, relativization) <strong>in</strong> many morphologically ergative languages should<br />

not be brought about by restrictions on <strong>the</strong> movement of ergative DPs. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, we argue that<br />

movement of <strong>the</strong> ergative argument is not prohibited per se but if it applies, it applies too early,<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g case assignment to <strong>the</strong> absolutive argument (DPabs). As a consequence,<br />

<strong>the</strong> derivation crashes.<br />

Background & Data: It has been noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature that <strong>in</strong> many ergative languages DPerg<br />

cannot be Ā-moved, <strong>in</strong> contrast to DPabs, cf. (1).<br />

(1) Katuk<strong>in</strong>a-Kanamari—Wh-Movement (Queixalos 2010)<br />

a. hanian tu Nodia nah=hoho-n<strong>in</strong>?<br />

b. *hanian tan dyuman tahi yu?<br />

whom Q Nodia ERG=call-DURATIVE who here spread water Q<br />

‘Whom is Nodia call<strong>in</strong>g?’<br />

‘Who spread water here?’<br />

There are at least two possible analyses: (i) The trace of DPerg is not licensed (e.g. <strong>in</strong> GB<br />

ter<strong>ms</strong>, it is not strictly governed); (ii) (covert) movement of DPabs blocks movement of DPerg,<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r due to m<strong>in</strong>imality (Campana 1992), or DPabs blocks <strong>the</strong> only escape hatch with<strong>in</strong> vP<br />

(Aldridge 2004, Coon 2010). Both approaches suffer from technical and empirical proble<strong>ms</strong>.<br />

As for (i), constra<strong>in</strong>ts on traces cannot be formulated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imalist framework. As for (ii),<br />

Campana’s analysis is based on a non-standard concept of <strong>in</strong>tervention while Aldridge (2004)<br />

and Coon (2010) must stipulate a ban on multiple specifiers. All three accounts must resort to<br />

covert movement of DPabs, which is hardly motivated on <strong>in</strong>dependent grounds. Empirically, <strong>the</strong><br />

analyses <strong>in</strong> (ii) make <strong>the</strong> wrong prediction that DPabs not only blocks movement of DPerg but<br />

also movement of o<strong>the</strong>r vP-<strong>in</strong>ternal elements like adjuncts or obliques (2). They also predict that<br />

similar movement asymmetries between coarguments should be found <strong>in</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>ative-accusative<br />

languages, contrary to fact.<br />

(2) Mam —Wh-Movement of Passive Agent (England 1983)<br />

al uPn xhi kub’ tzy-eet qa-cheej?<br />

Q RN DEP-3PL.ABS DIR GRAB-pass PL-horse<br />

‘By whom were <strong>the</strong> horses grabbed?’<br />

Assumptions: [A1] Follow<strong>in</strong>g Müller (2009), we assume that (i) case is assigned under Agree,<br />

(ii) <strong>in</strong> all languages, T assigns unmarked case (NOM/ABS) and v marked case (ERG/ACC),<br />

(iii) <strong>the</strong> only difference between accusative and ergative case syste<strong>ms</strong> is <strong>the</strong> order <strong>in</strong> which<br />

<strong>the</strong> basic operations Merge and Agree apply with<strong>in</strong> vP. S<strong>in</strong>ce v triggers two operations (it assigns<br />

case and selects an external argument), languages must give preference ei<strong>the</strong>r to Agree or<br />

Merge, given Earl<strong>in</strong>ess (Pesetsky 1989) and <strong>the</strong> tenet that operations cannot apply simultaneously.<br />

[A2] Instead of m<strong>in</strong>imality, we assume a Specifier-Head-Bias (SHB) which states that<br />

agreement between a head and its specifier is preferred to agreement between a head and an element<br />

its c-command doma<strong>in</strong> (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 1986, 1995, Koopman 2006; see Béjar & ˇRezáč 2009<br />

for a similar idea with a bias <strong>in</strong>versed). The SHB is compatible with equi-distance effects, which<br />

pose a problem for path-based def<strong>in</strong>itions of m<strong>in</strong>imality. [A3] Movement to SpecCP must make<br />

an <strong>in</strong>termediate stop <strong>in</strong> SpecTP. This is ensured by assum<strong>in</strong>g that ei<strong>the</strong>r TP is a phase (Richards<br />

2011), any XP is a phase (Müller 2010) or strict locality (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2005). [A4] Edge features<br />

on phase heads are freely available (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2000). [A5] Arguments may receive more than<br />

one case (cf. approaches to case stack<strong>in</strong>g: Andrews 1996, Nordl<strong>in</strong>ger 1998, Richards 2007).<br />

[A6] Agree is not sensitive to <strong>the</strong> PIC (see e.g. Boˇskovič 2007).<br />

Analysis: In ergative languages, preference is given to Merge over Agree with <strong>the</strong> result that v<br />

first selects <strong>the</strong> external argument (DPext) before it assigns case. Due to <strong>the</strong> SHB, <strong>the</strong> marked<br />

case of v ends up on its specifier while <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument (DP<strong>in</strong>t) receives case from T,


given [A6]. In accusative languages, preference is given to Agree over Merge, such that v has<br />

to assign case to DP<strong>in</strong>t before Merge of DPext, which <strong>in</strong> turn receives case from T (cf. Müller<br />

2009). Now, on <strong>the</strong> T head, <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy as on v arises: it assigns case and must<br />

have an edge feature if one argument is to undergo Ā-movement. Assum<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> languagespecific<br />

order of operations rema<strong>in</strong>s constant throughout <strong>the</strong> derivation, we can derive <strong>the</strong> ban on<br />

ergative movement and <strong>the</strong> asymmetry between ergative and accusative languages, consider<strong>in</strong>g<br />

two different derivations: [D1] DPext has an additional [wh]-feature and moves to an operator<br />

position <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> left periphery via SpecTP ([A3]; [A4]) to check this feature; [D2] DP<strong>in</strong>t has a<br />

[wh]-feature and moves to an operator position. As for [D1], <strong>in</strong> accusative languages DP<strong>in</strong>t has<br />

received accusative with<strong>in</strong> vP. DPext receives case via Agree as soon as T is merged because<br />

Agree is preferred over Merge. Afterwards, DPext is free to move and check <strong>the</strong> edge feature on<br />

T. In ergative languages, DPext receives case with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP; DP<strong>in</strong>t rema<strong>in</strong>s unvalued. As soon as<br />

T is merged, it first attracts DPext to satisfy its edge feature (preference for Merge over Agree).<br />

Due to <strong>the</strong> SHB ([A2]), DPext checks case on T ([A5]) with <strong>the</strong> result that DP<strong>in</strong>t does not<br />

receive any case. The derivation crashes because DPext has absorbed <strong>the</strong> case features provided<br />

for DP<strong>in</strong>t. As for [D2], <strong>in</strong> accusative languages, DP<strong>in</strong>t receives its case from v while DPext is<br />

still unvalued. When T enters <strong>the</strong> structure, it first assigns case to DPext before it attracts DP<strong>in</strong>t<br />

to its specifier (preference for Agree). Thus, <strong>the</strong> context for multiple case-check<strong>in</strong>g does not<br />

arise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. In ergative languages, DP<strong>in</strong>t is attracted to SpecTP where it receives its<br />

case due to <strong>the</strong> SHB while DPext receives case from v. The derivation converges. In summary,<br />

out of <strong>the</strong> four derivations <strong>in</strong> which one argument is extracted, three derivations converge. Only<br />

<strong>the</strong> derivation <strong>in</strong> which DPext <strong>in</strong> an ergative language is extracted is ungrammatical because<br />

DPerg moves before T has assigns case to DPabs. Hence, ergatives move too early.<br />

Conclusion: The present analysis has several advantages: (i) It captures <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuition by Pol<strong>in</strong>sky<br />

et al (2011) that movement of DPerg is not problematic per se but leads to a problem for <strong>the</strong><br />

identification of DPabs. (ii) It is not forced to assume unmotivated covert movement steps of <strong>the</strong><br />

absolutive. (iii) It avoids stipulations about <strong>the</strong> different nature of ergative and accusative syntax.<br />

One parameter, namely <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g of Merge and Agree, derives <strong>the</strong> difference <strong>in</strong> argument<br />

encod<strong>in</strong>g as well as <strong>the</strong> difference that <strong>the</strong>re is a movement asymmetry between coarguments <strong>in</strong><br />

ergative but not <strong>in</strong> accusative languages. (iv) It is empirically superior to o<strong>the</strong>r exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ories<br />

because it makes <strong>the</strong> correct prediction that <strong>in</strong> languages which exhibit a ban on movement of<br />

<strong>the</strong> ergative o<strong>the</strong>r elements like adjuncts, passive agents and obliques are still free to move (cf.<br />

(2)). It should also be clear that our analysis implies a strictly derivational syntax <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong><br />

order of operations plays an important role <strong>in</strong> deriv<strong>in</strong>g properties of <strong>the</strong> grammar.<br />

Outlook: F<strong>in</strong>ally, we address <strong>the</strong> related question of why not all ergative languages <strong>in</strong>stantiate<br />

a ban on ergative movement and discuss several possible answers: (i) The order of operations<br />

on T differs from <strong>the</strong> order on v. (ii) T is not a phase head. (iii) DPs cannot check multiple<br />

case features. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, we exam<strong>in</strong>e repair strategies for <strong>the</strong> ban on ergative movement<br />

such as antipassive or agent focus (Stiebels 2006, Aissen 1999). We argue that <strong>the</strong> agent focus<br />

morpheme is <strong>the</strong> morphological realization of an added probe which assigns case to DP<strong>in</strong>t,<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby prevent<strong>in</strong>g a crash of <strong>the</strong> derivation (cf. Béjar & ˇRezáč 2009, Coon 2010).<br />

Selected References: Aldrige, E. (2008): <strong>Generative</strong> Approaches to Ergativity, Language and <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> Compass<br />

2(5), 966-995. • Béjar, S. & M. ˇRezáč (2009): Cyclic Agree, L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 40(1), 35-73. • Boˇskovič,<br />

ˇZ. (2007): Agree, Phases, and Intervention Effects. In L<strong>in</strong>guistic Analysis 33: 54-96. • Campana, M. (1992):<br />

A Movement Theory of Ergativity, PhD <strong>the</strong>sis, McGill University, Montréal. • Coon, J. (2010): A-Bar Extraction<br />

Asymmetries. Manuscript. McGill University. • Müller. G. (2009): Ergativity, Accusativity, and <strong>the</strong> Order of<br />

Merge and Agree. In K. Grohmann (ed.), Explorations of Phase Theory. Features and Arguments, 269-308. Berl<strong>in</strong>:<br />

Mouton de Gruyter. • Pesetsky, D. (1989): The Earl<strong>in</strong>ess Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Ms. • Pol<strong>in</strong>sky, M., C. Gómez Gallo, P. Graff<br />

& E. Kravtchenko (to appear): ‘Subject Preference and Ergativity’, L<strong>in</strong>gua. • Richards, M. (2011): Deriv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

edge: What’s <strong>in</strong> a phase? Syntax. 14.1, 74-95.


Anke Assmann & Fabian Heck (Leipzig)<br />

Opaque Intervention <strong>in</strong> German Scrambl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Claim: Based on hi<strong>the</strong>rto unnoticed facts from German, we claim that an argument’s capacity to b<strong>in</strong>d a<br />

parasitic gap (PG) or to associate with a float<strong>in</strong>g quantifier (FQ) is not dependent on <strong>the</strong> argument’s surface<br />

position. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> distribution of PGs and FQs is often opaque: (i) There are cases where b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

a PG by an argument is impossible although no co-argument <strong>in</strong>tervenes on <strong>the</strong> surface (counter-feed<strong>in</strong>g);<br />

(ii) and <strong>the</strong>re are cases where a wh-phrase can associate with a FQ although a surface <strong>in</strong>tervener is present<br />

(counter-bleed<strong>in</strong>g). We suggest that opacity arises because <strong>the</strong>re is an earlier derivational stage where (i ′ )<br />

a co-argument b<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> PG and <strong>the</strong>n scrambles to a position where it ceases to <strong>in</strong>tervene on <strong>the</strong> surface;<br />

and where (ii ′ ) <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase occupies a position such that it is <strong>the</strong> closest element to associate with <strong>the</strong><br />

FQ, and later it moves on to a higher position, giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> surface impression to <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>in</strong>tervention.<br />

Observations: (i) An <strong>in</strong>direct object cannot b<strong>in</strong>d a PG by scrambl<strong>in</strong>g if a direct object co-argument has<br />

scrambled, too, not even if <strong>the</strong> co-argument does not <strong>in</strong>tervene on <strong>the</strong> surface between <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct object<br />

and <strong>the</strong> PG (1-a). A direct object can b<strong>in</strong>d a PG even if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct object co-argument <strong>in</strong>tervenes (1-b).<br />

(1) a. *wenn jemand das Buch der Anette2 [ ohne PG2 zu vertrauen ] ausleiht<br />

if someone <strong>the</strong>acc book <strong>the</strong>dat Anette without to trust<br />

“if someone lends Anette <strong>the</strong> book without trust<strong>in</strong>g her”<br />

lends<br />

b. wenn jemand das Buch2 der Anette [ ohne PG2 durchzulesen ] zurückgibt<br />

if someone <strong>the</strong>acc book <strong>the</strong>dat Anette without through-to-read<br />

“if some returns <strong>the</strong> book to Anette without hav<strong>in</strong>g read it”<br />

returns<br />

(ii) A wh-subject cannot associate with <strong>the</strong> FQ alles if an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite object <strong>in</strong>tervenes on <strong>the</strong> surface (2-a).<br />

The same holds for an <strong>in</strong>direct wh-object and an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite direct object (2-b). However, if <strong>the</strong> grammatical<br />

functions of wh-phrase and <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite are reversed, surface <strong>in</strong>tervention is unproblematic (3-a,b).<br />

(2) a. *Wer1 hat e<strong>in</strong>en Koch alles1 bezahlt?<br />

whonom has aacc cook all<br />

“Who all paid a cook?”<br />

paid<br />

b. *Wem1 hat er e<strong>in</strong>en Koch alles1 gezeigt?<br />

whodat has er aacc cook all shown<br />

“To whom all did he show a cook?”<br />

(3) a. Wen1 hat e<strong>in</strong> Koch alles1 beleidigt?<br />

whoacc has a cooknom all<br />

“Who all did a cook <strong>in</strong>sult?”<br />

<strong>in</strong>sulted<br />

b. Was1 hat er e<strong>in</strong>em Koch alles1 geborgt?<br />

whatacc has he adat cook all lent<br />

“What all did he lend to a cook?”<br />

Assumptions: Our analysis is embedded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2001) (thus presuppos<strong>in</strong>g phases,<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir impenetrability, and Agree). We follow Richards (2004) <strong>in</strong> assum<strong>in</strong>g that scrambl<strong>in</strong>g is triggered by<br />

edge features (EFs, Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2007). In a scrambl<strong>in</strong>g language like German, such EFs can be <strong>in</strong>serted (at<br />

least) on v and T. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Müller (2010), we assume that EF-<strong>in</strong>sertion on a head H is only possible as<br />

long as H is active, i.e., H still bears some o<strong>the</strong>r feature that is to trigger some syntactic operation. As<br />

Müller (2011) shows, this leads to <strong>the</strong> Intermediate Step Corollary (ISC), which states that <strong>in</strong>ternal Merge<br />

to SpecX triggered by an EF precedes external Merge (triggered by a selectional feature). Toge<strong>the</strong>r with<br />

<strong>the</strong> Extension Condition (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 1995), this implies that <strong>in</strong>ternal Merge triggered by an EF always<br />

targets an <strong>in</strong>ner SpecX while <strong>the</strong> outermost SpecX is created by external Merge (provided external Merge<br />

applies at all). If EFs are undeletable (see Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2007), it is plausible to assume that <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>serted<br />

on a head H only once per derivation. Once an EF has been <strong>in</strong>serted on H, it attracts all <strong>the</strong> categories<br />

C1, C2, . . ., Cn that are supposed to reach H’s specifier doma<strong>in</strong>. Suppose now that <strong>the</strong> EF first attracts<br />

C1, C2, . . ., Cn <strong>in</strong> a top down fashion, start<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> closest Ci (closeness be<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of<br />

asymmetric c-command). Every time a Ci is attracted, it is placed on a stack. Only after all of C1, C2, . . .,<br />

Cn have been placed on <strong>the</strong> stack, <strong>the</strong>y are subsequently merged <strong>in</strong> H’s specifier doma<strong>in</strong>. Note that Merge<br />

exclusively has access to <strong>the</strong> Ci on top of <strong>the</strong> stack. Once Ci is removed, Ci−1 occupies <strong>the</strong> top and thus<br />

becomes accessible. As a consequence, C1, C2, . . ., Cn are moved <strong>in</strong> parallel: due to <strong>the</strong> first <strong>in</strong> – last out<br />

procedure, <strong>the</strong>y are merged <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse order <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y have been attracted, see also Stroik (2009).<br />

Our assumptions about PGs and FQs are as follows. Adjunct clauses conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g PGs are merged <strong>in</strong> Specv<br />

(above or below <strong>the</strong> subject). PGs must establish Agree with <strong>the</strong>ir b<strong>in</strong>der (see Assmann 2010). Once<br />

an argument has established Agree with a PG, it does not <strong>in</strong>duce any M<strong>in</strong>imal L<strong>in</strong>k Condition effects


(MLC, Fanselow 1991, Cho<strong>ms</strong>k 1995) with respect to o<strong>the</strong>r Agree-relations <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g PGs. FQ alles<br />

must associate with an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite (see Reis 1992). Association <strong>in</strong>volves Agree. Alles is merged <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> TP.<br />

Analysis: In (1-a), <strong>the</strong> direct object is merged as sister of V, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct argument as its specifier. The<br />

adjunct clause (conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> PG) is merged <strong>in</strong> Specv. As long as <strong>the</strong> subject is not merged, v rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

active and an EF can be <strong>in</strong>serted on it. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> assumptions <strong>in</strong> Müller (2010), an EF <strong>in</strong>serted<br />

on H must serve its purpose before o<strong>the</strong>r features of H can be accessed. Therefore both objects are first<br />

attracted by <strong>the</strong> EF to Specv. Movement proceeds <strong>in</strong> parallel (via <strong>the</strong> stack), result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> objects’<br />

relative order der Anette ≻ das Buch. Both c-command <strong>the</strong> PG. But s<strong>in</strong>ce das Buch is closer to <strong>the</strong> PG,<br />

der Anette cannot b<strong>in</strong>d it without violat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> MLC (see also Fanselow 1993). Next, <strong>the</strong> subject is merged<br />

<strong>in</strong> Specv. When T is merged, it is active (due to its Φ-probes) and <strong>the</strong>refore accessible to EF-<strong>in</strong>sertion.<br />

EF on T attracts (aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> parallel) subject and direct object to SpecT, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (1-a). Although, on <strong>the</strong><br />

surface, der Anette is closest to <strong>the</strong> PG, b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g is impossible as <strong>the</strong> PG has already established Agree<br />

with das Buch. By <strong>the</strong> same reason<strong>in</strong>g (1-b) is grammatical. In (2-a), <strong>the</strong> direct object is merged as sister<br />

of V. In order to rema<strong>in</strong> PIC-accessible (to ultimately reach SpecT) it is attracted by an EF to Specv. Due<br />

to <strong>the</strong> ISC, this happens before <strong>the</strong> subject is merged, yield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> order wer ≻ e<strong>in</strong>en Koch with<strong>in</strong> vP.<br />

Next, alles enters <strong>the</strong> TP. S<strong>in</strong>ce T is active (Φ-probes), an EF can be <strong>in</strong>serted. Subject and object are<br />

attracted <strong>in</strong> parallel, conserv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir relative order. As a result, e<strong>in</strong>en Koch ends up closer to alles than<br />

wer. The MLC prevents wer from establish<strong>in</strong>g Agree with alles. Instead, alles enters Agree with <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite, which does not qualify for an associate, presumably due to semantic reasons. This accounts for<br />

<strong>the</strong> ungrammaticality of (2-a). Similar considerations apply to (2-b). In (3-a) <strong>the</strong> direct object is attracted<br />

to Specv (before <strong>the</strong> subject is merged), yield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> order e<strong>in</strong> Koch ≻ wen with<strong>in</strong> vP. After alles is merged<br />

<strong>in</strong> TP and an EF is <strong>in</strong>serted on T, <strong>the</strong> arguments are moved (<strong>in</strong> parallel) to SpecT. As <strong>the</strong>ir relative order<br />

is not altered, wen is closer to alles and establishes Agree with it, <strong>the</strong>reby creat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> association. In<br />

a later step, <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase moves away, giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> superficial impression of be<strong>in</strong>g separated from alles<br />

by a potential <strong>in</strong>tervener. Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> derivation of (3-b) is analog. The analysis also accounts for facts<br />

about German PGs that have been noted elsewhere. Thus, it has been observed that no <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong><br />

PG-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g arises (a) if <strong>the</strong> potential <strong>in</strong>tervener is <strong>the</strong> subject (Fanselow 1993), (b) if it is a pronoun (den<br />

Dikken & Mulder 1991, Fanselow 1993), or (c) if it b<strong>in</strong>ds ano<strong>the</strong>r PG (aga<strong>in</strong> Fanselow 1993).<br />

Consequences: Opacity <strong>in</strong> phonology has traditionally served as an argument for derivational <strong>the</strong>ories<br />

(Kenstowicz & Kisseberth 1979). However, with <strong>the</strong> advent of conta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>the</strong>ory (Pr<strong>in</strong>ce & Smolensky<br />

1993) th<strong>in</strong>gs changed: now it was possible to analyze opacity representationally. Not surpris<strong>in</strong>gly,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stances of counter-feed<strong>in</strong>g and counter-bleed<strong>in</strong>g discussed above can be reanalyzed by mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

reference to traces, too. However, <strong>the</strong>re is a reason why one should refra<strong>in</strong> from do<strong>in</strong>g so. On <strong>the</strong><br />

one hand, Brody (2001) argues that a <strong>the</strong>ory that is <strong>in</strong>herently derivationally to beg<strong>in</strong> with any resort to<br />

representational concepts should be m<strong>in</strong>imized. To <strong>the</strong> extend that this is conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g, opacity effects <strong>in</strong><br />

a derivational syntax should be analyzed without reference to traces/copies, as was proposed above. On<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, it can be argued that streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> representational character of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory as a whole<br />

by deriv<strong>in</strong>g scrambl<strong>in</strong>g via base-generation is ceteris paribus, not able to derive <strong>the</strong> facts about opaque<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of PG-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g and FQ-association discussed above.<br />

Selected references: •Assmann, Anke (2010): Parasitic Gaps <strong>in</strong> Derivational Grammar. Master’s <strong>the</strong>sis, Universität<br />

Leipzig. •Brody, Michael (2001): Some Aspects of Elegant Syntax. Ms., University College London. •Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, Noam<br />

(2001): Derivation by Phase. In: Kenstowicz, ed., Ken Hale. A Life <strong>in</strong> Language. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts,<br />

pp. 1–52. •Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, Noam (2007): Approach<strong>in</strong>g UG from Below. In: Sauerland & Gärtner, eds, Interfaces + Recursion =<br />

Language? Mouton de Gruyter, Berl<strong>in</strong>, pp. 1–30. •Dikken, Marcel den and René Mulder (1991): ‘Double Object Scrambl<strong>in</strong>g’,<br />

MIT Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 14, 67–82. •Fanselow, Gisbert (1993): ‘Die Rückkehr der Basisgenerierer’, Gron<strong>in</strong>ger<br />

Arbeiten zur Germanistischen L<strong>in</strong>guistik 36, 1–74. •Fanselow, Gisbert (2001): ‘Features, θ-Roles, and Free Constituent Order’,<br />

L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 32, 405–437. •Müller, Gereon (2010): ‘On Deriv<strong>in</strong>g CED Effects from <strong>the</strong> PIC’, L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 41, 35–<br />

82. •Müller, Gereon (2011): Constra<strong>in</strong>ts on Displacement. Benjam<strong>in</strong>s, A<strong>ms</strong>terdam. •Reis, Marga (1992): The Category of<br />

Invariant alles <strong>in</strong> Wh-Clauses. In: Tracy, ed., Who Climbs <strong>the</strong> Grammar Tree? Niemeyer, Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen, pp. 465–492. •Richards,<br />

Marc (2004): Object Shift and Scrambl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> North and West Germanic: A Case Study <strong>in</strong> Symmetrical Syntax. PhD <strong>the</strong>sis,<br />

University of Cambridge. •Stroik, Thomas (2009): Locality <strong>in</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imalist Syntax. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.


Rebekah Bagl<strong>in</strong>i (Chicago)<br />

Reduced clausal structure <strong>in</strong> comparatives: evidence from Wolof<br />

(Keywords: syntax, phrasal comparatives, clausal comparatives, subject/non-subject asymmetry)<br />

Introduction: A central topic <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study of comparative constructions cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically is <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

complexity of <strong>the</strong> standard constituent: whe<strong>the</strong>r a simple nom<strong>in</strong>al standard is base generated as a phrase or<br />

derived from a full clause. Clausal standards are assumed to be typologically rarer and restricted to certa<strong>in</strong><br />

grammatical strategies. Although underly<strong>in</strong>g clausal structure has been demonstrated <strong>in</strong> particle comparatives<br />

<strong>in</strong> English, German (Lechner 2001), and Greek (Merchant 2009), Stassen (1985) clai<strong>ms</strong> that exceed<br />

comparatives (a cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically widespread strategy <strong>in</strong> which comparison is expressed via a transitive<br />

verb mean<strong>in</strong>g ‘exceed’) are categorically restricted to phrasal standards.<br />

This paper represents <strong>the</strong> first formal challenge to Stassen’s prediction, and draws on novel evidence<br />

from Wolof to demonstrate that some exceed comparatives must <strong>in</strong>volve underly<strong>in</strong>g clausal structure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

standard.<br />

Evidence: The expression of unequal quality comparison <strong>in</strong> Wolof <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> comparative ma<strong>in</strong> verb<br />

gen-a, ‘exceed’ or ‘surpass’, comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g with a gradable predicate (GP) (1):<br />

(1) Mu-a gën-a-gatt B<strong>in</strong>ta.<br />

3sg-clf surpass-short B<strong>in</strong>ta.<br />

‘S/he is shorter than B<strong>in</strong>ta.’<br />

Stassen’s (1985) classification of gen-a as a phrasal exceed comparative <strong>in</strong>itially see<strong>ms</strong> plausible: no prepositions<br />

or special morphology <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> standard <strong>in</strong> (1) and <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al follow<strong>in</strong>g gen-a+GP appears<br />

to be a simple <strong>in</strong>dividual denot<strong>in</strong>g-expression, a DP. Thus, <strong>the</strong> surface structure of a Wolof comparative<br />

construction like (1) see<strong>ms</strong> consistent with a phrasal analysis, <strong>in</strong> which both <strong>the</strong> target and standard are<br />

arguments of <strong>the</strong> transitive gen-a+GP compound verb.<br />

I argue, however, that <strong>the</strong> apparent surface simplicity of comparative sentences like (1) is mislead<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

First, it is crucial to note that <strong>the</strong> target is obligatorily clefted <strong>in</strong> Wolof comparatives. This is curious<br />

as cleft<strong>in</strong>g is not widespread <strong>in</strong> Wolof, but restricted to <strong>the</strong> expression of focus and <strong>the</strong> formation of whquestions<br />

(Torrence 2005). Clefted arguments with<strong>in</strong> an embedded clause receive no special mark<strong>in</strong>g, but<br />

cleft<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> matrix clause is <strong>in</strong>dicated by dist<strong>in</strong>ctive morphology. The attachment site of <strong>the</strong> copular<br />

cleft marker -a- dist<strong>in</strong>guishes subject cleft (SC) sentences like (1)-(2) from non-subject cleft (NSC) sentences<br />

like (3): -a- follows a subject (pro)nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong> SC, and an expletive l- <strong>in</strong> NSC.<br />

(2) subject cleft<br />

Ma-a gën-a-bëgg djënn (*ci) B<strong>in</strong>ta.<br />

1sg-clf surpass-like fish (*ci) B<strong>in</strong>ta.<br />

‘I like fish more than B<strong>in</strong>ta (does).’<br />

(3) non-subject cleft<br />

G<strong>in</strong>aar l-a-a gën-a-bëgg ci djënn.<br />

Chicken l-clf -1sg surpass-like ci fish<br />

‘I like chicken more than fish.’<br />

Besides <strong>the</strong> different morphological mark<strong>in</strong>g of SC and NSC comparative constructions, <strong>the</strong>re is a crucial<br />

asymmetry exhibited by (2) and (3): <strong>the</strong> standard of comparison may be <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>the</strong> word ci <strong>in</strong> NSC<br />

constructions, but not <strong>in</strong> SC constructions. Ci most commonly occurs as a locative preposition <strong>in</strong> Wolof,<br />

but it is also known to function as a (prepositional) complementizer <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a CP (Torrence 2005), as<br />

illustrated <strong>in</strong> (4)-(5):<br />

(4) Da-ma soon ci tóx póón<br />

do-1sg tired c smoke tobacco<br />

‘I’m tired of smok<strong>in</strong>g tobacco.’<br />

(5) Da-ma dogu ci jënd-kó.<br />

do-1sg decide c buy-3s.<br />

‘I decided to buy it.’<br />

If ci <strong>in</strong> sentences (2) and (3) were a simple preposition, <strong>the</strong>re would be no obvious explanation for <strong>the</strong><br />

contrast <strong>in</strong> grammaticality. I argue <strong>in</strong>stead that ci is a prepositional complementizer <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se sentences.<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Merchant (2009)’s analysis of Greek reduced clausal comparatives, I propose that <strong>the</strong> standard<br />

<strong>in</strong> both SC and NSC comparatives <strong>in</strong> Wolof is generated with<strong>in</strong> a full clause and clefted to clause-<strong>in</strong>itial<br />

1


position, trigger<strong>in</strong>g clausal ellipsis. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> standard account of cleft<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Wolof, clefted subjects<br />

move to SpecTP, non-subjects to SpecCP (Torrence 2005). Thus, <strong>the</strong> observed asymmetry between (2)-(3)<br />

with <strong>the</strong> complementizer ci is entirely predicted: while <strong>the</strong> standard <strong>in</strong> both (2) and (3) is generated <strong>in</strong>side<br />

a clause, only <strong>the</strong> latter projects a full CP structure and thus co-occurs with ci.<br />

(2’) sc standard (3’) nsc standard<br />

TP<br />

PP<br />

B<strong>in</strong>tai<br />

T vP<br />

ti<br />

bëgg<br />

likes<br />

v’<br />

djënn<br />

fish<br />

ci CP<br />

djënnk<br />

fish C TP<br />

tk<br />

T vP<br />

1sg v’<br />

Besides expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> asymmetry observed <strong>in</strong> (2)-(3), an additional positive consequence of <strong>the</strong> clausal<br />

analysis proposed here is that it accounts for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise mysterious cleft<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> target <strong>in</strong> Wolof comparatives.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to my analysis, Wolof comparatives embed a full-fledged clausal doma<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong><br />

standard undergoes movement to a clause-<strong>in</strong>itial position, just as has been proposed for clausal comparative<br />

constructions <strong>in</strong> English, German, Greek, and o<strong>the</strong>r languages. The cleft<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> target is thus readily<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>ed as obligatory parallel movement to license ellipsis under identity with <strong>the</strong> standard. The trees <strong>in</strong><br />

(2’) and (3’) illustrate <strong>the</strong> proposed underly<strong>in</strong>g clausal structure for <strong>the</strong> standard <strong>in</strong> sentences (2)-(3).<br />

Conclusion: This paper shows that <strong>the</strong> Wolof gen-a construction is a clausal comparative, <strong>in</strong> which both<br />

target and standard are moved to a clause peripheral position to license ellipsis. This f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g has significant<br />

implications for <strong>the</strong> study of comparatives cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically, <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that clausal comparatives are not<br />

as typologically rare as is often assumed, nor <strong>in</strong>compatible with exceed strategies of comparison.<br />

References<br />

Lechner, W. 2001. Reduced and phrasal comparatives. Natural Language & L<strong>in</strong>guistic Theory 19:683–735.<br />

Merchant, J. 2009. Phrasal and clausal comparatives <strong>in</strong> Greek and <strong>the</strong>abstractnessofsyntax. Journal of<br />

Greek <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 9:134–164.<br />

Stassen, L. 1985. Comparison and universal grammar. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.<br />

Torrence, W.H. 2005. On <strong>the</strong> Distribution of Complementizers <strong>in</strong> Wolof. Doctoral Dissertation, UCLA.<br />

2<br />

bëgg<br />

like<br />

tk


Stefan Baumann (Köln)<br />

Types of Secondary Prosodic Prom<strong>in</strong>ence and <strong>the</strong>ir Relation to Information<br />

Structure<br />

A l<strong>in</strong>guistic element is prosodically prom<strong>in</strong>ent if it stands out from its neighbour<strong>in</strong>g<br />

elements by virtue of its suprasegmental properties. The prosodic differences between<br />

<strong>the</strong> elements can vary considerably, though. Thus, prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence is both gradual<br />

and relational <strong>in</strong> nature. These characteristics lead to proble<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> annotation of<br />

naturally spoken language, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> annotator is forced to classify <strong>in</strong>tonational events<br />

as categories.<br />

In order to circumvent this general problem of gradience/relativity versus categoriality,<br />

several types of 'secondary' prom<strong>in</strong>ences have been proposed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature, e.g.<br />

duration accent (Kohler 2005), secondary accent (Chafe 1994), ornamental accent<br />

(Bür<strong>in</strong>g 2007), subord<strong>in</strong>ate/secondary nucleus (Crystal 1969), or phrase accent (Grice et<br />

al. 2000). However, <strong>the</strong> various concepts refer to quite different phenomena or levels,<br />

namely<br />

(a) presence or absence of a pitch movement, i.e. tonal vs. non-­‐tonal prom<strong>in</strong>ence<br />

(b) accent type, i.e. <strong>the</strong> form of a pitch movement on a metrically strong syllable<br />

(c) accent position or <strong>the</strong> status of a prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> prosodic hierarchy<br />

The current paper presents experimental <strong>in</strong>vestigations on <strong>the</strong>se three types of<br />

secondary prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ences and <strong>the</strong>ir relation to various aspects of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

structure. First, <strong>in</strong> several acoustic and articulatory production studies on Second<br />

Occurrence Focus (SOF), i.e. words which are both focussed and contextually given, it<br />

could be shown that SOF ite<strong>ms</strong> receive an <strong>in</strong>termediate degree of prom<strong>in</strong>ence (e.g. Féry<br />

& Ishihara (2009) and Baumann et al. (2010) for German) which is not triggered by<br />

tonal movement but by <strong>in</strong>creased duration and <strong>in</strong>tensity (compared to background<br />

elements). The same pattern can be observed <strong>in</strong> some cases of bridg<strong>in</strong>g or 'implicit<br />

<strong>in</strong>ferrability' (Partee 1999), which do not display segmental copies of first occurrence<br />

expressions (cf. Riester & Baumann 2011).<br />

Second, a number of production studies confirmed that different accent types are<br />

related to different degrees of (perceived) givenness or <strong>in</strong>formation status of discourse<br />

referents (Pierrehumbert & Hirschberg 1990, Baumann & Grice 2006). Latest results of<br />

a perception study on German (Röhr & Baumann 2011) revealed a stepwise decrease <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> degree of perceived givenness from deaccentuation and prenuclear accents through<br />

low and early peak nuclear accents to high and ris<strong>in</strong>g nuclear accents. Fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence<br />

for <strong>the</strong> relevance of different accent types <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of an item's <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

status comes from a neurol<strong>in</strong>guistic perception study on <strong>the</strong> prosody of <strong>in</strong>ferentially<br />

accessible referents (Schumacher & Baumann 2010): Three different accent types on a<br />

meronymic expression revealed significant differences <strong>in</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g effort<br />

(deaccentuation > H* > H+L*) <strong>in</strong>dicated by variations <strong>in</strong> event-­‐related bra<strong>in</strong> potentials<br />

(<strong>in</strong> particular N400). Crucially, <strong>the</strong> 'secondarily prom<strong>in</strong>ent' accent type H+L* proved to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> most appropriate marker of <strong>the</strong> 'secondarily given' referent.<br />

Third, <strong>the</strong> syntagmatic relation between prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ences <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

perceived strength degree. In a recent perception study on German (Jagdfeld &<br />

Baumann 2011) subjects clearly dist<strong>in</strong>guished between strongly accented and<br />

unaccented words <strong>in</strong> two different positions with<strong>in</strong> an utterance. However, an order<br />

effect was found for weak pitch accents, which were not perceived as accents <strong>in</strong><br />

prenuclear but <strong>in</strong> nuclear position. In general, listeners proved to be less sensitive to<br />

categorical prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgements <strong>in</strong> prenuclear position (also reflected <strong>in</strong> longer


eaction times) than <strong>in</strong> nuclear position, which <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> special functional status of<br />

nuclear accents.<br />

The <strong>in</strong>sights of <strong>the</strong>se studies lead to <strong>the</strong> proposal of a model of prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> three levels discussed (see (1)). The model ai<strong>ms</strong> at be<strong>in</strong>g 'truly<br />

autosegmental-­‐metrical' <strong>in</strong> that it does not equate prom<strong>in</strong>ence with pitch movement but<br />

that it also takes non-­‐tonal criteria such as duration and <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>in</strong>to account. It<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>rmore considers <strong>the</strong> relative position of prom<strong>in</strong>ences with<strong>in</strong> an utterance.<br />

(1) + phonological prom<strong>in</strong>ence -­‐<br />

References<br />

nuclear non-­‐nuclear<br />

prenuclear postnuclear<br />

metrical level<br />

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐<br />

pitch accents non-­‐tonal prom<strong>in</strong>ences tonal level<br />

high ... low duration accent, phrase accent<br />

ris<strong>in</strong>g ... fall<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Baumann, Stefan & Mart<strong>in</strong>e Grice (2006). The Intonation of Accessibility. Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10).<br />

1636-­‐1657.<br />

Baumann, Stefan, Doris Mücke & Johannes Becker (2010). Expression of Second Occurrence Focus <strong>in</strong><br />

German. L<strong>in</strong>guistische Berichte 221. 61-­‐78.<br />

Bür<strong>in</strong>g, D. (2007). Intonation, Semantics and Information Structure. In: Ramchand, G. Reiss, C. (Eds.), The<br />

Oxford Handbook of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Interfaces.<br />

Chafe, W. (1994). Discourse, Consciousness, and Time. University of Chicago Press, Chicago/London.<br />

Crystal, D. (1969). Prosodic Syste<strong>ms</strong> and Intonation <strong>in</strong> English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Féry, C. & Ishihara, S. (2009). The phonology of second occurrence focus. Journal of <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 45, 285–<br />

313.<br />

Grice, M., Ladd, D.R., Arvaniti, A., (2000). On <strong>the</strong> Place of Phrase Accents <strong>in</strong> Intonational Phonology.<br />

Phonology 17 (2), 143-­‐185.<br />

Jagdfeld, Nils & Stefan Baumann (2011). Order Effects on <strong>the</strong> Perception of Relative Prom<strong>in</strong>ence.<br />

Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs 17th ICPhS, Hongkong, Ch<strong>in</strong>a. 958-­‐961.<br />

Kohler, K.J. (2005). Form and Function of Non-­‐Pitch Accents. AIPUK 35a. Prosodic Patterns of German<br />

Spontaneous Speech. 97-­‐123.<br />

Partee, B. (1999). Focus, Quantification, and Semantics-­‐Pragmatics Issues. In: P. Bosch & F. van der Sandt<br />

(eds.), Focus: L<strong>in</strong>guistic, Cognitive, and Computational Perspectives (Studies <strong>in</strong> Natural Language<br />

Process<strong>in</strong>g), Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Pierrehumbert, J.B. & Hirschberg, J. (1990). The Mean<strong>in</strong>g of Intonational Contours <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Interpretation of<br />

Discourse. In: P.R. Cohen, J. Morgan, M.E. Pollack, (eds.), Intentions <strong>in</strong> Communication. Cambridge: MIT<br />

Press. 271-­‐311.<br />

Riester, Arndt & Stefan Baumann (2011). Information Structure Annotation and Secondary Accents. In:<br />

Dipper, Stefanie & Heike Z<strong>in</strong>smeister (eds.): Beyond Semantics: Corpus-­‐based Investigations of Pragmatic<br />

and Discourse Phenomena. Bochumer L<strong>in</strong>guistische Arbeitsberichte 3. 111-­‐127.<br />

Röhr, Christ<strong>in</strong>e & Stefan Baumann (2011). Decod<strong>in</strong>g Information Status by Type and Position of Accent <strong>in</strong><br />

German. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs 17th ICPhS, Hongkong, Ch<strong>in</strong>a. 1706-­‐1709.<br />

Schumacher, Petra & Stefan Baumann (2010). Pitch accent type affects <strong>the</strong> N400 dur<strong>in</strong>g referential<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g. NeuroReport 21 (9). 618-­‐622.


Krist<strong>in</strong>e Bentzen (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø/CASTL) & Merete Anderssen (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø)<br />

Discourse effects on <strong>the</strong> availability of Object Shift<br />

In Norwegian, like <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r Ma<strong>in</strong>land Scand<strong>in</strong>avian language, weak/unstressed pronom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

objects typically undergo Object Shift (OS) across negation, while full DP objects rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> situ:<br />

(1) a. Jeg fant {*huset} ikke {huset}. b. Jeg fant {det} ikke {*det}.<br />

I found house.<strong>the</strong> not house.<strong>the</strong> I found it not it<br />

‘I didn’t f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> house.’ ‘I didn’t f<strong>in</strong>d it.’<br />

However, as shown by Andréasson (2008) and Anderssen et al. (to appear), <strong>the</strong> pronom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

object det ‘it’ has special properties with respect to OS. When this pronoun, which is <strong>the</strong> neuter<br />

form of <strong>the</strong> third person s<strong>in</strong>gular personal pronoun, refers back to an identifiable noun <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

neuter gender, it undergoes OS, as <strong>in</strong> (1). However, det ‘it’ may also have a clausal or VP<br />

referent, or a DP referent with a type <strong>in</strong>terpretation (cf. Houser et al. 2007, Josefsson 2010,<br />

Bor<strong>the</strong>n 2003, Lødrup to appear), and <strong>in</strong> such contexts, it resists OS, despite be<strong>in</strong>g unstressed:<br />

(2) A: Har hun gått hjem? B: Jeg tror {*det CLAUSE} ikke {det CLAUSE}.<br />

has she gone home I th<strong>in</strong>k it. NEUT not it. NEUT<br />

‘Has she gone home?’ ‘I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k so.’ (det = ‘that she has gone home’)<br />

(3) A: Spiste du noe frukt? B: Nei, jeg gjorde {*det VP} ikke {det VP}.<br />

ate you any fruit. MASC no I did it. NEUT not it. NEUT<br />

‘Did you eat any fruit?’ ‘No, I didn’t.’ (det = ‘eat any fruit’)<br />

(4) A: Hva med fisk til middag? B: Nei, Per spiser {#det} ikke {det}.<br />

what with fish. MASC to d<strong>in</strong>ner no Per eats it. NEUT not it. NEUT<br />

‘How about fish for d<strong>in</strong>ner?’ ‘No, Per doesn’t eat that.’ (det=fish as a type of food)<br />

Influenced by Andréasson (2008), Anderssen et al. (to appear) propose an analysis of OS <strong>in</strong><br />

ter<strong>ms</strong> of IP-<strong>in</strong>ternal topicalization, and fur<strong>the</strong>rmore argue that such topicalization only applies to<br />

pronom<strong>in</strong>al objects with an <strong>in</strong>dividuated referent, as <strong>in</strong> (1), while objects with a non-<strong>in</strong>dividuated<br />

referent, such as those <strong>in</strong> (2)-(4) refra<strong>in</strong> from OS. We adopt this approach and develop it fur<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

1. Type of topichood matters<br />

First of all, we connect <strong>the</strong> availability of OS with pronom<strong>in</strong>al det ‘it’ to what type of topic this<br />

pronoun constitutes. We argue that det ‘it’ <strong>in</strong> (1) has <strong>the</strong> typical characteristics of familiar topics<br />

(Frascarelli 2007, Frascarelli & H<strong>in</strong>terhölzl 2007); it is distressed, <strong>in</strong>formationally given, and dl<strong>in</strong>ked<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that it has an accessible referent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discourse. In contrast, det ‘it’ <strong>in</strong> (2)-(4)<br />

refers to what <strong>the</strong> sentence is about, and is hence analysed as an aboutness topic. We thus<br />

propose that OS only applies to familiar topics <strong>in</strong> Norwegian, while aboutness topics typically<br />

rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> situ. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, although <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>in</strong> (2)-(4) out of context is <strong>the</strong> default word<br />

order when det ‘it’ has a non-<strong>in</strong>dividuated reference, <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> discourse situations OS of even<br />

such <strong>in</strong>stances of det is preferred. The follow<strong>in</strong>g dialogue between speakers ‘Karmøy03_gm’ and<br />

‘Karmøy04_gk’ is taken from spontaneous speech <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nordic Dialect Corpus 1 :<br />

(5) Discourse topic: The problem of tourists hik<strong>in</strong>g on foot <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ski tracks:<br />

Karmøy03_gm: Men problemet var at når da alle fotturistene kom så fant jo ut de at det var<br />

f<strong>in</strong>est å gå i skisporene for da slapp de å vasse.<br />

‘But <strong>the</strong> problem was that when all <strong>the</strong> hik<strong>in</strong>g tourists came, <strong>the</strong>y found out<br />

that it was best to walk <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ski track ‘cause <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y didn’t have to walk<br />

through snow.’<br />

1<br />

http://www.tekstlab.uio.no/nota/scandiasyn/Search_Facilities.html, cf. Johannessen, Priestley,<br />

Hagen, Åfarli & Vangsnes 2009.


Karmøy04_gk: mm. Var akkurat det så skjedde nå i Bjørgene og sant # at # så alle for og<br />

trødde og så # ødela de.<br />

‘Right. Exactly what happened now <strong>in</strong> Bjørgene, right, # that #, so everyone<br />

stepped around and messed it up’<br />

Karmøy03_gm: mm. Ja # for der er jo ikke kultur her veit du for… Så de skjønner det ikke.<br />

‘Right. Yes # ‘cause <strong>the</strong>re <strong>the</strong>y have no tradition for… So <strong>the</strong>y don’t get it.’<br />

[det = that <strong>the</strong>y shouldn’t hike on foot <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ski tracks]<br />

In this dialogue, we see that <strong>in</strong> ‘Karmøy03_gm’s f<strong>in</strong>al utterance, he uses <strong>the</strong> pronoun det ‘it’ to<br />

refer to a whole clause. However, <strong>in</strong> contrast to (2), it is here perfectly natural to place this<br />

pronoun <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> OS position. We argue that <strong>the</strong> reason for this is that <strong>the</strong> pronoun here refers to <strong>the</strong><br />

topic of <strong>the</strong> whole discourse. Hence it functions as a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g topic. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Frascarelli &<br />

H<strong>in</strong>terhölzl (2007), cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g topics syntactically/phonologically behave like familiar topics.<br />

Thus, it is expected that it will undergo OS. We <strong>the</strong>refore propose that OS applies to pronom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

objects that constitute ei<strong>the</strong>r familiar or cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g topics, but not to aboutness topics.<br />

2. Parallels between ±OS and it vs. that <strong>in</strong> English<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Gundel et al. (1993) it and that differ <strong>in</strong> cognitive status, it be<strong>in</strong>g IN FOCUS (i.e.<br />

topic) and that be<strong>in</strong>g merely ACTIVATED. Andréasson (2008) has argued that OS <strong>in</strong> Swedish and<br />

Danish applies to IN FOCUS elements. We adopt that proposal, and argue IN FOCUS elements are <strong>in</strong><br />

fact familiar topics. Moreover, compar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> distribution of it and that <strong>in</strong> English (to <strong>the</strong><br />

distribution of shifted and non-shifted det ‘it’ <strong>in</strong> Norwegian, we demonstrate <strong>the</strong>re is a strik<strong>in</strong>g<br />

correlation between: In contexts where det ‘it’ typically does not undergo OS <strong>in</strong> Norwegian,<br />

Enlgish uses that. In contrast, when det ‘it’ <strong>in</strong> Norwegian undergoes OS, this corresponds to <strong>the</strong><br />

use of it <strong>in</strong> English. Two examples are provided here:<br />

(6) a. John liker å svømme. Maria liker ikke det. b. John liker å svømme. Maria liker det ikke.<br />

John likes to swim Maria likes not it John likes to swim Maria likes it not<br />

‘John likes swimm<strong>in</strong>g. Maria doesn’t like that.’ ‘John likes swimm<strong>in</strong>g. Maria doesn’t like it.’<br />

(det/that = ‘that John likes swimm<strong>in</strong>g’) (det/it = ‘swimm<strong>in</strong>g’)<br />

(7) John gikk til jobben. Maria forventet ikke det 1 . Susanne forventet det 2 heller ikke.<br />

John walked to work.<strong>the</strong> Maria expected not it Susanne expected it ei<strong>the</strong>r not<br />

‘John walked to work. Maria didn’t expect that. Susanne didn’t expect it ei<strong>the</strong>r.’<br />

(both det/that/it = ‘that John walked to work’)<br />

In both <strong>the</strong>se examples, we argue that <strong>the</strong> shifted det and English it are cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g topics,<br />

whereas <strong>the</strong> non-shifted det and English that are aboutness topics. This correlation <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

provides support for our proposal that OS applies to both familiar and cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g topics.<br />

Selected references:<br />

Anderssen et al. To appear. The acquisition of Norwegian Object Shift. Language Acquisition.<br />

Andréasson 2008. Not all objects are born alike. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> LFG08 Conference. Bor<strong>the</strong>n<br />

2003. Norwegian Bare S<strong>in</strong>gulars. Ph.D. <strong>the</strong>sis, NTNU. Frascarelli 2007. Subjects, topics and <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of referential pro. NLLT 25. Frascarelli & H<strong>in</strong>terhölzl 2007. Types of topics <strong>in</strong> German<br />

and Italian. In On Information Structure, Mean<strong>in</strong>g and Form. Gundel, Hedberg & Zacharski. 1993.<br />

Cognitive status and <strong>the</strong> form of referr<strong>in</strong>g expressions <strong>in</strong> discourse. Language. Houser, Mikkelsen &<br />

Toosarvandani 2007. Verb phrase pronom<strong>in</strong>alization <strong>in</strong> Danish: Deep or surface anaphora? Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Thirty-Fourth Western Conference on <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>. Josefsson 2010. “Disagree<strong>in</strong>g” pronom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

reference <strong>in</strong> Swedish and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay between formal and semantic gender. L<strong>in</strong>gua 120. Lødrup to<br />

appear. Are Norwegian ‘type anaphora’ really surface anaphora? Journal of Germanic <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>.


Valent<strong>in</strong>a Bianchi (Siena) & Mara Frascarelli (Roma III)<br />

ON HOW TO BE ROOTED IN A CONTEXT<br />

1. Introduction. The impact of <strong>in</strong>formation-structural categories on <strong>the</strong> formal properties of<br />

<strong>the</strong> sentence has led some authors to assume dedicated discourse/contextual projections <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

C-doma<strong>in</strong> (Rizzi 1997 and related work). However, this conflicts with a strongly modular<br />

view accord<strong>in</strong>g to which only features that are truth-conditionally relevant, but not purely<br />

contextual features, belong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic computation (Horvath 2010, Fanselow–Lenertova<br />

2010). The arguments are often focussed on a s<strong>in</strong>gle phenomenon; we contend <strong>in</strong>stead that an<br />

approach compar<strong>in</strong>g different phenomena allows a more comprehensive view of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay<br />

between syntax and context. This will be shown by consider<strong>in</strong>g a set of ‘root phenomena’<br />

which can apply <strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct types of embedded clauses, requir<strong>in</strong>g a f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir distributional properties. Our discussion will focus exclusively on declarative clauses.<br />

2. Data. We show that it is necessary to dist<strong>in</strong>guish at least two types of ‘root phenomena’:<br />

– Type I phenomena occur <strong>in</strong> clauses embedded under bridge verb (e.g. <strong>the</strong> question tag <strong>in</strong><br />

(1)), and <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>terpretation does not <strong>in</strong>teract with elements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> matrix clause: (a) In Italian,<br />

a fronted focus cannot associate with a matrix clause negation (2); (b) In English, a Left<br />

Dislocated QP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> embedded clause does not scopally <strong>in</strong>teract with a matrix QP (3):<br />

(1) I {th<strong>in</strong>k/?*am glad} you like it, don’t you?<br />

(2) ?* Leo non ha detto che [DI SARA] è <strong>in</strong>namorato.<br />

Leo NEG has said that WITH SARA (he) is <strong>in</strong>-love<br />

(3) ? Every student tells me that one exam, I can prepare it <strong>in</strong> two weeks (*∀>∃)<br />

– Type II phenomena (German V2, English Topicalization) also occur <strong>in</strong> clauses embedded<br />

under non-bridge verbs (4), and <strong>the</strong>y do not require an <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong><br />

embedded clause w.r.t. <strong>the</strong> matrix clause: cp. (5) to (2) and (6) to (3):<br />

(4) I am glad that this unreward<strong>in</strong>g job, she has f<strong>in</strong>ally decided to give up.<br />

(5) (?) Hans glaubt NICHT, Peter hat GEWONNEN... (Truckenbrodt 2006, (67))<br />

Hans believes not, Peter has won...<br />

(6) a. Jeder me<strong>in</strong>er Kollegen me<strong>in</strong>te auf e<strong>in</strong> Examen kann ich mich <strong>in</strong>nerhalb von 2 Wochen<br />

vorbereiten. b. Every student tells me that one exam, I can prepare <strong>in</strong> two weeks ( √ ∀>∃)<br />

Draw<strong>in</strong>g a first dist<strong>in</strong>ction, type I phenomena occur <strong>in</strong> discourse active embedded clauses (<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> sense of Dayal–Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw 2009): <strong>the</strong> proposition expressed bears a non-vacuous update<br />

potential w.r.t. <strong>the</strong> discourse context, because <strong>the</strong> modal base <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>the</strong> matrix verb<br />

is not realistic. Type II phenomena also occur <strong>in</strong> embedded clauses whose update potential<br />

gets ‘absorbed’ <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> derived context <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>the</strong> matrix attitude verb (Gärtner 2002,<br />

Truckenbrodt 2006; cf. also Krifka 2011, §3.6), with no impact on <strong>the</strong> discourse context. Our<br />

conclusion is that root phenomena are not a unitary class; <strong>the</strong> debate about whe<strong>the</strong>r or not<br />

‘assertive potential’ is a necessary condition for root phenomena (Bentzen et al. 2007) is due<br />

to <strong>the</strong> failure to dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>the</strong> two subclasses.<br />

3. Analysis. Step 1: How to characterize <strong>the</strong> two types of root-like embedded clause?<br />

In Stalnaker/Heim update semantics, <strong>the</strong> Context Change Potential (CCP) of an assertion<br />

updates <strong>the</strong> set of shared beliefs of <strong>the</strong> conversational community (common ground), while <strong>in</strong><br />

Gunlogson (2003) it updates <strong>the</strong> set of public commitments of a s<strong>in</strong>gle participant. Farkas–<br />

Bruce (2010) propose a componential view of <strong>the</strong> context which subsumes both <strong>the</strong>se aspects:<br />

an assertion has <strong>the</strong> effect of updat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> speaker’s commitment set and also of project<strong>in</strong>g an<br />

updated common ground. Suppose, however, that <strong>the</strong>se two updates can be separated; we <strong>the</strong>n<br />

have <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g parameters w.r.t. CCP: (i) <strong>in</strong>dividual commitment / (proposed) shared<br />

commitment; (ii) discourse context / derived context <strong>in</strong>troduced by a matrix attitude verb.We


assume that derived contexts do not comprise a shared common ground, but only <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

commitment sets (cf. Truckenbrodt 2006, 281). We obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g comb<strong>in</strong>ations:<br />

1. Simple assertion 2. Non-discourse- 3. Discourse-active<br />

active subord<strong>in</strong>ate subord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

discourse derived discourse derived discourse derived<br />

context context context context context context<br />

Individual commitment + (nil) - + - +<br />

Shared commitment + (nil) - (nil) + (nil)<br />

This view of discourse-active subord<strong>in</strong>ates agrees with Dayal–Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw’s claim that <strong>the</strong><br />

speaker does not commit herself to <strong>the</strong> truth of <strong>the</strong> proposition expressed by <strong>the</strong> subord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

(pace Hooper–Thompson 1973), yet <strong>the</strong> latter has a proper CCP w.r.t. <strong>the</strong> discourse context.<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r ter<strong>ms</strong>, <strong>the</strong> speaker places <strong>the</strong> embedded proposition ‘on <strong>the</strong> table’ as a potential<br />

relevant update of <strong>the</strong> shared common ground, without tak<strong>in</strong>g responsibility for its truth.<br />

Step 2: The permissible contexts for root phenomena depend on <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>terpretive impact.<br />

– Type I phenomena are l<strong>in</strong>ked to <strong>the</strong> conversational dynamics. Specifically, we show that:<br />

a) Question tags implement a request for <strong>the</strong> addressee to confirm <strong>the</strong> relevant proposition;<br />

b) Italian focus front<strong>in</strong>g implements a correction (partial reversal of a previous assertion);<br />

c) English LD implements a topic shift, steer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conversation toward a new topic.<br />

These conversational moves update <strong>the</strong> shared commitments of <strong>the</strong> conversational<br />

community: this is why type I phenomena are only allowed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first and third clause type.<br />

– Type II phenomena, <strong>in</strong>stead, have no impact on <strong>the</strong> conversational dynamics, but <strong>the</strong>y at<br />

most implement <strong>the</strong> structur<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>formation with<strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle assertion: hence, <strong>the</strong>y only<br />

require <strong>the</strong> presence of an <strong>in</strong>dividual commitment set, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discourse context or <strong>in</strong> a<br />

derived context. This is why <strong>the</strong>y are licensed <strong>in</strong> all three clause types.<br />

– Type I phenomena are only licensed if <strong>the</strong> proposition expressed by <strong>the</strong> embedded clause<br />

has autonomous CCP w.r.t. <strong>the</strong> matrix clause: this is why <strong>the</strong>re cannot be any scopal<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction (or association with focus) between a matrix element and an element <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> embedded clause (cf. (2)-(3)), contrary to type II phenomena (cf. (5)-(7)).<br />

4. Consequences. The data <strong>in</strong> (2)-(3) show that <strong>the</strong> discourse active status of <strong>the</strong> subord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

clause rules out a syntactically and semantically permissible relation between a matrix and an<br />

embedded element. The two compet<strong>in</strong>g views of <strong>the</strong> syntax–context <strong>in</strong>terface <strong>the</strong>n reduce to<br />

<strong>the</strong> opposition between failure–proof grammar vs. «free generation + filter<strong>in</strong>g» (Boeckx 2010,<br />

a.o.). If syntax and semantics are bl<strong>in</strong>d to <strong>the</strong> discourse active status of <strong>the</strong> embedded clause,<br />

(2)-(3) must be filtered out at <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terface with <strong>the</strong> context. (CP-extraposition (Me<strong>in</strong>unger<br />

2004) may account for (2)-(3), but, if it is <strong>in</strong>terface-driven, it still requires reference set<br />

computation and filter<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> non-<strong>in</strong>terface-comply<strong>in</strong>g outputs.) If <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>the</strong> syntax<br />

encodes <strong>the</strong> CCP status of a clause <strong>in</strong> its C head, <strong>the</strong> relevant scope <strong>in</strong>teractions will be<br />

blocked <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> course of <strong>the</strong> derivation. We believe that, by considerations of computational<br />

efficiency, failure-proof computation should be regarded as <strong>the</strong> null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis.<br />

[1] Bentzen et al 2007. Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> Scand<strong>in</strong>avian Syntax 79, 93–118. [2] Boeckx<br />

2010. In Putnam (ed.), Explor<strong>in</strong>g Crash-Proof Grammars, 105–124. Benjam<strong>in</strong>s. [3] Dayal–<br />

Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw 2009. Subord<strong>in</strong>ation at <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terface. Ms., Rutgers Univ. [4] Fanselow–Lenertova<br />

2011. NLLT 29, 169-209. [5] Farkas–Bruce 2010. J. Semantics 27, 81–118. [6] Gärtner 2002.<br />

Theoretical <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 28, 33–42. [7] Gunlogson 2003. True to Form. Routledge. [7] Horvath<br />

2010. L<strong>in</strong>gua 120, 1346–1369. [8] Hooper–Thompson 1973. LI 4, 465–497. [9] Krifka 2011.<br />

Embedd<strong>in</strong>g speech acts. Ms., Humboldt Univ. zu Berl<strong>in</strong>. [10] Me<strong>in</strong>unger 2004. In Lohnste<strong>in</strong>–<br />

Trissler (eds.), The Syntax and Semantics of <strong>the</strong> Left Periphery, 313–341. Mouton de Gruyter.<br />

[11] Rizzi 1997. In Haegeman (ed.), Elements of Grammar, 281–337. Kluwer. [12]<br />

Truckenbrodt 2006. Theoretical <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 32, 257–306.


Jason Bishop (UCLA)<br />

Information structure, prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence and <strong>in</strong>dividual differences:<br />

evidence from on-l<strong>in</strong>e process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

In <strong>the</strong> present study we explored listeners’ knowledge about how prosody can express<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation structure <strong>in</strong> English. In particular, we probed listeners for expectations regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

how prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence relates to <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong> focus constituent (broad vs. narrow) <strong>in</strong><br />

SVO constructions. While it is well-known that <strong>the</strong> prosodic realizations of contrasts along<br />

this dimension are ambiguous <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of nuclear pitch accent location, recent studies have<br />

shown that speakers can dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>the</strong>m us<strong>in</strong>g gradient phonetic cues. In particular, it has<br />

been reported that (a) narrow focus on an object is associated with phonetically lower<br />

prenuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence and/or phonetically higher nuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence, and (b) broader VP<br />

and Sentence focus show <strong>the</strong> opposite pattern (e.g., Breen et al. 2010 and references <strong>the</strong>re<strong>in</strong>).<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, it has also been shown that, <strong>in</strong> perception, listeners exhibit expectations for exactly<br />

this asymmetry (e.g., Bishop 2010). In <strong>the</strong> present study, we made use of <strong>the</strong> cross-modal<br />

associative prim<strong>in</strong>g paradigm to probe on-l<strong>in</strong>e process<strong>in</strong>g mechanis<strong>ms</strong> for a similar<br />

sensitivity.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> experiment presented, 174 English-speak<strong>in</strong>g listeners made lexical decisions<br />

about 32 visual targets (e.g., BRUNETTE) which followed auditorily-presented SVO sentences<br />

<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> object was <strong>the</strong> prime (e.g., He kissed a blonde).<br />

To test for <strong>the</strong> effects of<br />

prosody, sentences were heard by listeners with two different patterns of prom<strong>in</strong>ence: high<br />

prenuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence/low nuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence (ToBI annotations with H* on <strong>the</strong> verb and<br />

!H* on <strong>the</strong> object) and low prenuclear/high nuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence (unaccented verb and (L+)H*<br />

on <strong>the</strong> object). To hold <strong>the</strong>ir acoustic properties constant, <strong>the</strong> primes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two conditions<br />

were identical productions, spliced <strong>in</strong>to different SV productions (see Fig 1). These two<br />

prosodic conditions were <strong>the</strong>n crossed with two focus conditions. The first represented our<br />

primary <strong>in</strong>formation structural <strong>in</strong>terest, namely focus size (broad VP vs. narrow object focus);<br />

however, we also explored <strong>the</strong> possible effect of focus type (non-contrastive/WH focus vs.<br />

contrastive focus). Focus size and type were manipulated us<strong>in</strong>g lead-<strong>in</strong> questions (e.g., What<br />

did John do? for broad VP focus and Who did John kiss? for narrow object focus), with<br />

explicit alternatives offered (Did John kiss Mary?) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of contrastive focus.<br />

Mixed-effects l<strong>in</strong>ear regression was used to model listeners’ reaction times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

lexical decision task as a function of our manipulations, and also several stimuli and listener<br />

variables. Among <strong>the</strong>se were scores on <strong>the</strong> Autism Spectrum Quotient (AQ; Baron-Cohen et<br />

al. 2001), recently shown to be a predictor of performance <strong>in</strong> speech perception and<br />

pragmatic tasks by “normal-function<strong>in</strong>g” adults (Yu 2010; Xiang, Grove and Giannakidou<br />

2011). Results were as follows. The most significant f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g was that lexical decision times<br />

were slowest follow<strong>in</strong>g a prime that was <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a narrow contrastive focus, but bore<br />

an accent that was low <strong>in</strong> relative prom<strong>in</strong>ence (Fig 2). This disruption to prim<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted as <strong>the</strong> result of a focus/ prosody mis-match, and is consistent with our prediction<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g listeners’ expectations. Also consistent with those predictions was <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

response times were fastest when <strong>the</strong> prime was narrowly focused and high <strong>in</strong> relative<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ence. Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, however, it was found that <strong>the</strong> advantage from this focusprom<strong>in</strong>ence<br />

match depended considerably on listeners’ AQ scores, as listeners with more<br />

“autistic” traits benefited less (Fig 3). Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> results provide strong evidence that<br />

English-speak<strong>in</strong>g listeners have conventionalized knowledge about <strong>the</strong> relationship between<br />

focus size and prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence, as this knowledge was found to have psychologically<br />

real consequences. We discuss <strong>the</strong>se results and <strong>the</strong>ir fur<strong>the</strong>r implications for <strong>the</strong> relationship<br />

between prosody and <strong>in</strong>formation structure, sentence and lexical process<strong>in</strong>g, and <strong>the</strong><br />

relevance of <strong>in</strong>dividual differences <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic process<strong>in</strong>g.


Fig1. Example of <strong>the</strong> two prosodic conditions. Sentences were presented with ei<strong>the</strong>r high<br />

prenuclear/low nuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence (left), or low prenuclear/high nuclear prom<strong>in</strong>ence (right).<br />

Primes (always <strong>the</strong> nuclear accented object) were thus relatively high or relatively lower <strong>in</strong><br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ence.<br />

Fig 2. Mean reaction times to targets as a<br />

function of a preced<strong>in</strong>g prime word’s focus<br />

size and relative prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence.<br />

Fig 3. Benefit from a focus-prom<strong>in</strong>ence<br />

match: mean RTs to targets follow<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ent prime that was narrowly<br />

focused and highly prom<strong>in</strong>ent. Three AQ<br />

groups of listeners are shown (higher AQ<br />

scores <strong>in</strong>dicate more prom<strong>in</strong>ent “autistic”<br />

traits).<br />

References<br />

Bishop, J. (2010). Information structural expectations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perception of prosodic<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ence, UCLA Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> Phonetics, 108, 223-225.<br />

Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Sk<strong>in</strong>ner, R., Mart<strong>in</strong>, J., Clubley, E. (2001). The Autism-<br />

Spectrum Quotient (AQ): evidence from Asperger Syndrome/high-function<strong>in</strong>g autism,<br />

males and females, scientists and ma<strong>the</strong>maticians. Journal of Autism and Developmental<br />

Disorders 31, 5-17.<br />

Breen, M., Fedorenko E., Wagner., M, & Gibson, E. (2010). Acoustic correlates of<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation structure. Language and Cognitive Processes 25, 1044-1098.<br />

Yu, A.C.L. (2010). Perceptual compensation is correlated with <strong>in</strong>dividuals' “autistic” traits:<br />

implications for models of sound change. PLoS ONE, 5, e11950.<br />

doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0011950<br />

Xiang, M., Grove, J., Giannakidou, A. (2011). Interference “licens<strong>in</strong>g” of NPIs: pragmatic<br />

reason<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>dividual differences. Poster presented at <strong>the</strong> 2011 CUNY Conference on<br />

Sentence Process<strong>in</strong>g.


In search of (im)perfection: <strong>the</strong> illusion of counterfactual aspect<br />

Puzzle: It has long been noticed that <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> grammatical contexts, morphemes that o<strong>the</strong>rwise<br />

contribute temporal mean<strong>in</strong>gs suddenly fail to do so. One such context is counterfactual<br />

conditionals (CFs), which <strong>in</strong> many languages are marked by “fake” tense and aspect (Iatridou,<br />

2000).Example (1) from Greek illustrates both past and imperfective morphology used to mark<br />

afuture-less-vividconditional:<br />

(1) [An<br />

if<br />

Bronwyn M. Bjorkman (Nor<strong>the</strong>astern) & Claire Halpert (MIT)<br />

peTene<br />

die.PST.IMP<br />

o<br />

<strong>the</strong><br />

arXiGos]<br />

chief<br />

Ta<br />

FUT<br />

ton Tavame st<strong>in</strong> korifi tu vunu<br />

him bury.PST.IMP on.<strong>the</strong> top <strong>the</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong><br />

‘If <strong>the</strong> chief died, we would bury him on <strong>the</strong> top of <strong>the</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong>.’ (Iatridou, 2000)<br />

The use of “fake” past morphology associated with CF <strong>in</strong>terpretations has been widely<br />

documented (Steele, 1975; James, 1982; Iatridou, 2000, a.o.). Several proposals analyze fake<br />

past as <strong>the</strong> locus of CF semantics, ei<strong>the</strong>r by constru<strong>in</strong>g “past”asamarkerofmodal,ra<strong>the</strong>rthan<br />

temporal, remoteness (Steele, 1975; Iatridou, 2000; RitterandWiltschko,2010)orbyderiv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

CF mean<strong>in</strong>g from a purely temporal past (Ippolito, 2002; Arregui, 2009). It has been claimed<br />

that fake imperfective is also <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> CF mark<strong>in</strong>g, though itsuseislesswell-understood:<br />

for Iatridou (2000, 2009) imperfective <strong>in</strong> CFs is a default aspect; Arregui (2004) clai<strong>ms</strong> that<br />

it reflects <strong>in</strong>compatibility between perfective and CFs; while Ippolito (2004) proposes that a<br />

“modal imperfective” reflects a speaker’s <strong>in</strong>direct evidence foraproposition. Iatridou(2009)<br />

proposes that imperfective-marked CFs occur <strong>in</strong> a subset of <strong>the</strong> languages with past-marked<br />

CFs, a generalization she based on <strong>the</strong> fact that Slavic languages have “fake” past but “real”<br />

aspect <strong>in</strong> CFs. In this paper we show that a full typology <strong>in</strong>cludes languages with “fake”<br />

perfective aspect <strong>in</strong> CFs as well, contradict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se previous approaches.<br />

Proposal: We argue that <strong>the</strong> apparent requirement for imperfective <strong>in</strong> CFs <strong>in</strong> some languages<br />

is illusory, amorphologicalreflexof<strong>the</strong>needtorealizeatruePAST feature. “Past<br />

imperfective” morphology <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se languages actually expresses only PAST, weclaim;itreceives<br />

an imperfective <strong>in</strong>terpretation due to contrast with atruePERFECTIVE. In CFs, this<br />

“past imperfective” morphology reflects only CF “past”; it does not reflect syntactic IMPER-<br />

FECTIVE features. We illustrate this proposal with <strong>the</strong> morphological paradigm of three types<br />

of languages: (a) Greek, Romance, and Zulu, where imperfective unspecified and see<strong>ms</strong> to occur<br />

<strong>in</strong> CFs; (b) Arabic, where perfective is unspecified and occurs <strong>in</strong> CFs; and (c) Slavic, where<br />

PAST is specified <strong>in</strong>dependently of aspect, and CFs preserve full aspectual contrasts.<br />

Pattern A: In languages like Greek and Romance, where <strong>the</strong> puzzle of fake CF imperfective<br />

<strong>in</strong>itially arose, CFs are always marked with past-imperfective morphology, while “real” tense<br />

and aspect is suppressed, as illustrated above <strong>in</strong> (1).<br />

We argue based on <strong>in</strong>dependent evidence that this pattern arises because <strong>the</strong> “past imperfective”<br />

encodes only PAST features and is unspecified for aspect; “past perfective”, by contrast,<br />

expresses only PERFECTIVE aspect, and receives a past <strong>in</strong>terpretation by default, due to<strong>in</strong>compatibility<br />

between perfective and present tense (Dahl, 1985). The imperfective <strong>in</strong>terpretation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> “past imperfective” arises due to <strong>the</strong> absence of a privative PERFECTIVE feature.<br />

The absence of “real” aspect mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> CFs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se languages arisesbecausePAST and<br />

PERFECTIVE morphemes compete for realization <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle position. In Zulu, which we argue<br />

has <strong>the</strong> same morphological specifications as Greek and Romance and thus appears to require<br />

“past imperfective” mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> CFs, a perfective suffix can co-occur with this “fake imperfective”<br />

<strong>in</strong> perfective CFs, though <strong>the</strong> two are normally <strong>in</strong>compatible (due to <strong>the</strong> redundancy of<br />

mark<strong>in</strong>g both PAST and PERFECTIVE when both are <strong>in</strong>terpreted temporally):<br />

(2) [ukuba be- ngi-thimulile ]be-ngi-zo-d<strong>in</strong>gaithishi<br />

if PST.IMP1SGsneeze PFV IMP-1SG-FUT-need 5tissue<br />

‘If I had sneezed, I would have needed a tissue.’<br />

1


What dist<strong>in</strong>guishes Zulu from languages like Greek and Romance is that PAST and PERFEC-<br />

TIVE do not compete for a s<strong>in</strong>gle morphological “slot”; as a result, realPERFECTIVE features<br />

and fake PAST features can both be realized on a s<strong>in</strong>gle verb.<br />

Pattern B: Fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence for our approach comes from CF mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Arabic, a language<br />

<strong>in</strong> which perfective, ra<strong>the</strong>rthanimperfective,isrequired<strong>in</strong>CFs. Wearguethat<strong>the</strong><br />

morphological specification <strong>in</strong> this language is <strong>the</strong> reverse of Pattern A languages: here “past<br />

perfective” is simply specified for syntactic PAST features, while “imperfective” is underspecified<br />

for tense (see Benmamoun 2000, Karawani & Zeijlstra 2010, Bjorkman 2011, a.o. for<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependent evidence of this feature specification).<br />

(3) [iza úileQ halaP,] kaan b-iwsal Qal waPt la l-muèaadara<br />

if leave.PST.PFV now, be.PST B-arrive.IMP on <strong>the</strong>-time for <strong>the</strong>-lecture<br />

‘If he left now, he would arrive on time for <strong>the</strong> lecture.’ (Halpert and Karawani, 2011)<br />

Like Zulu, Arabic expresses real tense and aspect <strong>in</strong> CFs via an auxiliary<strong>in</strong>aseparate<br />

position from fake past. Auxiliary kaan, whichisa“perfective”formof<strong>the</strong>verb,markspast<br />

tense alone, while real temporal morphology occurs on <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> verb:<br />

(4) [iza kanno b-yitlaQ bakkeer kul yom,] kaan b-iwsal Qa l-waPt<br />

if be.PST B-leave.IMP early every day, be.PST B-arrive.IMP on <strong>the</strong>-time<br />

‘If he were <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> habit of leav<strong>in</strong>g early, he would arrive on time.’ (H&K)<br />

This ability of <strong>the</strong> past perfective auxiliary kaan alone to mark CFs supports <strong>the</strong> view that<br />

<strong>the</strong> “past perfective” CF mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (3) is <strong>the</strong> exponent of PAST features only.<br />

Pattern C: F<strong>in</strong>ally, Slavic allows full aspectual contrasts <strong>in</strong> CFs, as <strong>in</strong>(5)fromRussian:<br />

(5) a. Esli by Dˇzon umer, my poxoroni-l-i by ego na gor-e.<br />

if SUBJ J. die.PFV.PST we bury.PFV-PST-PL SUBJ he.ACC on mounta<strong>in</strong>-LOC<br />

‘If John died, we would bury him on <strong>the</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong>.’<br />

b. Esli by Dˇzon umira-l, s nim by-l by doktor.<br />

if SUBJ J. die.IMPF-PST with he.INSTR be-PST SUBJ doctor<br />

‘If John were dy<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> doctor would be with him.’<br />

We propose that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se languages, unlike <strong>in</strong> Patterns A and B, PAST, PERFECTIVE, and<br />

IMPERFECTIVE all have separate morphological exponents. Evidence for this can be found <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> existence of morphological past and present for<strong>ms</strong> for imperfective and perfective verbs<br />

<strong>in</strong> Slavic (though a morphological “present” perfective receives a future <strong>in</strong>terpretation). As a<br />

result, real aspectual features PERFECTIVE and IMPERFECTIVE can both be realized <strong>in</strong> addition<br />

to <strong>the</strong> fake PAST mark<strong>in</strong>g required by CFs and <strong>the</strong> illusion of counterfactual aspect disappears.<br />

Implications: The claim that “past imperfective” morphology expresses only PAST features,<br />

and that “imperfective” <strong>in</strong> past-marked CFs is illusory, br<strong>in</strong>gs us closer to understand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> broader contextual requirement for PAST <strong>in</strong> CFs. We argue that perfective morphology<br />

cannot mark CFs <strong>in</strong> Pattern A because “past perfective” does not express PAST features <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>se languages. Given that past perfectives have past <strong>in</strong>terpretations, we argue that it is past<br />

tense features, ra<strong>the</strong>rthanpasttense<strong>in</strong>terpretations, thatresult<strong>in</strong>CF<strong>in</strong>terpretations. Iftrue,<br />

this proposal is an argument <strong>in</strong> favor of analyses <strong>in</strong> which PAST features represent a broader<br />

temporal or modal “exclusion” (Iatridou, 2000) or [-co<strong>in</strong>cidence] (Ritter and Wiltschko, 2010)<br />

feature, and aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> past mark<strong>in</strong>g of CFs reflects <strong>the</strong> contribution of past tense<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation (Arregui, 2009; Ippolito, 2002).<br />

Selected References: Arregui, A. 2009. On similarity <strong>in</strong> counterfactuals. L&P 32.; Halpert, C., & H. Karawani.<br />

2011. Aspect <strong>in</strong> counterfactuals from A(rabic) to Z(ulu). WCCFL 29.; Iatridou, S. 2000. The grammatical <strong>in</strong>gredients<br />

of counterfactuality. LI 31.; — 2010. Some thoughts about <strong>the</strong> imperfective <strong>in</strong> counterfactuals. Handout.;<br />

Ippolito, M. 2002. On <strong>the</strong> Semantic Composition of Subjunctive Conditionals. Ms. MIT/Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen.; — 2004.<br />

Imperfect modality. In The syntax of time. MITPress.;Ritter, E., & M. Wiltschko. 2010. The composition of<br />

INFL. L<strong>in</strong>gBuzz/001078.<br />

2


Andreas Blümel (Goe<strong>the</strong>-Universität Frankfurt am Ma<strong>in</strong>)<br />

Successive-cyclic Movement as <strong>in</strong>termediate Labell<strong>in</strong>g Indeterm<strong>in</strong>acies<br />

Background: Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2008) proposes (1-a) as an algorithm to determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> label when two<br />

syntactic objects undergo external merge (EM, a symmetric process of set-formation) and (1-b)<br />

for <strong>in</strong>ternal merge (IM). Both statements express <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> set result<strong>in</strong>g from IM/EM<br />

must be identified to participate <strong>in</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r operations. But especially <strong>the</strong> stipulation (1-b) is<br />

dubious on conceptual grounds and failures of <strong>the</strong> application of (1-b) have been claimed to be<br />

empirically desireable to derive free relatives among o<strong>the</strong>r constructions (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2008, Citko<br />

2008, Ott 2011a). Thus (1-b) is better derived from <strong>in</strong>dependent factors. There is no shortage<br />

of proposals accord<strong>in</strong>g to which ‘reprojection’ of <strong>the</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g XP may take place (Citko 2008,<br />

Georgi/Müller 2010, Hornste<strong>in</strong>/Uriagereka 2002), but <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se works violations of (1-b) serve<br />

as descriptive devices, not as sources of (failures to apply) (1-b).<br />

Already for EM Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2008:fn.34) addresses an exception to <strong>the</strong> application of (1-a),<br />

namely EM of a subject-DP to v*P as <strong>in</strong> (2): “[T]hese structures lack a label and have an<br />

<strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong>stability, so that one of <strong>the</strong> two members [. . . ] must raise.” An attractive side-effect<br />

of this idea is that it gives a partial explanation for <strong>the</strong> EPP: <strong>the</strong> symmetry created by EM<br />

is broken by IM of <strong>the</strong> subject to Spec-TP. Recently, a number of works have capitalized on<br />

this idea and suggested that <strong>in</strong>stances of IM are ‘triggered’ by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terfaces’ avoidance and<br />

<strong>in</strong>tolerance of symmetry and ambiguity created by narrow syntax (Boecks 2008:116-118, Moro<br />

2008, Ott 2011b). When one of <strong>the</strong> two members <strong>in</strong> (2) moves at <strong>the</strong> phase level, an asymmetry<br />

and concomitantly <strong>the</strong> label (3) is created: IM of DP yields a discont<strong>in</strong>uous object, a set of<br />

occurrences of DP, while v* is identified as <strong>the</strong> label (boldfaced on <strong>the</strong> right <strong>in</strong> (3)); just as only<br />

<strong>the</strong> head of a movement cha<strong>in</strong> can move and cause <strong>in</strong>tervention for Agree, only <strong>the</strong> head of a<br />

movement cha<strong>in</strong> is elegible for labell<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Proposal: Adopt<strong>in</strong>g phase <strong>the</strong>ory, I propose that such ‘<strong>in</strong>stable’ structures may not only result<br />

from EM but also from IM (cf. also Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2010): symmetry-break<strong>in</strong>g movement effectively<br />

leaves <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>-situ category as <strong>the</strong> label. But IM results aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a symmetric, unlabellable<br />

structure <strong>in</strong> need of desymmetrization once we partially dispense with (1-b). Thus <strong>the</strong> process<br />

solves <strong>the</strong> labell<strong>in</strong>g problem downstairs, but only to create a new one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> target. I claim that<br />

this pr<strong>in</strong>cipally <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite symmetry-destroy<strong>in</strong>g/symmetry-creat<strong>in</strong>g character of derivations is <strong>the</strong><br />

source, i.e. <strong>the</strong> ‘trigger’ of <strong>in</strong>termediate steps of successive-cyclic A’-movement, <strong>the</strong> empirical<br />

doma<strong>in</strong> to which I conf<strong>in</strong>e myself here. The symmetry-avoid<strong>in</strong>g character at Transfer (i.e. at<br />

<strong>the</strong> next higher phase) is thus what derives (1-b): <strong>the</strong> target category becomes <strong>the</strong> label due to<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g XP must move fur<strong>the</strong>r to break <strong>the</strong> newly created symmetry. Of course,<br />

this powerful mechanism needs tam<strong>in</strong>g. I propose that Agree between a phase-head and <strong>the</strong><br />

mov<strong>in</strong>g WH-element does just that: at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t when a C-head with an unvalued Q-feature<br />

is merged, it probes for (<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretable Q-feature on) <strong>the</strong> WH-element. It is <strong>the</strong> successful<br />

prob<strong>in</strong>g relationship which ultimately and effectively br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong> WH-element to a halt, captured<br />

<strong>in</strong> (4) (taken from Boeckx 2008:91-98): as <strong>the</strong> probe becomes <strong>the</strong> label by (4), movement of<br />

XP to Spec-probe creates a symmetry which is unproblematic, because (4) renders <strong>the</strong> structure<br />

sufficiently asymmetric for label determ<strong>in</strong>ation. The probe functions similar to what Boeckx<br />

(2003) calls ‘Strong Occurrences’ and Rizzi (2006) ‘Criterial Positions.’<br />

Consider (5), an abstract partial representation of <strong>the</strong> pervasive, structurally unbounded phenomenon<br />

of successive-cyclic WH-movement: an object WH-element ends up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> specifier<br />

of <strong>the</strong> phase head v* (for <strong>in</strong>dependent reasons). At this derivational stage v* or WH may determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>the</strong> label. At <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t when C merges, IM of <strong>the</strong> WH-phrase to Spec-CP asymmetrizes<br />

<strong>the</strong> structure, solv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> labell<strong>in</strong>g problem as far as <strong>the</strong> TP is concerned: TP-<strong>in</strong>ternally, v* determ<strong>in</strong>es<br />

<strong>the</strong> label because IM applies to WH, stabiliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> structure (6). But <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g<br />

1


workspace <strong>the</strong> label <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy problem once aga<strong>in</strong> arises, i.e. <strong>the</strong> edge{WH{C{. . .}}} is<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> ‘too symmetric’ and unstable. In this sense <strong>the</strong> edge configurations <strong>in</strong> (2)/(5) and (6) are<br />

parallel. Aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> asymmetry is restored once WH moves on (on <strong>the</strong> right <strong>in</strong> (6)).<br />

In (7-a) <strong>the</strong> matrix verb doesn’t select an <strong>in</strong>direct question. A spurious [WH]/[EPP]-feature<br />

on <strong>the</strong> embedded C head to derive <strong>in</strong>termediate movement steps is thus dubious and ad hoc.<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> present analysis, <strong>the</strong> successive-cyclic character of long WH-movement follows automatically<br />

from <strong>the</strong> symmetry-avoid<strong>in</strong>g character <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terfaces impose on each <strong>in</strong>termediate<br />

configuration. What blocks movement to <strong>the</strong> matrix Spec-C <strong>in</strong> cases like (8-a), i.e. why don’t<br />

we have to get (8-b)? I propose that <strong>in</strong>terrogative C bears a prob<strong>in</strong>g Q-feature which Agrees<br />

with <strong>the</strong> WH-word. Such a feature appears plausible as <strong>the</strong> CP is selected by wonder. By contrast,<br />

such an Agree relation between non-<strong>in</strong>terrogative C (=that) and which book is crucially<br />

miss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (7-a), which is why (7-b) is out: <strong>the</strong> WH-word is stuck <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> symmetric structure{WH{C=that<br />

. . .}}, where an <strong>in</strong>termediate labell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy arises which rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

unresolved. In (8-a)/(9) on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, Agree(uQ,WH) determ<strong>in</strong>es C as <strong>the</strong> label by (4).<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not IM of WH takes place at this po<strong>in</strong>t is irrelevant for labell<strong>in</strong>g: if WH moves, no<br />

problematic symmetry arises, as (4) renders C <strong>the</strong> label. But notice that WH has to move, because<br />

<strong>the</strong> labell<strong>in</strong>g question between v and WH is still not decided. Once <strong>the</strong> labell<strong>in</strong>g question<br />

is settled for v/WH (i.e. by mov<strong>in</strong>g WH), no fur<strong>the</strong>r movement is enforced despite <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong> WH-element ends up be<strong>in</strong>g a sister of C. As no fur<strong>the</strong>r movement is enforced by symmetry,<br />

I take it that fur<strong>the</strong>r movement must not take place. In this sense, <strong>the</strong> function of (4) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

current system is to stop fur<strong>the</strong>r movement, i.e. to prevent fur<strong>the</strong>r symmetries. Notice also that<br />

after Agree(uQ,WH) Q is valued, which means that for SEM it becomes <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable from<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretable Q-features. As such it must be selected by <strong>in</strong>terrogative-embedd<strong>in</strong>g predicates,<br />

and no fur<strong>the</strong>r dist<strong>in</strong>ctions (as <strong>in</strong> Pesetsky/Torrego 2007) are needed.<br />

Consequences: The current analysis reconciles tensions between ‘late trigger’ <strong>the</strong>ories of successivecyclic<br />

movement that rely on (variants of) stipulations like Shortes Steps or <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imize Cha<strong>in</strong><br />

L<strong>in</strong>ks Condition (cf. Boeckx 2003 and references <strong>the</strong>re<strong>in</strong>) on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and ‘early trigger’<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories that rely on spurious <strong>in</strong>termediate WH/EPP/Edge-features on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r (cf. Pesetsky/Torrego<br />

2007 among o<strong>the</strong>rs). The former are problematic <strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y violate <strong>the</strong> Extension<br />

Condition and are <strong>in</strong>compatible with phases. The latter rely on stipulated <strong>in</strong>termediate features<br />

to trigger movement. Also, <strong>the</strong> current analysis is less costly than Boˇsković’s (2007) <strong>in</strong><br />

requir<strong>in</strong>g less features: movement is a by-product of labell<strong>in</strong>g, which <strong>in</strong> his work is implicitly<br />

presupposed (and stipulated) to work without justification. But goal-driven movement is<br />

superfluous under <strong>the</strong> current assumptions.<br />

(1) a. if EM of XP and simplex H yields{H, XP}, <strong>the</strong>n H is <strong>the</strong> label<br />

b. ifαundergoes IM toβ, form<strong>in</strong>g{α,β} <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> label ofβis <strong>the</strong> label of{α,β}<br />

(2) {DP{v* . . .}}<br />

(3) C{DP{T{〈DP〉{v* . . .}}}}→C{DP{T{〈DP〉{v* . . .}}}}<br />

(4) Probe-Label Correspondence Axiom: The label of{α,β} is whichever ofαorβprobes<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, where <strong>the</strong> Probe=Lexical Item whose uF gets valued<br />

(5) {WH v*{. . .}}<br />

(6) {WH C{. . . T{〈WH〉 v*{. . .}}}}→WH . . .{〈WH〉 C{. . . T{〈WH〉 v*{. . .}}}}<br />

(7) a. [Which book]i do you [vP ti th<strong>in</strong>k/believe [CP ti C=that Mary [vP ti wrote ti]]]<br />

b. *You th<strong>in</strong>k/believe which book (that) Mary wrote?<br />

(8) a. John wonders [what C Mary will eat]<br />

b. *What does John wonder Mary will eat?<br />

(9) [C [uQ] [. . . [v∗P what[Q] [v*=eat . . . ]]]]<br />

2


Lucas Champollion (Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen)<br />

Temporal dependencies: Anaphora vs. movement<br />

Temporal dependencies provide a useful testbed for syntactic and semantic <strong>the</strong>ories of<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g/context <strong>in</strong>teraction. In this talk, I consider two k<strong>in</strong>ds of temporal dependencies:<br />

those that hold between temporal adjuncts as <strong>in</strong> (1a) and (1b), and those that hold<br />

between before and its complement, as <strong>in</strong> (2a).<br />

(1) a. Last year, it ra<strong>in</strong>ed every day.<br />

b. Last year, it ra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> afternoon.<br />

(2) a. John left before Mary claimed she would arrive.<br />

b. John left before Mary made <strong>the</strong> claim that she would arrive.<br />

These dependencies are rem<strong>in</strong>iscent of well-known phenomena such as quantifier doma<strong>in</strong><br />

restriction, pronoun b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, and movement. For example, it looks like Last year restricts<br />

<strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of every day <strong>in</strong> (1a) and provides an antecedent to <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> afternoon <strong>in</strong> (1b).<br />

The dependency <strong>in</strong> (2a) is like movement <strong>in</strong> that it can be ei<strong>the</strong>r local (John left before<br />

Mary’s claim) or long-distance (John left before Mary’s claimed time of arrival), and <strong>in</strong><br />

that its long-distance <strong>in</strong>terpretation is blocked by island constra<strong>in</strong>ts (2b). Despite <strong>the</strong>se<br />

similarities, <strong>the</strong>re is currently no consensus on <strong>the</strong> status of temporal dependencies. For<br />

example, it is not agreed whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> process that allows last year to restrict <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of<br />

<strong>the</strong> quantifier every day <strong>in</strong> (1a) is due to movement (von Stechow, 2002) or variable b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(Pratt and Francez, 2001, henceforth P&F), presupposition accommodation (Onea,<br />

2011) or contextual processes as <strong>in</strong> Recanati (2002). Determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> nature of temporal<br />

dependencies is <strong>the</strong>refore crucial <strong>in</strong> elucidat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role of context <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

The Pratt&Francez/von Stechow debate. P&F analyze temporal dependencies<br />

between adjuncts semantically. Technically, <strong>the</strong>y add an extra temporal argument λI to<br />

<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of nouns, as <strong>in</strong> (3a), and transfer this up <strong>the</strong> tree by some ad hoc rules<br />

result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> contextualized constituent mean<strong>in</strong>gs as <strong>in</strong> (3b)-(3d).<br />

(3) a. [day] = λIλx[day(x) ∧ τ(x) ⊆ I]<br />

b. [every day] = λP λI∀x[day(x) ∧ τ(x) ⊆ I → P (x)]<br />

c. [it ra<strong>in</strong>s every day] = λI∀x[day(x) ∧ τ(x) ⊆ I → it-ra<strong>in</strong>s(τ(x))]<br />

d. [(1a)] = λI∀y[year(y)∧τ(y) ⊆ I → ∀x[day(x)∧τ(x) ⊆ τ(y) → it-ra<strong>in</strong>s(τ(x))]]<br />

This solution is criticized by Stechow as “too local” because it does not allow for long<br />

distance dependencies as <strong>in</strong> (2a). Stechow favors a syntactic approach, where only one<br />

temporal adjunct attaches to <strong>the</strong> VP, and where <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs are embedded <strong>in</strong> it and undergo<br />

quantifier rais<strong>in</strong>g at LF. For example, Stechow’s LF of (1a) would be this:<br />

(4) [Last year] λi [every day (with<strong>in</strong>) ti] λj [it ra<strong>in</strong>ed (on) tj].<br />

This proposal. I argue that nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> semantic account of P&F nor <strong>the</strong> movementbased<br />

approach of Stechow captures <strong>the</strong> whole picture, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re is a previously unnoticed<br />

dichotomy with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field of temporal dependencies: Attitude-verb dependencies,<br />

like (2a), are subject to syntactic movement constra<strong>in</strong>ts and should <strong>the</strong>refore be handled<br />

by a Stechow-style movement-based account. By contrast, dependencies between<br />

adjuncts, like (1a), systematically violate constra<strong>in</strong>ts on syntactic movement, as shown<br />

by <strong>the</strong> novel data below <strong>in</strong> (5) and (6). Specifically, <strong>the</strong>y can span because-clauses (5a),<br />

relative clauses (5b), if -clauses (5c), sentential subjects (5d), etc. Moreover, <strong>the</strong>y show<br />

<strong>the</strong> same range of <strong>in</strong>terpretations as pronouns and implicit variables: donkey read<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

(6a), quantificational (6b) and modal subord<strong>in</strong>ation (6c).


(5) a. Every year, John got anxious because he needed to file taxes <strong>in</strong> April.<br />

b. Every year, some guy who needs to file taxes <strong>in</strong> April gets anxious <strong>in</strong> March.<br />

c. Last year, I wonder if John went to France <strong>in</strong> August or <strong>in</strong> September.<br />

d. On most days, that it ra<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> afternoon is a good possibility.<br />

(6) a. Whenever John spends a week <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Alps, he hikes every day.<br />

b. Every year, John spends a week <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Alps. Some years, he hikes every day.<br />

c. John might spend <strong>the</strong> next summer <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Alps. He would hike every day.<br />

Formal implementation. The parallel between temporal adjunct dependencies and<br />

anaphora has not been previously noticed and can shed new light on exist<strong>in</strong>g formal accounts<br />

of anaphoric dependencies. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Partee (1989), it is common to avoid mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a pr<strong>in</strong>cipled dist<strong>in</strong>ction between implicit dependencies and overt phenomena such as pronouns.<br />

We can <strong>the</strong>refore take several routes <strong>in</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g temporal adjunct dependencies.<br />

The textbook account of pronoun b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g (Heim and Kratzer, 1998) requires quantificational<br />

antecedents to move (possibly str<strong>in</strong>g-vacuously) – o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong>y cannot create<br />

an <strong>in</strong>dex, which <strong>in</strong> that system is required for b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g a pronoun. This movement appears<br />

unmotivated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of adjunct dependencies. I will present and discuss two<br />

syste<strong>ms</strong> which allow b<strong>in</strong>ders to rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> situ: dynamic semantics and variable-free semantics<br />

(VFS). Each of <strong>the</strong>se syste<strong>ms</strong> has been successfully applied to implicit arguments<br />

(Condoravdi and Gawron, 1996; Pedersen, 2011). VFS is especially appeal<strong>in</strong>g because it<br />

allows us to free P&F of its drawbacks. It represents anaphoric dependencies as additional<br />

lambda slots, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way as P&F represent temporal dependencies. For example,<br />

<strong>the</strong> λx <strong>in</strong> (7) is directly comparable to <strong>the</strong> λI <strong>in</strong> (3a)-(3d). Through its g (Geach) rule,<br />

VFS provides a pr<strong>in</strong>cipled way of pass<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>the</strong>se slots, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g at long distances if<br />

necessary. We <strong>the</strong>refore no longer need to rely on <strong>the</strong> ad hoc rules <strong>in</strong> P&F.<br />

(7) a. [him] = λx.x b. [Mary loves him] = λx[love(mary, x)]<br />

References<br />

Condoravdi, C. and Gawron, J. M. (1996). The context-dependency of implicit arguments.<br />

In Kanazawa, M., Piñón, C., and de Swart, H., editors, Quantifiers, deduction and<br />

context, pages 1–32. CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA.<br />

Heim, I. and Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics <strong>in</strong> <strong>Generative</strong> Grammar. Blackwell Publish<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

Oxford, UK.<br />

Onea, E. (2011). On temporal quantification. In Reich, I., Horch, E., and Pauly, D.,<br />

editors, Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of S<strong>in</strong>n und Bedeutung 15, pages 451–465. Universaar – Saarland<br />

University Press.<br />

Partee, B. H. (1989). B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g implicit variables <strong>in</strong> quantified contexts. In Wiltshire,<br />

C., Music, B., and Graczyk, R., editors, Papers from CLS 25, pages 342–356. Chicago<br />

<strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> Society, Chicago, IL.<br />

Pedersen, W. A. (2011). Implicit arguments, paychecks and variable-free semantics. In<br />

Ashton, N., Chereches, A., and Lutz, D., editors, Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of SALT 21, pages 155–<br />

175. Rutgers University.<br />

Pratt, I. and Francez, N. (2001). Temporal prepositions and temporal generalized quantifiers.<br />

<strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> and Philosophy, 24(2):187–255.<br />

Recanati, F. (2002). Unarticulated constituents. <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> and Philosophy, 25:299–345.<br />

von Stechow, A. (2002). Temporal prepositional phrases with quantifiers: Some additions<br />

to Pratt and Francez (2001). <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> and Philosophy, 25:755–800.


Hsu-Te Cheng (UConn)<br />

Ellipsis: its Correlates with Phase and Movement<br />

Synopsis The aim of <strong>the</strong> paper is to argue for two generalizations regard<strong>in</strong>g ellipsis: (1) Phases cannot be<br />

elided. (2) The Movement Ellipsis Generalization (MEG): For a certa<strong>in</strong>ly category XP, if XP can be<br />

elided, it cannot be moved and vice versa. It will be argued that <strong>the</strong>se two generalizations can capture a<br />

wider range of data regard<strong>in</strong>g Argument Ellipsis (AE), and provide some <strong>in</strong>sight on how to detect phases.<br />

Introduction It is well known that languages differ <strong>in</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y allow free occurrence of null<br />

arguments (Huang (1984)). One special type of null arguments, AE, where arguments, but not adjuncts,<br />

may be elided (cf. Oku (1998), Saito (2007), Takahashi (2008), among o<strong>the</strong>rs), has received close<br />

<strong>in</strong>spections recently. Japanese, for example, allows objects and subjects to be elided, as evidenced by <strong>the</strong><br />

availability of <strong>the</strong> sloppy read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (1)-(4), irrespective of <strong>the</strong>ir categories (DP, PP, CP, etc). AE,<br />

however, is fairly constra<strong>in</strong>ed. Cheng (2011) argues that <strong>the</strong> paradigm and <strong>the</strong> distribution of AE may be<br />

represented <strong>in</strong> (5). Only languages listed <strong>in</strong> (5a), but not those <strong>in</strong> (5b), are claimed to allow AE.<br />

(1) Taroo-ga [NP zibun-no hahaoya-o ] sonkeisiteiru Ziroo-mo [NP e ] sonkeisiteiru<br />

Taroo-nom self-gen mo<strong>the</strong>r-acc respect Ziroo-also respect<br />

‘Taroo respects his own mo<strong>the</strong>r. ‘Ziroo also respects e.’( OK strict, OK sloppy)<br />

(2) a. Taroo-wa [NP zibun-no teian-ga ] Hanako-o odorokasu to omotteiru<br />

Taroo-top self-gen proposal-nom Hanako-acc surprise that th<strong>in</strong>k<br />

‘Taroo th<strong>in</strong>ks that his proposal will surprise Hanako.’ (Takahashi (2008), p.404)<br />

b. Ken-wa [NP e ] Yumiko-o odorokasu to omotteiru ( OK strict, OK sloppy)<br />

Ken-top Yumiko-o surprise that th<strong>in</strong>k ‘lit. Ken th<strong>in</strong>ks that e will surprise Yumiko.’<br />

(3) a. Taroo to Hanako-ga [PP otagai kara ] meeru-o uketotta<br />

Taroo and Hanako-nom each.o<strong>the</strong>r from e-mail-acc received<br />

‘Taroo and Hanako received e-mail from each o<strong>the</strong>r.’<br />

b. Ken to Yumiko-wa [PP e ] tegami-o uketotta<br />

Ken and Yumiko-top letter-acc received ‘Ken and Yumiko received letters.’<br />

(4) a. Taroo-wa [CP zibun-no teian-ga Hanako-o odorokasu to] omotteiru<br />

Taroo-top self-gen proposal-nom Hanako-acc surprise that th<strong>in</strong>k<br />

‘Taroo th<strong>in</strong>ks that his proposal will surprise Hanako.’<br />

b. Ziroo-mo [CP e ] omotteiru<br />

Ziroo-also th<strong>in</strong>k ‘Ziroo also th<strong>in</strong>ks (that his proposal will surprise Hanako).’<br />

(5) a. Languages that allow AE (and sloppy <strong>in</strong>terpretation): Japanese Korean Ch<strong>in</strong>ese, Turkish…<br />

b. Languages that DO NOT allow AE (and sloppy <strong>in</strong>terpretation): English, French, German, Dutch…<br />

The Proposal I propose that <strong>the</strong>re is a general ban on ellipsis that phases cannot be elided, as <strong>in</strong> (6).<br />

English provides supports for this generalization. Arguments <strong>in</strong> English have been argued to be DPs (cf.<br />

Abney (1987)), and it has been argued that DPs are phases (Svenonius (2004), among o<strong>the</strong>rs). Therefore,<br />

it is <strong>the</strong>n expected that AE is not available <strong>in</strong> English, given (6), s<strong>in</strong>ce arguments are phases (DPs) <strong>in</strong><br />

English, as <strong>in</strong> (7). Moreover, it has been argued that vPs and CPs are strong phases <strong>in</strong> English. (8b) shows<br />

that CPs cannot be elided, conform<strong>in</strong>g with (6). As for vP ellipsis, Merchant (2008) argues that it is really<br />

VP ellipsis, based on <strong>the</strong> facts <strong>in</strong> (9) that ellipsis tolerates voice mismatches. Under <strong>the</strong> assumption that<br />

voice is hosted <strong>in</strong> v, it follows that what is elided is VP, not vP, conform<strong>in</strong>g with (6). For Japanese and<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese, it has been argued that DP is miss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se languages (Bošković (2008)). The existence of AE<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se languages <strong>the</strong>n follows, given that NP is not a phase (Despić (2011)) and thus can be elided.<br />

(6) The Non-Elidability Condition of Phases: If XP is a phase, XP cannot be elided <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> PF component.<br />

(7) a. *John likes his mo<strong>the</strong>r, and Bill also likes [DP e ].<br />

b. *John th<strong>in</strong>ks that his son is smart. Bill also th<strong>in</strong>ks that [DP e ] is smart.<br />

(8) a. John suspects [CP whe<strong>the</strong>r Mary will pass <strong>the</strong> exam]. b. *Bill also suspects [CP e ].<br />

(9) a. This problem was to have been looked <strong>in</strong>to, but obviously nobody did [VP e ].<br />

b. Actually, I have implemented it with a manager, but it doesn’t have to be [VP e ].<br />

Analysis Hav<strong>in</strong>g substantiated <strong>the</strong> validity of (6), I argue that it may be derived from o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>dependently<br />

motivated assumptions about phases and Spell-Out. I adopt <strong>the</strong> three commonly assumed proposals <strong>in</strong><br />

(10a-c) plus <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>in</strong> (10d). Given <strong>the</strong>se assumptions, <strong>the</strong> ban <strong>in</strong> (6) may be derived. As shown <strong>in</strong>


(11a), when <strong>the</strong> sentence is built to a phase (e.g. vP), <strong>the</strong> complement (VP) will be sent to Spell-Out. The<br />

PF component can choose whe<strong>the</strong>r to realize it properly (with full phonological realization) or not, as <strong>in</strong><br />

(11b). Later, when <strong>the</strong> structure is built to <strong>the</strong> next higher phase, as <strong>in</strong> (11c), <strong>the</strong> shaded element <strong>in</strong> (11c),<br />

namely v to IP, will be sent to Spell-Out, given <strong>the</strong> cyclic (phase-by-phase) nature of Spell-Out. The<br />

whole result will be ei<strong>the</strong>r sluic<strong>in</strong>g, if <strong>the</strong>se elements are spelled out as null, as <strong>in</strong> (11d), or VP ellipsis, if<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are properly realized, as <strong>in</strong> (11e). The condition <strong>in</strong> (6) is thus derived. The complement and <strong>the</strong> edge<br />

of <strong>the</strong> phase are always <strong>in</strong> two different spell<strong>in</strong>g out cycles. The only way to elide <strong>the</strong> whole phase is, <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> second Spell-Out, to realize <strong>the</strong> edge of <strong>the</strong> phase as null but to assign <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong> spell<strong>in</strong>g out cycle<br />

proper realization. This option, however, is impossible, given that PF cannot handle elements with<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistent phonological features <strong>in</strong> one spell<strong>in</strong>g out cycle, as <strong>in</strong> (10d). In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>in</strong> (11c) PF<br />

cannot realize v and vP as null but realize I and IP properly. The ban on elid<strong>in</strong>g phases is thus derived.<br />

One consequence of this condition is that <strong>the</strong> category that may be elided is restricted to complements of<br />

phase heads, given that only <strong>the</strong> complement of phase head HP may be sent to Spell-Out, as <strong>in</strong> (12).<br />

(10) a. Derivations proceed successive cyclically and cycle is def<strong>in</strong>ed by phase (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2000, 2001)).<br />

b. Transfer: In phase P with head HP, Transfer applies to <strong>the</strong> complement doma<strong>in</strong> of HP as<br />

soon as <strong>the</strong> edge of P is extended. (Hiraiwa (2003))<br />

c. At each Spell-Out cyle, <strong>the</strong> PF component must decide whe<strong>the</strong>r to spell out <strong>the</strong> elements properly<br />

or not (with null/zero phonological realization). (cf. Holmberg (2001))<br />

d. PF Uniformity: In each cycle, PF can only handle elements with consistent phonological features.<br />

(11) a. [vP [ v [VP eat a cake ]]] b. [vP [ v [VP Δ ] ]] c. [CP C [IP I [vP v [VP ] ] ] ]<br />

� sent to Spell-Out � VP realized as null � sent to Spell-Out<br />

d. [CP C [IP Δ ] ] � sluic<strong>in</strong>g (IP-ellipsis) e. [CP C [IP I [vP v [VP Δ ] ] ] ] � VP ellipsis<br />

(12) a. [Phase H [ …… [Phase Specifier H [XP complement] ]]]<br />

|_____Spell-Out______| |__Spell-Out__|<br />

The Movement Ellipsis Generalization (MEG) MEG, as <strong>in</strong> (13), can <strong>the</strong>n be derived from <strong>the</strong> condition<br />

<strong>in</strong> (6). For a phrase to undergo ellipsis, it must be <strong>the</strong> complement of phase heads, which has been argued<br />

to be immobile, given <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay of PIC and Anti-Locality (cf. Abels (2003) and o<strong>the</strong>rs), as <strong>in</strong> (14). On<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, for a phrase to undergo movement, it must NOT be <strong>the</strong> complement of phase heads so that<br />

movement will not be blocked by PIC and Anti-Locality. However, not be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> complement of phase<br />

will <strong>in</strong> turn exclude it to be eligible for ellipsis. MEG thus predicts that movement and ellipsis are<br />

mutually-exclusive for a given phrase, and this is empirically substantiated. (15-17) show that MEG holds<br />

for CP, DP, and IP. For VP, while it may be elided (18a), it cannot be moved (18b), evidence com<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from Huang’s (1993) b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g examples show<strong>in</strong>g what’s fronted is vP, which conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> subject trace.<br />

(13) MEG: For a certa<strong>in</strong>ly category XP, if XP can be elided, it cannot be moved and vice versa.<br />

(14) a. [Phase Spec [ HP XP ] ] b. [Phase Spec [ H XP ] ]<br />

(banned by Anti-Locality) (banned by PIC)<br />

(15) a. [CP that John will marry a supermodel]1, I will never believe t1 .<br />

b. *John believes that Mary is smart, and Bill also believes [CP e ].<br />

(16) a. [DP Banana]1, John really likes t1 . b. *John likes this book, but Bill does not like [DP e ].<br />

(17) a. *[IP Sam likes Sue]1, Joe doesn’t believe that t1 . b. Joe saw someone, but I don’t know who [IP e ].<br />

(18) a. Sam will come, but Sue will not [VP e ]. b. Sami said that [wash hi<strong>ms</strong>elf*i/j] Joej certa<strong>in</strong>ly would tvP.<br />

Discussion I fur<strong>the</strong>r argue that <strong>the</strong> existence of scrambl<strong>in</strong>g and AE <strong>in</strong> Japanese does not pose a problem<br />

to MEG. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Ohtaki (2011), I will argue that what is elided is not a full DP/NP <strong>in</strong> Japanese, but a<br />

sub-part of it, licensed by (null) KP, a phase. I will argue that <strong>the</strong> same holds for Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese as<br />

well. MEG thus provides us a tool to detect what a phase is, which may be moved but not elided.<br />

Selected References Abels, K. (2003). Successive cyclicity, anti-locality, and adposition strand<strong>in</strong>g. UConn<br />

dissertation. Abney, S. (1987). The English noun phrase <strong>in</strong> its sentential aspect. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT.<br />

Bošković, Ž. (2008). What will you have, DP or NP? In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> 37 th North NELS. Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. (2000).<br />

M<strong>in</strong>imalist Inquires. In Step by step, 89-155. Huang, J. (1984). On <strong>the</strong> distribution and reference of empty<br />

pronouns. LI 15: 531-574. Oku, S. (1998). A <strong>the</strong>ory of selection and reconstruction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imalist perspective.<br />

Doctoral Dissertation, UConn. Saito, M. (2007). Notes on East Asian argument ellipsis. Language Research 43:<br />

203-227. Takahashi, D. (2008). Noun Phrase Ellipsis. In The Oxford Handbook of Japanese <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>, 394-422.


Sofiana Chiriacescu (Stuttgart)<br />

Focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases <strong>in</strong> German and English: consequences of reference<br />

form on <strong>the</strong> subsequent discourse.<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> fundamental questions underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ories of language production concerns<br />

referent-track<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g what referents are preferred to be picked up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent<br />

discourse and what types of referr<strong>in</strong>g expressions are used for this purpose. A body of<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guistic and psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic studies found out that several factors and criteria <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong><br />

frequency of re-mention of referents, such as prom<strong>in</strong>ent syntactic positions (e.g. subjects,<br />

focus of clefts) and different <strong>the</strong>matic roles (e.g. Stimulus role <strong>in</strong> a transitive event with<br />

Stimulus and Experiencer roles). Given <strong>the</strong>ir high accessibility or prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of<br />

syntactic and semantic factors, <strong>the</strong>se referents are fur<strong>the</strong>rmore likely to be picked up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g discourse by means of a more reduced type of referr<strong>in</strong>g expression (typically a<br />

pronoun) compared to <strong>the</strong>ir less-prom<strong>in</strong>ent counterparts (Ariel 2001, Grosz, Joshi and<br />

We<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong> 1995). In this paper, we focus on referents mentioned <strong>in</strong> non-prom<strong>in</strong>ent positions<br />

<strong>in</strong> English and German, i.e. as direct objects realized as <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases, and argue<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y differ <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of frequency of subsequent mention and likelihood of<br />

pronom<strong>in</strong>alization. The results are discussed <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of how different types of <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

noun phrases affect <strong>the</strong> discourse structur<strong>in</strong>g potential of <strong>the</strong>ir referents dur<strong>in</strong>g reference<br />

production.<br />

Study1: The English data (Indef<strong>in</strong>ite-this vs. <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite-a)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to several studies (Pr<strong>in</strong>ce 1981, Ion<strong>in</strong> 2006), English this can be used as an<br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er alongside <strong>the</strong> simple <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite article a(n). The Experiment (Exp1)<br />

<strong>in</strong>vestigates whe<strong>the</strong>r referents <strong>in</strong>troduced by this and a(n) differ <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of likelihood of<br />

subsequent mention and likelihood pronom<strong>in</strong>alization. Design. We used a sentencecont<strong>in</strong>uation<br />

task with no pronoun-prompt. Participants (n=20) read story fragments (e.g. (1))<br />

and were asked to add five logical and natural-sound<strong>in</strong>g sentence cont<strong>in</strong>uations to each of <strong>the</strong><br />

stories. All critical referents were constructed <strong>in</strong> direct object position and were realized as<br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases. We only manipulated <strong>the</strong> morphological realization of <strong>the</strong> direct<br />

objects (2 conditions: this-condition and a(n)-condition). Note that <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite this occurs<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong> conversational English, thus, <strong>the</strong> test ite<strong>ms</strong> were kept <strong>in</strong> a colloquial tone.<br />

(1) Sample experimental item from Exp1<br />

this-condition a(n)-condition<br />

Yesterday even<strong>in</strong>g was so warm that Yesterday even<strong>in</strong>g was so warm that James<br />

James decided to hang out with friends decided to hang out with friends at <strong>the</strong> local<br />

at <strong>the</strong> local coffee shop. On his way coffee shop. On his way downtown, he saw<br />

downtown, he saw this kid com<strong>in</strong>g down<br />

<strong>the</strong> street.<br />

a kid com<strong>in</strong>g down <strong>the</strong> street.<br />

Each target item conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>dividual references to two characters. In (1), for example, <strong>the</strong><br />

first referent (James) is <strong>the</strong> clearly established topic constituent of <strong>the</strong> story fragment, as it is<br />

mentioned twice (with a proper name and pronoun) <strong>in</strong> grammatical subject position. The<br />

critical item <strong>in</strong> (1), this kid, is <strong>in</strong>troduced as an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrase <strong>in</strong> direct object position<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> last clause of <strong>the</strong> story fragment. In light of previous studies on <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite-this<br />

(Gernsbacher & Shroyer 1989), we predict that this-referents will be: (i) more frequently<br />

picked up and (ii) more likely to be mentioned with a pronoun <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent discourse,<br />

compared to a-referents. Results. The first part of our prediction was confirmed, as thisreferents<br />

were picked up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent discourse more often than a-referents (<strong>in</strong> 85% vs.<br />

15% of <strong>the</strong> cases). The second part of our prediction was not confirmed, as <strong>the</strong> anaphoric


expressions used for both <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite types were def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases (Fig1).<br />

Fig. 1. Type of referr<strong>in</strong>g expression used for <strong>the</strong> first re-mention of <strong>the</strong> referents <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> this-condition and a(n)-condition<br />

Study2: The German data (Indef<strong>in</strong>ite-so’n vs. <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite-e<strong>in</strong>)<br />

The German determ<strong>in</strong>er so’n can be used <strong>in</strong> a similar way as English <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite this (von<br />

Heus<strong>in</strong>ger 2011). Experiment 2 (Exp2) had <strong>the</strong> same design, but tested <strong>the</strong> discourse behavior<br />

of <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>te-so’n compared to that of <strong>the</strong> simple <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite headed by e<strong>in</strong>(e) (‘a(n)’). Aga<strong>in</strong>,<br />

we manipulated only <strong>the</strong> type of <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrase, which resulted <strong>in</strong> 2 conditions: so’ncondition<br />

and e<strong>in</strong>(e)-condition, as <strong>in</strong> (2). Our prediction is, that if <strong>the</strong> accessibility of so’nreferents<br />

is comparable to that of referents preceded by <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite-this, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>the</strong><br />

two experiments should be similar. Results: Similar to <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of Exp 1, so’n-referents<br />

were picked up more often <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ensu<strong>in</strong>g discourse than <strong>the</strong> e<strong>in</strong>(e)-referents (<strong>in</strong> 80% vs. 17%<br />

of <strong>the</strong> cases), but did not show a preference for pronom<strong>in</strong>alization (Fig.2).<br />

Fig. 2. Type of referr<strong>in</strong>g expression used for <strong>the</strong> first re-mention of <strong>the</strong> referents <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> so’n-condition and e<strong>in</strong>(e)-condition<br />

Conclusions: First, both <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite this and <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite so’n signal <strong>the</strong> likelihood of subsequent<br />

mention of <strong>the</strong>ir referents. Second, <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of both Exp1 and Exp2 underl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

necessity to dissociate between likelihood of subsequent mention and likelihood of<br />

pronom<strong>in</strong>alization (confirmation of recent studies on language production, e.g. Kehler, Kertz,<br />

Rohde & Elman 2008), as <strong>the</strong>y do not po<strong>in</strong>t to <strong>the</strong> same type of accessibility of a referent.<br />

Third, we argue that <strong>the</strong> different markers of <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite noun phrases (i.e. this <strong>in</strong> English and<br />

so’n <strong>in</strong> German) were developed to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between accessible and non-accessible<br />

referents when realized as direct objects, as such referents are better competitors for <strong>the</strong><br />

subject referents, at least <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of likelihood of subsequent mention.<br />

References:<br />

*Ariel, M.: Accessibility <strong>the</strong>ory: An overview. In Ted J.M. Sanders, Joost Schilperoord & Wilbert Spooren<br />

(eds.), Text representation: L<strong>in</strong>guistic and psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic aspects, 29–87. A<strong>ms</strong>terdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s (2001).<br />

*Gernsbacher, M & Shroyer, A.: The cataphoric use of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite this <strong>in</strong> spoken narratives. Memory &<br />

Cognition 1989, 17 (5), 536-540. *Grosz, A. Joshi, A. & We<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong>, S.: Center<strong>in</strong>g: a framework for modell<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> local coherence of discourse. Computational <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 21: 203 - 225 (1995). *Ion<strong>in</strong>, T.: This is def<strong>in</strong>itely<br />

specific: specificity and def<strong>in</strong>iteness <strong>in</strong> article syste<strong>ms</strong>. Natural Language Semantics. Spr<strong>in</strong>ger. 14. 175-234<br />

(2006). *von Hes<strong>in</strong>ger, K.: Specificity, referentiality and discourse prom<strong>in</strong>ence: German <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

demonstratives. In Reich, Ingo et al. (eds.), Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of S<strong>in</strong>n & Bedeutung 15, Saarland University Press:<br />

Saarbrücken, Germany (2011). *Kehler, A., Kertz, L., Rohde, H., & Elman, J. L.: Coherence and coreference<br />

revisited. Journal of Semantics, 25, 1–44 (2008).


Kaily Clackson (Essex), Vera Heyer (Potsdam) & Harald Clahsen (Potsdam)<br />

Onl<strong>in</strong>e application of B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples A and B:<br />

Evidence from eye movements dur<strong>in</strong>g listen<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Previous experiments exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> time course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

dur<strong>in</strong>g onl<strong>in</strong>e process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> adults have yielded mixed results. Early cross-modal prim<strong>in</strong>g<br />

experiments suggested that only grammatically accessible antecedents were considered as<br />

potential antecedents for a pronoun or reflexive, lead<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> proposal that b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples act as an ‘<strong>in</strong>itial filter’, restrict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> search for an antecedent to syntactically<br />

appropriate positions (Nicol & Sw<strong>in</strong>ney 1989). More recent studies have shown that o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

sources of <strong>in</strong>formation such as gender, discourse salience and recency also contribute to<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> referent, although <strong>the</strong> question of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se factors operate <strong>in</strong> parallel<br />

with syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts or somewhat later is still controversial (see e.g. Badecker and<br />

Straub 2002, Sturt, 2003).<br />

To <strong>in</strong>vestigate <strong>the</strong> moment-to-moment process<strong>in</strong>g of reflexives and pronouns, <strong>the</strong> present<br />

study employed <strong>the</strong> visual world paradigm, monitor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> eye-movements of 42 adult native<br />

speakers to ‘task-relevant visual contexts’ (Trueswell, 2008: 145) while <strong>the</strong>y listened to<br />

stories such as (1) and (2).<br />

(1) Reflexives<br />

Peter/Susan was wait<strong>in</strong>g outside <strong>the</strong> corner shop. He/She watched as Mr Jones<br />

bought a large box of popcorn for hi<strong>ms</strong>elf over <strong>the</strong> counter.<br />

(2) Pronouns<br />

Peter/Susan was wait<strong>in</strong>g outside <strong>the</strong> corner shop. He/She watched as Mr Jones<br />

bought a large box of popcorn for him/her over <strong>the</strong> counter.<br />

Each story <strong>in</strong>volved two characters and an object (e.g. popcorn <strong>in</strong> (1)). One character was<br />

structurally accessible as an antecedent for <strong>the</strong> reflexive/pronoun (e.g., Mr. Jones <strong>in</strong> (1)),<br />

and one character was structurally <strong>in</strong>accessible (e.g., Peter/Susan <strong>in</strong> (1)). The gender of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent ei<strong>the</strong>r matched or mismatched <strong>the</strong> gender of <strong>the</strong> reflexive/pronoun.<br />

Participants first saw a picture of <strong>the</strong> object, <strong>the</strong>n were asked to listen to <strong>the</strong> story, <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

as quickly as possible ‘who is it for?’ by press<strong>in</strong>g a button correspond<strong>in</strong>g to one of 4 pictures:<br />

<strong>the</strong> two characters mentioned, <strong>the</strong> object, and a distracter character (whose gender did not<br />

match <strong>the</strong> reflexive/pronoun). A video camera record<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> participant’s face provided an<br />

onl<strong>in</strong>e measure of gaze direction at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>the</strong> pronoun/reflexive, and button presses<br />

provided onl<strong>in</strong>e reaction times and accuracy scores reflect<strong>in</strong>g participants’ f<strong>in</strong>al offl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong> pronoun/reflexive.<br />

Offl<strong>in</strong>e accuracy scores showed that for reflexive sentences <strong>the</strong> experimental manipulation<br />

had little effect on <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>terpretation (Match: 95%; Mismatch: 98%), but for <strong>the</strong> pronoun<br />

sentences accuracy was significantly lower when <strong>the</strong> gender of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent<br />

matched that of <strong>the</strong> pronoun (Match: 86%; Mismatch: 96%). In Match conditions almost all<br />

erroneous responses selected <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent. In both reflexive and pronoun<br />

sentences, reaction times were significantly slower when <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent<br />

matched <strong>in</strong> gender with <strong>the</strong> pronoun/reflexive (108<strong>ms</strong> difference for reflexive sentences,<br />

243<strong>ms</strong> for pronoun sentences).


For both reflexives and pronouns, gaze direction was affected by <strong>the</strong> gender of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent, with participants’ gaze mov<strong>in</strong>g more quickly away from <strong>the</strong> picture<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent when it mismatched <strong>in</strong> gender with <strong>the</strong> reflexive/pronoun.<br />

Statistical analysis showed significant 3-way <strong>in</strong>teractions between Time, Antecedent<br />

(accessible/<strong>in</strong>accessible) and Gender of <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent (match/mismatch) from <strong>the</strong><br />

earliest po<strong>in</strong>t at which eye-movements reflect process<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> pronoun/reflexive (200<strong>ms</strong><br />

after <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> reflexive/pronoun).<br />

Results show that although <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>terpretation of a reflexive is constra<strong>in</strong>ed by pr<strong>in</strong>ciple A,<br />

a discourse salient <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent is also considered as a potential referent from<br />

<strong>the</strong> earliest measurable time. In <strong>the</strong> case of pronouns (where <strong>the</strong> structural constra<strong>in</strong>t does<br />

not pick out a particular referent), <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>terpretation is affected by a recently mentioned<br />

gender match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent, and this competition is also reflected <strong>in</strong> onl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

measures.<br />

Our results provide support for <strong>the</strong> view (e.g., Badecker & Straub, 2002) that from <strong>the</strong><br />

earliest measurable po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts work <strong>in</strong> tandem with o<strong>the</strong>r sources of<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation to determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> referent for a reflexive or pronoun.<br />

References<br />

Badecker, W., Straub, K. (2002) The process<strong>in</strong>g role of structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of pronouns and anaphors. Journal of Experimental Psychology:<br />

Learn<strong>in</strong>g, Memory and Cognition, 28 748-769<br />

Nicol, J., Sw<strong>in</strong>ney, D. (1989) The role of structure <strong>in</strong> coreference assignment dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sentence comprehension. Journal of Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic research, 18 5-19.<br />

Sturt, P. (2003) The time-course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> reference<br />

resolution. Journal of Memory and Language, 48 542-562.<br />

Trueswell, J. (2008). Us<strong>in</strong>g eye movements as a developmental measure with<strong>in</strong><br />

psychol<strong>in</strong>guistics. Developmental Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistics: On-l<strong>in</strong>e methods <strong>in</strong> children‘s<br />

language process<strong>in</strong>g, 73-96.


����� ����������� �� ��� ������ ��� ������ �������������<br />

� ������������ ��������� ��� ����������� �����<br />

�� ���� ������ � ����� ��� � ��� ��������� ��� ����������� ����� ���� ������������� ���� ������<br />

�� � ����� ����������� �������� �� �������� ������ ����������� ����������� �������� ��<br />

�������� �������� ���� ������ ����� �� �������� �� ������������ �� ���� �� ������� �������<br />

�� � ��� ���� �� ��������� ���� �������� ��������� ��� ���������� ��� ��������� ����������<br />

���������� �� ��� �� ������������ ���� �������� ��������������� ������ ��� ��������� ��<br />

���������� ��� ������� �������� ����� �� �� ��������� ��� �������� �� ���� ��� �����������<br />

�� ��� �������� ���������<br />

��� ���� ���� ���� �������� �� �� ��� �� ������� ��� �� ������������ ������ �����������<br />

���� ��� ��������� �� ��� ��� ��� ������ �� �� ��� ���� ������ �� ��� ����� �� ��� ��� �����<br />

��� ���������� �� ��� ������� � �������� �������� ����� ������ �� ���������� ���� �������<br />

���� ��� ���� ���������� ��� �� ������� �� ����� �� ���� ����� ��� ����������� ������ ����<br />

��� ����� ������� ���� ���� �� ��� ��� �� ���� ���<br />

��� �� ���� ��� ���� ��� ���� ����<br />

�� ���� ��� ��� ������<br />

���� ���� �� ����<br />

��� �� ��� ��� ��� ����� ��� ��� ������<br />

�� ���� ��� ��� ������<br />

�� �� ���� ����<br />

� ������� �� ������� ��� ����� ������� ������� ����� � �������� ������ ��������� �� �����������<br />

������� �������� ���� ��� ����� �������� ������ ��� ��� ����� �������� �� ���� ����� �����������<br />

���� � ����� �τ �������� �� ��� ����� ����� � �������� ���� �τ �� ����������� ����� ���� ��������<br />

��� �������� �� ���� ������ ��� ����� ��� ������ ������ �� � ��������� ��� ���������<br />

������������ ��� ��������� ��� ������ ���� �� ��������� ����������� �������������� �������������<br />

��� ���� ������� �� ���� ���� �������� �� ����������� ����� ���� ���� ������ ����<br />

��� �� [[���i α]] o�g � λx.[[α]] o�gx/i<br />

�������� �������� �����<br />

�� [[���i α]] f�g � {λx.[[α]] f�gx/i } ����� �������� �����<br />

������������ ������������ ������� ���� ���� �� ��� ����� �� � ����� �������� �������� �� ���<br />

������� � ������ �� �� ���� ��������� ������������ �� ����� ������ ������� �� � ������ �����<br />

����� ���������� ���� �� ������������� ������ �� ������ ���� �� ��������� �� ��� ����������<br />

������ ������ ������� ��� � ���� ������� ����������<br />

���<br />

∼<br />

�����<br />

!<br />

����<br />

"<br />

��<br />

Noah Constant (UMass Amherst)<br />

[[!]] f�g �<br />

#<br />

���<br />

�<br />

{���� ��� ��� ������ ���� ��� ��� ������ �}�<br />

{���� ��� ��� ������ ���� ��� ��� ������ �}�<br />

� � �<br />

�<br />

[["]] f�g � {λx.{x ��� ������ x ��� ������ �}}<br />

[[#]] f�g � {g��� ��� ������ g��� ��� ������ �}<br />

� ��� ����� ��<br />

�� ���� ��������� �� ��� �������� ���� ��� ����� ����� �� � �������� ���� ���������� ��<br />

������� �� ��� ��������� ��������� �� ����� �� � ����������� ������� �� ������� ������ ��������<br />

�������� �∼�� �� ���� ��������������� �������������� �� �������� ∼ ��������� �� � ������ φ<br />

���� ���������� ���� ��� ������� �������� �� ������������ �������� �� ���� ��������� �� �<br />

������ �� [[φ]] f ���������� �� ����� ��� ��������� ��� �� ���������� ���������� [[φ]] o ���������<br />

������ ��� ��� ���� ���� ���� ������� ���� ��� ������� ������� � ������� �������� ��� ���������<br />

��������� ���� �� �� �������� ��������� �� ��� ���� ���� ��� � ���� ��� ��������� �� ����������<br />


��� ������������ ���� ��� ���� ���� ��������� �������� ������� ��� ��������� ��� ����<br />

����������������� ���������� �� � �������� ��� �������� ���� ��� ��� ����� �� ����� ����� ���<br />

������ �� ����� ������������ �� �������� ������ ����������� �������� �� �������� ��� ���������<br />

������������� ���� ��� ��� ������ �� ���������� �� ������<br />

��� ��������� ��������� �� ��� ����� ����������� ������� �� ���� �� ������� �� ����� ����� ��<br />

���������� �� ���������� ����� ������� ���� ��� ��������� ��� ��� ����� ������� �� ����������<br />

������� ��� �������� �������� �� ��������� ���� ��� ��� ������ �� �������� �������� ������<br />

�������� ��������� ������ ��� ����� ���������� ��� �� ������ �� ���� ��������� �� ���<br />

���� �������� ���� �� ���� �� ������������� ��� ��� ������ �� �� ���� � �������� ���� �������<br />

�������� �� ��� ���������� ����� ��� ����� ��������<br />

��� � $%&& !"#$%'(& )*+*', -.&'/*0<br />

���� ��������� ����� ������<br />

��� ���� ����� ����� ��� ����� ����<br />

������� ����� �<br />

��������� ���� �� ������� ���� � ������� ��� �������� ������ ������ �������� ���� ���<br />

���� ���� ��� ��������� ��� �������� �� ����� �� ������������� �� ��� �������� �������� ������<br />

����� ��������� ������� ������ ����� ����� ��������� ���� ������� �� �������� ����� ����� ��<br />

���������� ��� ����� �� �������� ��� ��� �������� �� ��������� ����������� �� ��� �������<br />

�������� �� ��� ������� ���������� ������� � ��������� �������� ��� � ������� ��������<br />

�� ��������� ������ �� ����������� ��� ����� ����� ��� �������� ��������� �� ��� ��������<br />

�� [[� ���� ��� ����]] o ������� ��� �������� {���� ��� ��� ������ ���� ��� ��� ������ �}� ����<br />

��� ����� ����� [[����� ���� � �� ��� ����]] f ���� �� ���� ��� ������� �������� �� ��� �� ����<br />

������ ��� ���� ������� ���� ��� ���� ����<br />

�������� ����� ����������� ����� ��� ��������� ��� ������� �� ��� ����� ���� ������� �� ��������<br />

� ����� ���� ���� �� ��������� �� ������� ��� ����� �� �������� ����� ���� ���� ����� ��� ���<br />

����� �� ���� ��� ����� ������ �� ��� ������ ��� �������� ����� ����� ��������� ������ �������<br />

�� � ����� �������� ���������� �� ������� ��������� ����� ���� ������� ���� ������ ������ ���<br />

��������� ���� ������� ��� �������� ��� ���� ���� ���� ���� ���� ������ �� �� ���� ���� ���<br />

����� ������� ���������� ���� ���� �� ������ ������ ���� ���� ��� ����� ����� �� ������� �������<br />

�� ����� �������� ������ �� ������� ����� �������� ��������� ������ ����� �� ���� � ������<br />

����������� ������� ��� ��� ��������� ��� ����� ����� ��������� �� ��� ����������� ���������<br />

��� �� �� ��������<br />

����<br />

���� ���� ���� ����<br />

����� �����<br />

�� ����<br />

�� �����<br />

�� ��������<br />

�� ����� �����<br />

���� ���� ���� ����<br />

�� ����<br />

�<br />

��� � ���� ��� ���������<br />

!!��� �� �������� �� ������<br />

�<br />

�<br />

��� �� �������� �� ������<br />

!!��� � ���� ��� ���������<br />

�������� ���������� � ������� �� ����� �� �������� ������ ��� ���������� ����������� ���<br />

���������� ��� ��������� �� ����� �� ��� ������������ �� �������� ��������� ��� �����������<br />

�������������� ��� �� ����� ����� ��� ��������� �� ����� ����������� ���������� ���<br />

��� ������� ����������� �� ����� �������� �������������� �� ���������� �������� ��� ������<br />

�������� �� ����� ����������� ��������� �� ���������� ������� �� ���������� ������ ������ ��<br />

����������� ���� ����� �� ��� ��� ������ �� ����� ����������� ���� ������ ����� �������<br />

��� ������� ����� �� ����� ������� ��������� ������� ������������ ����� ��� �������������<br />

���������� �� ����� ���� ��� ������� �� ������ �������� �� ����� ����������� ������ ������� ��<br />

������ ����� �� ����������� ���������� ������������ ������������ ��� ������������ �������������<br />

���� �� ����������� �� ����� ������ �� ������<br />

�<br />


NPI licens<strong>in</strong>g by exclusives: Just scope could ever expla<strong>in</strong> it<br />

We offer an analysis of <strong>the</strong> NPI licens<strong>in</strong>g properties of a range of exclusives, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g adverbial<br />

and adjectival only, mere, exclusive, and just. Our proposal is that all exclusives license NPIs<br />

with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir semantic scope, and differences <strong>in</strong> behavior arise from differences of scope, which <strong>in</strong><br />

turn derive from differences of semantic type: some exclusives correspond to one application of <strong>the</strong><br />

Geach type-shift<strong>in</strong>g rule to Beaver and Clark’s (2008) lexical entry for only, and o<strong>the</strong>rs correspond<br />

to two.<br />

Data. Despite <strong>the</strong> synonymy between He is only a child and He is a mere child, <strong>the</strong> two exclusives<br />

cannot both license NPIs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> VP of a clause whose subject <strong>the</strong>y modify:<br />

(1) Only a child said anyth<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Elizabeth Coppock (Lund) & David Beaver (U. Texas, Aust<strong>in</strong>)<br />

(2) *A mere child said anyth<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

The adjectival exclusives only and exclusive do not license NPIs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> VP ei<strong>the</strong>r, although <strong>the</strong>y do<br />

license NPIs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir syntactic scope:<br />

(3) a. *The only author got any royalties.<br />

b. The *(only) student who asked any questions got an A.<br />

(4) a. *The exclusive supplier of gas energy got any new contracts.<br />

b. As part of our agreement with your group, <strong>the</strong> Club is <strong>the</strong> *(exclusive) supplier<br />

of any beverage served on our property.<br />

Unlike only and exclusive, mere does not license NPIs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> modified noun phrase ((5)), but it<br />

does license NPIs outside its syntactic scope <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> constructions ((6)):<br />

(5) *He is a mere author of any children’s books<br />

(6) I toiled for decades on a Wiscons<strong>in</strong> campus on which *(a mere) 18 percent of <strong>the</strong> enter<strong>in</strong>g<br />

freshmen [VP ever graduate ].<br />

Just sometimes behaves like mere, and sometimes like only. (7) can be paraphrased as (8).<br />

(7) Just <strong>the</strong> thought of him sends shivers down my sp<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

(8) The mere thought of him sends shivers down my sp<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

On this read<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>the</strong> scalar read<strong>in</strong>g), his touch would send shivers too, if noth<strong>in</strong>g worse. On <strong>the</strong><br />

non-scalar read<strong>in</strong>g, noth<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> thought of him, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g his touch, would send <strong>the</strong><br />

shivers. This is <strong>the</strong> most prom<strong>in</strong>ent read<strong>in</strong>g with only:<br />

(9) Only <strong>the</strong> thought of him sends shivers down my sp<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

It is only on <strong>the</strong> non-scalar read<strong>in</strong>g that just licenses NPIs. (10) is acceptable when it means (11),<br />

but not on <strong>the</strong> most prom<strong>in</strong>ent read<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> subject NP (≈ a mere smile from him).<br />

(10) ?Just a smile from him would make any difference.<br />

(11) Only a smile from him would make any difference.


Scalar particles and competition<br />

Synopsis. We provide an account for <strong>the</strong> variation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> distribution of scalar particles that is based<br />

on three assumptions: (i) scalar particles may move at LF (cf. Karttunen & Peters 1979), (ii) some<br />

scalar particles are morphologically complex (cf. Guerzoni 2003, Lahiri 2010), and (iii) scalar<br />

particles form scales and compete for <strong>in</strong>sertion.<br />

1. Cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic variation. At first sight <strong>the</strong>re appear to be many distributional differences<br />

between scalar particles <strong>in</strong> different languages. However, a more careful exam<strong>in</strong>ation reveals that<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir distribution varies along only two dimensions: <strong>the</strong> pragmatic strength of <strong>the</strong> associate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

immediate surface scope of <strong>the</strong> scalar particle and, roughly, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> scalar particle can be<br />

characterized as an n-word (cf. Gast & van der Auwera 2011).<br />

1.1. First dimension of variation. Scalar particles can be classified with respect to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y may<br />

associate with pragmatically weak or strong elements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir immediate surface scope – we call<br />

<strong>the</strong>se particles weak and strong scalar particles, respectively. With respect to this criterion, <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

three ma<strong>in</strong> groups of scalar particles: (i) scalar particles that may be weak or strong (e.g. even <strong>in</strong><br />

English, même <strong>in</strong> French), (ii) scalar particles that may only be strong (e.g. sogar <strong>in</strong> German, hasta <strong>in</strong><br />

Spanish), and (iii) scalar particles that may only be weak (e.g. so much as <strong>in</strong> English, auch nur,<br />

e<strong>in</strong>mal <strong>in</strong> German). This idiosyncratic distribution is schematized <strong>in</strong> (1), while <strong>the</strong> relevant implicational<br />

generalization is <strong>in</strong> (2).<br />

(1) a. Hans read { even / sogar / *auch nur } SYNTACTIC STRUCTURES<br />

b. If Hans read { even / *sogar / auch nur } ONE book, he passed <strong>the</strong> exam<br />

(2) There is a scalar particle that is only strong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language<br />

⇒ There is a scalar particles that is only weak <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language<br />

1.2. Second dimension of variation. Scalar particles that may only be weak can be split <strong>in</strong>to three<br />

subclasses: (iii.a) scalar particles that may occur both <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate scope of negation and <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

DE environments (so much as <strong>in</strong> English), (iii.b) scalar particles that occur only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate<br />

scope of negation (e.g. e<strong>in</strong>mal <strong>in</strong> German, niti <strong>in</strong> Slovenian), and (iii.c) scalar particles that never<br />

occur <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate scope of negation (e.g. auch nur <strong>in</strong> German, tudi <strong>in</strong> Slovenian). This<br />

distribution is schematized <strong>in</strong> (3), while <strong>the</strong> relevant implicational generalization is <strong>in</strong> (4).<br />

(3) a. Hans didn't read { so much as / e<strong>in</strong>mal / *auch nur } ONE book<br />

b. If Hans read { so much as / *e<strong>in</strong>mal / auch nur } ONE book, he passed <strong>the</strong> exam<br />

(4) There is a scalar particle that may only be weak and only occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate scope of<br />

negation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language ⇒ No o<strong>the</strong>r weak scalar particle that may only be weak occurs <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> immediate scope of negation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language<br />

2. Derivation. We derive <strong>the</strong> variation described above from two parameters (whe<strong>the</strong>r a particle<br />

spells out one or two scalar components, whe<strong>the</strong>r a particle bears a negative feature) and <strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> grammar (Maximize Presupposition, Relativized M<strong>in</strong>imality).<br />

2.1. Morphology. All scalar particles share <strong>the</strong> scalar component that requires its sister to denote a<br />

proposition that is less likely than a relevant alternative (Bennett 1982, Kay 1990). We represent this<br />

component with EVEN (5a). There is ano<strong>the</strong>r component to scalar particles, which is however not<br />

shared by all scalar particles: a scalar component that requires its sister to denote a proposition that is<br />

most likely among <strong>the</strong> alternatives (cf. Guerzoni 2003, Lahiri 2010). We represent this component<br />

with NUR (5b). These two components may move at LF (cf. Karttunen & Peters 1979) and <strong>the</strong>y<br />

associate with <strong>the</strong> same focused element (cf. Krifka 1991). F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> some languages, <strong>the</strong> NUR<br />

component may bear an un<strong>in</strong>terpretable negative feature, mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scalar particle comparable to nwords<br />

or n-<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites of <strong>the</strong> language.<br />

(5) a. [[ EVEN ]] g,c (C, p, w) is def<strong>in</strong>ed only if ∃q∈C [p < c q].<br />

If def<strong>in</strong>ed, [[ EVEN ]] g,c (C, p, w) = 1 iff p(w) = 1<br />

Luka Crnic (Hebrew University)


. [[ NUR ]] g,c (C, p, w) is def<strong>in</strong>ed only if ∀q∈C [q < c p].<br />

If def<strong>in</strong>ed, [[ NUR ]] g,c (C, p, w) = 1 iff p(w) = 1<br />

In a language like German, sogar spells out (6a), auch nur spells out (6b), while (nicht) e<strong>in</strong>mal spells<br />

out (6c). In English, even is ambiguous between (6a) and (6b), while so much as spells out (6b); <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is no scalar particle <strong>in</strong> English that bears a negative feature.<br />

(6) a. [EVEN] ↔ even; sogar b. [EVEN] [NUR] ↔ even; so much as; auch nur<br />

c. [EVEN] [NUR] [uNEG] ↔ (nicht) e<strong>in</strong>mal<br />

2.2. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g distribution. The characterization <strong>in</strong> (6) does not suffice to account for <strong>the</strong> peculiar<br />

restrictions on <strong>the</strong> associates of sogar and auch nur. For example, sogar could occur with a weak<br />

associate where EVEN would move at LF. We block this by assum<strong>in</strong>g that sogar, auch nur and (nicht)<br />

e<strong>in</strong>mal form a scale and compete for <strong>in</strong>sertion (7). The same holds for its k<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r languages.<br />

(7) < [EVEN], [EVEN][NUR], [EVEN][NUR] [uNeg] ><br />

The competition of <strong>the</strong> particles <strong>in</strong> (7) is governed by Maximize Presupposition, which requires one<br />

to use among contextually equivalent alternatives <strong>the</strong> one with stronger presuppositions (Heim 1991).<br />

On <strong>the</strong> one hand, this necessitates sogar to be base-generated adjo<strong>in</strong>ed to clauses denot<strong>in</strong>g strong<br />

propositions: if <strong>the</strong> clause denoted a weak proposition, auch nur would have to be <strong>in</strong>serted s<strong>in</strong>ce this<br />

would lead to stronger presuppositions of <strong>the</strong> sentence (8).<br />

(8) a. ✗ [EVEN C 3] [I doubt [[EVEN C 3] you read one F book]] (spell out: sogar)<br />

b. ✔ [EVEN C 3] [I doubt [[EVEN C 3] [NUR C 0] you read one F book]] (spell out: auch nur)<br />

On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, auch nur may only be adjo<strong>in</strong>ed to clauses denot<strong>in</strong>g weak propositions: if it were<br />

adjo<strong>in</strong>ed to a strong clause, <strong>the</strong>n NUR would ei<strong>the</strong>r trigger an <strong>in</strong>correct presupposition (9b) or it<br />

would have to move above EVEN which is ruled out by Relativized M<strong>in</strong>imality (9c). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<br />

[EVEN][NUR] must be embedded under an appropriate non-upward entail<strong>in</strong>g operator s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> two<br />

scalar components would o<strong>the</strong>rwise trigger clash<strong>in</strong>g presuppositions (cf. Guerzoni 2003).<br />

(9) a. ✔ [I doubt [[EVEN C 3] you read (all) twelve F books]] (spell out: sogar)<br />

b. ✗ [EVEN C 3][I doubt [[EVEN C 3][NUR C 0] you read twelve F books]] (spell out: auch nur)<br />

c. ✗ [NUR C 3][I doubt [[EVEN C 3][NUR C 0] you read twelve F books]] (spell out: auch nur)<br />

[EVEN][NUR] [uNEG] may be spelled out only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate scope of negation where its negative<br />

feature, which has no semantic reflex, can be checked. An Elsewhere Condition <strong>the</strong>n dictates that <strong>in</strong> a<br />

language that has both weak scalar particles, [EVEN][NUR] may not be spelled out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate<br />

scope of negation but only <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r non-upward-entail<strong>in</strong>g environments. Thus, (nicht) e<strong>in</strong>mal and<br />

auch nur are treated analogously to <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites nie and je, respectively (e.g. Penka & Zeijlstra 2005).<br />

As expected, <strong>the</strong>y exhibit a parallel distribution, e.g. both <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite je and auch nur may occur<br />

under (covert) negation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of an n-<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite (10). This is different <strong>in</strong> Slavic languages<br />

where all <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites and weak scalar particles under clausemate negation must be n-marked.<br />

(10) a. Niemand hat { je, *nie } etwas gegessen<br />

n-<strong>in</strong>def-nobody has { <strong>in</strong>def, *n-<strong>in</strong>def } someth<strong>in</strong>g eaten<br />

b. Ich habe nie { auch nur, *nicht e<strong>in</strong>mal, *e<strong>in</strong>mal } EIN Buch gelesen<br />

I have n-<strong>in</strong>def-never { auch nur, *nicht e<strong>in</strong>mal, *e<strong>in</strong>mal } one book read<br />

3. Conclusion. We have derived <strong>the</strong> five classes of scalar particles – (i)-(iii.c) above – <strong>in</strong> a<br />

framework that, first, allows for movement of EVEN and, second, assumes morphological variation<br />

among scalar particles. We left aside <strong>the</strong> issue of additivity of scalar particles; we propose that this is<br />

derived along <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es put forward by Rullmann (1997). Ano<strong>the</strong>r issue left aside is <strong>the</strong> noncanonicity<br />

of movement of EVEN. A fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>quiry <strong>in</strong>to this is mandated.<br />

Selected references. Gast, V. & J. van der Auwera (2011) "Scalar additive operators <strong>in</strong> languages of Europe." Guerzoni,<br />

E. (2003) Why even ask? Lahiri, U. (2010) "Some evens are even ifs." Rullmann, H. (1997) "Even, polarity and scope."


Ian Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs & Patrick Sturt (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh)<br />

The Time-Course of Reference Resolution <strong>in</strong> Picture Noun Phrases:<br />

Evidence from Eye-Movements Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Read<strong>in</strong>g</strong><br />

Although b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, 1981) as orig<strong>in</strong>ally formulated predicts that reflexives<br />

and pronouns should be <strong>in</strong> complementary distribution (e.g. ‘John1 <strong>in</strong>jured hi<strong>ms</strong>elf1/him*1’), a<br />

number of researchers have noted that complementarity breaks down <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> contexts (e.g.<br />

Pollard & Sag, 1992; Re<strong>in</strong>hart & Reuland, 1993). One construction <strong>in</strong> particular where<br />

complementarity appears to break down is <strong>the</strong> picture noun phrase (PNP), as <strong>in</strong> ‘John1 saw a<br />

picture of hi<strong>ms</strong>elf1/him1’, and <strong>the</strong> question of whe<strong>the</strong>r or not possessed picture noun phrases<br />

(PPNPs; e.g. ‘John’s1 picture of hi<strong>ms</strong>elf1/him?1’) should also be exempt from b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

has been <strong>the</strong> subject of some debate (see e.g. Runner et al. 2006).<br />

Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic research has exam<strong>in</strong>ed to what extent b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts are violable dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

onl<strong>in</strong>e sentence process<strong>in</strong>g. While it has been argued that, at least for reflexives, b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory applies early to help guide <strong>the</strong> antecedent search for b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory accessible<br />

antecedents (e.g. ‘John’ <strong>in</strong> ‘Steven knew that John had <strong>in</strong>jured hi<strong>ms</strong>elf’) ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

<strong>in</strong>accessible ones (e.g. ‘Steven’; see e.g. Sturt 2003) dur<strong>in</strong>g onl<strong>in</strong>e sentence comprehension, it<br />

has been claimed that <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents can have early effects on process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (P)PNP<br />

contexts (Kaiser et al. 2009; Runner et al. 2006).<br />

We exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of reflexives and pronouns <strong>in</strong> PNP and PPNP contexts <strong>in</strong> four<br />

eye-track<strong>in</strong>g experiments. In each experiment, 28 different native English speakers read 32<br />

critical and 64 filler texts while <strong>the</strong>ir eye-movements were monitored. Experiments 1 and 2<br />

exam<strong>in</strong>ed reflexives. Critical texts conta<strong>in</strong>ed one accessible and one <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent,<br />

and gender congruence (match vs. mismatch) between each antecedent and <strong>the</strong> reflexive was<br />

manipulated <strong>in</strong> a 2x2 design. Congruence between <strong>the</strong> reflexive and <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent<br />

was manipulated us<strong>in</strong>g proper names (Jonathan/Jennifer), while pre-tested gender stereotypes<br />

were used for <strong>the</strong> accessible antecedent (<strong>the</strong> soldier… hi<strong>ms</strong>elf/herself). PNP and PPNP<br />

contexts were tested <strong>in</strong> Experiments 1 and 2 respectively:<br />

Jonathan/Jennifer was walk<strong>in</strong>g through <strong>the</strong> military barracks. He/she heard...<br />

(1a) ... that <strong>the</strong> soldier had a picture of hi<strong>ms</strong>elf/herself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> mess hall.<br />

(1b) ... about <strong>the</strong> soldier’s picture of hi<strong>ms</strong>elf/herself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> mess hall.<br />

Experiments 3 and 4 exam<strong>in</strong>ed pronouns <strong>in</strong> PNP and PPNP contexts. Similar manipulations<br />

between <strong>the</strong> accessible and <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents and a pronoun were used, except that this<br />

time we avoided use of <strong>the</strong> female pronoun as a result of its temporary ambiguity as a full<br />

noun phrase or specifier (see Clifton et al. 1997):<br />

The medical staff had a meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> office. The surgeon/nurse recalled...<br />

(2a) ... that Jonathan/Jennifer noticed a portrait of him over at <strong>the</strong> back of <strong>the</strong> room.<br />

(2b) ... about Jonathan’s/Jennifer’s portrait of him over at <strong>the</strong> back of <strong>the</strong> room.<br />

The results of Experiments 1 and 2 <strong>in</strong>dicated <strong>the</strong> same relative time-course of antecedent<br />

effects for reflexives <strong>in</strong> both PNP and PPNP contexts. In both experiments, comparatively<br />

earlier read<strong>in</strong>g time measures were longer when <strong>the</strong> accessible antecedent mismatched <strong>the</strong><br />

stereotypical gender of <strong>the</strong> reflexive compared to when <strong>the</strong>re was a gender match, while<br />

effects of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent were <strong>in</strong> comparison delayed. For example, <strong>in</strong> (1b),<br />

stereotypical gender mismatches between <strong>the</strong> reflexive and accessible antecedent <strong>in</strong>curred<br />

longer read<strong>in</strong>g times dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial <strong>in</strong>spection of both <strong>the</strong> reflexive and a spillover region<br />

consist<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> two words after <strong>the</strong> reflexive, whereas effects of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent<br />

were only observed <strong>in</strong> second pass times of <strong>the</strong> spillover region. In Experiments 3 and 4, we


observed reliable effects of <strong>the</strong> accessible antecedent only. For example, <strong>in</strong> both experiments,<br />

second pass times of <strong>the</strong> pronoun were found to be reliably longer follow<strong>in</strong>g a stereotypical<br />

gender mismatch between <strong>the</strong> pronoun and accessible antecedent <strong>in</strong> comparison to when <strong>the</strong>re<br />

was a stereotypical gender match.<br />

The results of Experiments 1 and 2 extend previous f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs that b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory applies early<br />

to help guide <strong>the</strong> resolution of reflexives (Sturt, 2003). Although previous offl<strong>in</strong>e studies have<br />

shown that comprehenders will accept a non-local ‘<strong>in</strong>accessible’ antecedent as a potential<br />

antecedent for a reflexive <strong>in</strong>side a (P)PNP (e.g. Asudeh & Keller, 2001; Runner et al. 2003<br />

Experiment 1), our data suggest that, contra <strong>the</strong> results of Runner et al. (2006) who did not<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude gender (mis)match<strong>in</strong>g control conditions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir visual world experiments, accessible<br />

antecedents only are <strong>in</strong>itially considered as a potential antecedent for a reflexive dur<strong>in</strong>g earlier<br />

stages of process<strong>in</strong>g dur<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>g. The antecedent search for pronouns <strong>in</strong> (P)PNP contexts<br />

appears to be similarly constra<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

References.<br />

Asudeh, A. & Keller, F. (2001). Experimental evidence for a predication-based b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory. Papers from <strong>the</strong> 37 th meet<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society, 1-14.<br />

Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. (1981). Lectures on Government and B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. Dordrecht, Foris.<br />

Clifton, C., Kennison, S., & Albrecht, J. (1997). <strong>Read<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>the</strong> words her, his, him: Implications<br />

for pars<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples based on frequency and on structure. Journal of Memory and<br />

Language, 36, 276-292.<br />

Kaiser, E., Runner, J., Sussman, R., & Tanenhaus, M. (2009). Structural and semantic<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> resolution of pronouns and reflexives. Cognition, 112, 55-80.<br />

Pollard, C. & Sag, I. (1992). Anaphors <strong>in</strong> English and <strong>the</strong> scope of B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g Theory. L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Inquiry, 23, 261-303.<br />

Runner, J., Sussman, R. & Tanenhaus, M. (2003). Assignment of reference to reflexives and<br />

pronouns <strong>in</strong> picture noun phrases: evidence from eye-movements. Cognition, 2003,<br />

B1-B13.<br />

- (2006). Process<strong>in</strong>g reflexives and pronouns <strong>in</strong> picture noun phrases. Cognitive<br />

Science, 30, 193-241.<br />

Re<strong>in</strong>hart, T. & Reuland, E. (1993). Reflexivity. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry, 24, 657-720.<br />

Sturt, P. (2003). The time-course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> reference<br />

resolution. Journal of Memory and Language, 48, 542-562.


Roberta D’Alessandro & Marc van Oostendorp (Leiden)<br />

Cyclic syntax mirrors cyclic phonology. Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italian Vocatives <strong>in</strong> context.<br />

1. The issue. Vocatives pose a number of proble<strong>ms</strong> for various modules of l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>the</strong>ory. For<br />

syntax, <strong>the</strong>y raise <strong>the</strong> issue where exactly such 'case', as vocative is traditionally def<strong>in</strong>ed, is<br />

supposed to be assigned, given that it does not fit <strong>the</strong> traditional taxonomy of <strong>in</strong>herent vs. structural<br />

case: vocative is nei<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>ked to any obvious <strong>the</strong>matic role, nor to any classical case position. Yet,<br />

it displays a dedicated end<strong>in</strong>g (or special phonological form; pace Schaden 2010). Syntactically,<br />

vocatives have been identified with topics (Lambrecht 1969, Portner 2004) or with isolated<br />

elements (Zwicky 2004), and <strong>the</strong>ir function has been classified <strong>in</strong> various ways (Schlegoff 1968,<br />

Zwicky 1974, Portner 2004, Schaden 2010) accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir semantics. None of <strong>the</strong> syntaxsemantics<br />

based analyses, however, offers a solution for <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g phonological puzzle:<br />

vocatives are expressed <strong>in</strong> many languages as truncation patterns (e.g. Yapese, Jensen 1977;<br />

Indonesian, Cohn 2005; Arabic, Russian, Yadroff 1996), even though truncation is o<strong>the</strong>rwise very<br />

marked, while <strong>the</strong>re are no conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g examples of e.g. Nom<strong>in</strong>ative or Dative be<strong>in</strong>g expressed <strong>in</strong><br />

this way <strong>in</strong> any language. Observe that it has been noted that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> verbal doma<strong>in</strong>, imperatives<br />

show a very similar behavior to that of vocatives (e.g. <strong>in</strong> Hebrew, Bat-El 2002, and much of <strong>the</strong><br />

work by Zanutt<strong>in</strong>i & Portner on imperatives and exclamatives).<br />

2. Proposal. In this paper, we suggest that <strong>the</strong> syntactic and <strong>the</strong> phonological puzzles should be<br />

solved <strong>in</strong> tandem, as <strong>the</strong>y are two sides of <strong>the</strong> same issue: <strong>the</strong> exocentric phonological behaviour is<br />

a result of <strong>the</strong> peripheral/external syntactic position and of <strong>the</strong> fact that discourse-related features<br />

(which we will <strong>in</strong>clude among <strong>the</strong> edge features) are read by a different phonological cycle than φ-<br />

and case features. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Zanutt<strong>in</strong>i (2008), we claim that vocatives are different from imperative<br />

subjects. Yet, we ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y are l<strong>in</strong>ked to an [addressee] position, though be<strong>in</strong>g external to<br />

<strong>the</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>e (much like Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky’s adjuncts). Their position is with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> left periphery of <strong>the</strong> clause,<br />

and it is precisely such position which allows for prosodic exponence (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of <strong>in</strong>tonation).<br />

We argue that truncation is – at least <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syste<strong>ms</strong> we are study<strong>in</strong>g here - Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italian dialects<br />

– actually a response to <strong>the</strong> demands of an <strong>in</strong>tonational pattern imposed by <strong>the</strong> [addressee] head.<br />

There is converg<strong>in</strong>g evidence that <strong>the</strong>re are two “submodules” <strong>in</strong> syntax, although authors do not<br />

concur on <strong>the</strong>ir actual implementation: one type is 'core syntax' deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>matic relations etc.<br />

and correspond<strong>in</strong>g roughly to propositional semantics. The o<strong>the</strong>r is ‘peripheral syntax’, and deals<br />

with 'edge features' (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2000 ff.), i.e. features <strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g movement which impacts semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, and corresponds to discourse semantics (topic-focus structure, question formation,<br />

etc.). The fact that <strong>the</strong>se two types of syntax also roughly correlate with different phonological<br />

implementation is less frequently observed, although it see<strong>ms</strong> quite evident: <strong>in</strong> typical non-tonal<br />

languages, (<strong>in</strong>tonational) tone can be used to mark e.g. questions, or focus, but it is never used to<br />

mark e.g. passive formation or number agreement.<br />

The syntactic split has received several types of formalization. Most prom<strong>in</strong>ently, <strong>the</strong>re have been<br />

those who argue that <strong>the</strong> split is somewhere <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntax, so that <strong>the</strong>re are at least two k<strong>in</strong>ds of<br />

syntactic features (φ –and case- features, ma<strong>in</strong>ly active <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> A-doma<strong>in</strong>, and “edge” and discourse<br />

features like Speaker and Addressee, ma<strong>in</strong>ly active <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> left periphery, Speas 2000, 2004;<br />

Sigurðsson 2000, 2001 ff.) correspond<strong>in</strong>g to different semantics (and, we would say, different<br />

phonologies), vs. those who claim that <strong>in</strong>formation structure is only extrasyntactic. We argue that<br />

vocatives shed light on this issue, especially if looked at from a cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic po<strong>in</strong>t of view. On<br />

<strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong>y have many of <strong>the</strong> properties of 'external' syntax, but on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, it is<br />

difficult to l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>m precisely to <strong>in</strong>formation structure, and more importantly, <strong>the</strong>y can also be<br />

expressed <strong>in</strong> some languages by non-<strong>in</strong>tonational morphological means (e.g. <strong>the</strong> special case<br />

end<strong>in</strong>gs of Lat<strong>in</strong> for <strong>the</strong> vocative). We claim that this argues for a syntax-phonology implementation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> split.<br />

3. Data. As observed above, truncation has been attested as <strong>the</strong> phonological exponence of <strong>the</strong><br />

vocative for a number of languages. Here we concentrate on <strong>the</strong> case of Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italian dialects. In<br />

<strong>the</strong>se dialects, a vocative is formed by a prefix (a or o) and a truncated form of <strong>the</strong> DP, which<br />

consists of all <strong>the</strong> phonological material up until and <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> stressed vowel:


(1) a. (A) Mariagiova’! c. (A) Sje’! [Abruzzese]<br />

Mariagiovanna (VOC) Sjef (VOC)<br />

b. (A) Robbe’! d. (A) surelle de lu padre di Giuwa'!<br />

Roberto (VOC) Sister of Giovanni's fa<strong>the</strong>r (VOC)<br />

These examples show that <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al size of <strong>the</strong> DP does not matter: everyth<strong>in</strong>g until <strong>the</strong> stressed<br />

vowel is <strong>in</strong>cluded, and everyth<strong>in</strong>g follow<strong>in</strong>g it (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g coda consonants) is deleted. An analysis<br />

of <strong>the</strong> phenomenon necessarily calls for a syntax-phonology <strong>in</strong>terface analysis.<br />

4. Phonological analysis. Phonologically, <strong>the</strong>re is one major issue to be resolved: <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r curious<br />

shape of <strong>the</strong> truncation. Alber (2010) argues that <strong>the</strong>re are two (OT) Alignment constra<strong>in</strong>ts at work:<br />

one ensur<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> left edge of <strong>the</strong> constituent is preserved, and one mak<strong>in</strong>g sure that <strong>the</strong><br />

truncation ends <strong>in</strong> a stressed vowel. (Yet ano<strong>the</strong>r constra<strong>in</strong>t ensures that everyth<strong>in</strong>g between two<br />

preserved segments is also preserved.) Although this is def<strong>in</strong>itely descriptively adequate, it should<br />

be noted that hav<strong>in</strong>g a constra<strong>in</strong>t align<strong>in</strong>g a stressed vowel with <strong>the</strong> edge of a phrase is somewhat<br />

suspicious for a template. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, phonological accounts so far do not take <strong>in</strong>to account why it<br />

is exactly vocatives that show this behavior. We <strong>the</strong>refore propose a different analysis: <strong>the</strong> exponent<br />

of <strong>the</strong> vocative is (at least) a pitch accent, which is specified for be<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> same time a boundary<br />

tone (i.e. H*%). The fact that it is specified as a pitch accent makes it want to be on <strong>the</strong> stressed<br />

syllable; <strong>the</strong> fact that it is a boundary tone makes it want to be at <strong>the</strong> edge of <strong>the</strong> constituent. The<br />

paradox is resolved by mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> stressed vowel be exactly on <strong>the</strong> edge of <strong>the</strong> constituent – i.e. by<br />

truncation of everyth<strong>in</strong>g follow<strong>in</strong>g it.<br />

5. Syntactic analysis. Although we believe that this phonological account describes <strong>the</strong> truncation<br />

<strong>in</strong> a more elegant way (as well as one which makes more precise predictions about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tonational<br />

pattern), it does not yet expla<strong>in</strong> why truncation patterns are so typical for vocatives (as well as for<br />

imperatives) and why <strong>the</strong>y do not occur for o<strong>the</strong>r morphological cases or verbal tenses. As a po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

of departure for a formalization of <strong>the</strong> 'two syntaxes' mentioned above, we take Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky's (2000)<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between 'edge features' and 'φ-features', where <strong>the</strong> latter seem typical for '<strong>in</strong>ternal'<br />

syntax, and <strong>the</strong> former for 'external syntax'. We take ‘edge features’ to <strong>in</strong>clude all “semantic” and<br />

discourse-related features (i.e. not only topic-focus or wh, but also Speaker and Addressee). We<br />

propose that <strong>the</strong>se two types of features are derivationally dist<strong>in</strong>ct, and syntax has, as it were, two<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependent cycles: first, one <strong>in</strong> which φ-features operate, and afterwards one <strong>in</strong> which edge<br />

features are operative. Each of <strong>the</strong>se two cycles has its own spell-out: <strong>the</strong> former to segmental<br />

phonology (and propositional semantics), <strong>the</strong> second to <strong>in</strong>tonational and o<strong>the</strong>r types of prosodic<br />

phonology (and discourse semantics). The reason why <strong>in</strong>tonation etc. can only play a role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

second cycle is obvious: syntactic heads which phonologically consist of only suprasegmental<br />

material can only be realized if segmental material has already been provided on an earlier cycle. A<br />

model such as this has as its advantage, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, that both modules are syntactic (thus stay<strong>in</strong>g<br />

close to <strong>the</strong> conservative assumption that syntax is <strong>the</strong> sole mediator between phonology and<br />

semantics) while <strong>the</strong>y are also ordered and have different functions (thus captur<strong>in</strong>g some of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>sights of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation structure based accounts).<br />

Vocative 'case' is obviously not assigned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier cycle, s<strong>in</strong>ce it has no connection to <strong>the</strong>matic<br />

structure and is not a structural case <strong>in</strong> any way. We argue that it is assigned by an [addressee] head.<br />

Vocative is <strong>the</strong>refore different from o<strong>the</strong>r morphological cases, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is assigned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 'outer<br />

cycle' of syntax. This opens <strong>the</strong> possibility for it to be realized by <strong>in</strong>tonational tones.<br />

6. Possible extensions. We show how an <strong>in</strong>tonational analysis might also work for some of <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r truncated vocatives of languages of <strong>the</strong> world, as well as possibly to imperatives (which<br />

similarly may be l<strong>in</strong>ked to an [adressee] head).<br />

Selected References<br />

Alber, Birgit. (2010) An exploration of truncation <strong>in</strong> Italian. Rutgers Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> vol. 3: 1-30. Bat-El,<br />

Outi. (2002). True truncation <strong>in</strong> Colloquial Hebrew Imperatives. Language 78.4: 651-665. Cabré, Teresa & Maria del<br />

Mar Vanrell. (2010) Non-templatic truncation: <strong>the</strong> case of vocatives. Cohn, Abby. (2005). Truncation <strong>in</strong> Indonesian.<br />

Evidence for violable m<strong>in</strong>imal words and AnchorRight. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of NELS 34, 175-189. Howell, Mortimer Sloper.<br />

1986. A grammar of <strong>the</strong> Classical Arabic language. Delhi: Gian Publish<strong>in</strong>g House. Jensen, John Thayer. (1977). Yapese<br />

Reference Grammar. Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii. Michael Yadroff (1996). Modern Russian Vocatives: A Case<br />

of Subtractive Morphology. Journal of Slavic <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>, pp. 133-153.


Alexandre Delf<strong>in</strong>o, Maria Luiza Cunha Lima & Pablo Arantes (Universidade Federal de M<strong>in</strong>as Gerais)<br />

Prosodic mark<strong>in</strong>g of referential status <strong>in</strong> Brazilian Portuguese<br />

A ris<strong>in</strong>g trend <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area of reference process<strong>in</strong>g clai<strong>ms</strong> that prosodic and contextual<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation are processed along with grammatical <strong>in</strong>formation as <strong>the</strong> hearer receives<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put. A view widely accepted (Gundel, 1993, <strong>in</strong>ter alia) posits referential<br />

expressions as tak<strong>in</strong>g a whole range of referential statuses. One central question on<br />

<strong>the</strong> production and perception of prosodically-encoded <strong>in</strong>formation structure relates<br />

to determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g which of <strong>the</strong>se different statuses can receive a specific prosodic<br />

counterpart. Different methods have been used to tap <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>se differences, rang<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from phonological descriptions to ERP experiments.<br />

In west Germanic languages as English and German, a three-way dist<strong>in</strong>ction - new,<br />

given and accessible - is said to be dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of prosodic encod<strong>in</strong>g (Baumann,<br />

2006; Baumann & Grice, 2006). Us<strong>in</strong>g ToBI representation, new referents tend<br />

to be marked with a phrasal accent (H*), given referents tend to be deaccented<br />

and accessible referents tend to be marked with an <strong>in</strong>termediate phrase accent<br />

(H+L*). Us<strong>in</strong>g an ERP experiment, Schumacher & Baumann (2010) <strong>in</strong>vestigated<br />

how <strong>the</strong> prosodic <strong>in</strong>formation can affect <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of referents with three<br />

different <strong>in</strong>formational statuses: given, new and accessible. The N400 and latepositivity<br />

results lead <strong>the</strong> authors to conclude that (i) <strong>the</strong> three-way classification<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formational status makes difference not only for production, but also for<br />

perception, and (ii) <strong>the</strong> prosodic <strong>in</strong>formation is processed very early, along with o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

grammatical and context <strong>in</strong>formation.<br />

We propose that <strong>the</strong>se methods can be fruitfully aided by more concrete acoustical<br />

analyses. We also <strong>in</strong>tend to <strong>in</strong>vestigate which acoustic parameters are more heavily<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved with this prosodic mark<strong>in</strong>g. Ano<strong>the</strong>r goal is <strong>the</strong> description of <strong>the</strong> prosody<strong>in</strong>formational<br />

status relationship <strong>in</strong> Brazilian Portuguese, a language scarcely<br />

studied, expand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation about prosody and referential status relationship<br />

to languages different from <strong>the</strong> West Germanic languages. More specifically,<br />

we tried to see if <strong>the</strong> proposed three-folded statuses can be found <strong>in</strong> Brazilian<br />

Portuguese as well.<br />

For this study, we designed a corpus of approximately 30 groups of sentences,<br />

distributed <strong>in</strong>to three conditions: given, new and accessible. For each group<br />

of sentences, we set one target word, which is embedded <strong>in</strong> a control phrase.<br />

Preced<strong>in</strong>g text determ<strong>in</strong>ed if <strong>the</strong> target NP was given, new or accessible. The<br />

sentences below illustrate <strong>the</strong> construction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formational status from <strong>the</strong><br />

context (target words <strong>in</strong> bold):<br />

New<br />

Um terremoto causou destruição em boa parte da costa leste. Várias cidades não<br />

t<strong>in</strong>ham um programa de evacuação, o que deu trabalho para as equipes de resgate.<br />

(An earthquake caused destruction <strong>in</strong> a huge part of <strong>the</strong> East coast. Several cities<br />

did not have an evacuation program, which caused proble<strong>ms</strong> to <strong>the</strong> rescue tea<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

Given<br />

O governo decidiu fechar a us<strong>in</strong>a nuclear após o terremoto ocorrido no mês<br />

passado. O terremoto causou destruição no núcleo do reator, aumentando o risco<br />

de contam<strong>in</strong>ação. (The government decided to shut down <strong>the</strong> nuclear plant after <strong>the</strong><br />

earthquake occurred last month. The earthquake caused destruction to <strong>the</strong> reactor<br />

nucleus, <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> risk of contam<strong>in</strong>ation.)


Acessible<br />

Estudiosos da Sismologia têm procurado analisar os dados de tremores para prever<br />

novas ocorrências. O terremoto causou destruição sem que n<strong>in</strong>guem pudesse se<br />

prevenir.<br />

(Seismology experts have tried to analyse <strong>the</strong> tremors data to predict new<br />

occurences. The earthquake caused destruction without any one be<strong>in</strong>g able to<br />

prevent it.)<br />

Four participants read a list conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g n<strong>in</strong>ety randomized groups of sentences,<br />

presented one by one <strong>in</strong> a computer screen. In order to ascerta<strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong> three<br />

referential statuses have dist<strong>in</strong>ct prosodic patterns, a number of acoustic features<br />

(traditionally seen as correlates of prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence) were analyzed: (a) target<br />

word duration, (b) F0 mean, standard deviation (SD) and range and (c) timenormalized<br />

F0 contours of <strong>the</strong> DP conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> target word. Data from <strong>the</strong> four<br />

subjects were analyzed separately. Analysis of variance was used to determ<strong>in</strong>e if<br />

differences <strong>in</strong> mean values of <strong>the</strong> acoustic parameters were statistically different.<br />

The statistical analysis showed that referential status does not significantly affect<br />

F0 SD and range for all speakers. Mean F0 and word duration were affected by<br />

referential status for three of <strong>the</strong> subjects (new referents have higher mean F0 and<br />

are longer than given and/or accessible ones). Analysis of <strong>the</strong> time-nomalized F0<br />

contours revealed that F0 contours of new referents are different from <strong>the</strong> given and<br />

accessible ones. Despite <strong>in</strong>dividual variability, new referents are characterized by <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of two major pitch peaks, one extend<strong>in</strong>g through <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> of pre-stressed<br />

syllables and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r aligned to <strong>the</strong> stressed syllable. Given and accessible<br />

referents contours are very similar to each o<strong>the</strong>r and tend to: (a) have just one peak,<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r aligned to <strong>the</strong> pre-stressed syllables or to <strong>the</strong> stressed or (b) be relatively<br />

flat. The current results lead us to conclude that from <strong>the</strong> speech production side<br />

prosody plays an important role signal<strong>in</strong>g referential status, ma<strong>in</strong>ly differentiat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

new referents from o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

References<br />

BAUMANN, S. 2006. The Intonation of Givenness - Evidence from German.<br />

L<strong>in</strong>guistische Arbeiten, n.508. Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Niemeyer.<br />

BAUMANN S, GRICE, M. 2006. The <strong>in</strong>tonation of accessibility. Journal of<br />

Pragmatics. v. 38, 1636–1657.<br />

GUNDEL, J. et al. 1993. Cognitive Status and <strong>the</strong> Form of Referr<strong>in</strong>g Expressions. In:<br />

Discourse. Language, v. 69, n. 2, 274-307.<br />

SCHUMACHER, P. & BAUMANN, S. 2010. Pitch accent type affects <strong>the</strong> N400<br />

dur<strong>in</strong>g referencial process<strong>in</strong>g. NeuroReport, vol. 21, n. 9, 618-622.


Ewan Dunbar (Maryland), Brian Dillon (UMass Amherst) & William Idsardi (Maryland)<br />

Learn<strong>in</strong>g phonetic categories by learn<strong>in</strong>g allophony & vice versa: a computational model<br />

We consider <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fant’s early problem of group<strong>in</strong>g signals <strong>in</strong>to phonetic categories, (Werker and<br />

Tees 1984), as well as <strong>the</strong> problem of learn<strong>in</strong>g allophonic processes, and demonstrate how <strong>the</strong>se<br />

relate to Tesar et al.’s (2003) problem of mutual dependence <strong>in</strong> language acquisition: learn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

one component of a full grammatical system affects what <strong>the</strong> (best) hypo<strong>the</strong>ses about some<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r component will be, and vice versa. We present <strong>the</strong> results of an unsupervised Bayesian<br />

statistical model of phonetic category and process learn<strong>in</strong>g which learns categories and grammar<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>tly, allow<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>the</strong> two learn<strong>in</strong>g proble<strong>ms</strong>. We compare our model to<br />

modular learners, which separate phonetic category learn<strong>in</strong>g from grammatical learn<strong>in</strong>g, and<br />

demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> phonetic category learn<strong>in</strong>g problem and <strong>the</strong> grammar learn<strong>in</strong>g problem are<br />

mutually dependent. This implies that standard phonological learn<strong>in</strong>g models cannot be taken<br />

at face value, because, as <strong>the</strong>y are conventionally formulated, <strong>the</strong>y take <strong>in</strong>puts pre-categorized<br />

<strong>in</strong>to phones or features, and thus build <strong>in</strong> an implicit modularity assumption. We show fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

that our model succeeds <strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g contextual rules without observ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> contexts <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves.<br />

In particular, we consider data from Inuktitut (Eskimo-Aleut, Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Canada), a language<br />

with a three-vowel system. Uvular consonants trigger allophony for all three vowels: before<br />

[q] and [K], /i u a/ → [e o A] respectively (see Figure 1). We use phonetic data elicited from a<br />

native speaker (F1 × F2, segmented; Denis and Pollard 2008) and fit a Bayesian model of phonetic<br />

category syste<strong>ms</strong> as simple dependent Dirichlet processes (Ferguson 1973; MacEachern<br />

1999). Each category is a multivariate Gaussian distribution which is shifted by some amount<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of a uvular. (The shift is a real vector, i.e., we model <strong>the</strong> allophonic process as<br />

sub-categorical; see Port and O’Dell 1986; Cohn 1990.) The output of learn<strong>in</strong>g is a system of<br />

categories and processes learned jo<strong>in</strong>tly. The model is unsupervised: it learns <strong>the</strong> number of<br />

categories, <strong>the</strong>ir locations and shapes, and <strong>the</strong> degree of pre-uvular retraction per category, entirely<br />

on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> statistics of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put. In Model 1, <strong>the</strong> learner is told whe<strong>the</strong>r each token<br />

preceded a uvular. The learner f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> three vowel phonemes of Inuktitut (Figure 2) with results<br />

more accurate than a standard phonetic category model (Dirichlet process mixture model,<br />

e.g. <strong>the</strong> distributional learn<strong>in</strong>g algorithm of Feldman et al. 2009, F statistic for classification<br />

0.75 for our model vs 0.69 for <strong>the</strong> standard model, 12 runs; t = 4.26, p < 0.001). Crucially, if<br />

we encourage a distributional learner to f<strong>in</strong>d more categories, lead<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> discovery of all six<br />

allophones, and <strong>the</strong>n use <strong>the</strong>se categories’ context distributions as <strong>in</strong>put to <strong>the</strong> GLA (Boersma<br />

1997) or <strong>the</strong> statistical allophone learn<strong>in</strong>g model of Peperkamp et al. (2006), we fail to learn <strong>the</strong><br />

relevant categorical rule, as <strong>the</strong> learned allophones are too poorly aligned with <strong>the</strong> true ones.<br />

In Model 2, <strong>the</strong> learner is not told whe<strong>the</strong>r a uvular followed, but only <strong>the</strong> approximate frequency<br />

of follow<strong>in</strong>g uvulars. This simulates a learner who has not fully learned to categorize<br />

<strong>the</strong> relevant features of <strong>the</strong> context, or one who is learn<strong>in</strong>g a language <strong>in</strong> which a trigger<strong>in</strong>g<br />

environment is obscured by a later process <strong>in</strong> a counterbleed<strong>in</strong>g relation. This model succeeds<br />

<strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> vowels of Inuktitut and simultaneously discover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> uvular/non-uvular dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

only by observ<strong>in</strong>g vowel tokens (Figure 3). As before, <strong>the</strong> model f<strong>in</strong>ds three categories<br />

and three rules (although it cannot reliably determ<strong>in</strong>e which phones are <strong>the</strong> output and which<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put of <strong>the</strong> rules). We show that this is not an accident of Inuktitut uvulars, and that <strong>the</strong><br />

model also learns a subset of English vowel categories along with systematic sex differences <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> pronunciations of those vowels, without observ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sex of <strong>the</strong> speaker.<br />

Our results demonstrate that (1) allophony and o<strong>the</strong>r contextual effects are crucial <strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

phonetic categories; (2) <strong>the</strong> shape of phonetic categories <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves can be helpful <strong>in</strong> detect<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> effects of context. This mutual dependence is consistent with <strong>the</strong> strongly <strong>in</strong>teractive<br />

character of category identification <strong>in</strong> speech perception (Liberman et al., 1953; Whalen et al.,<br />

1997). We conclude that this lack of strong modularity extends to learn<strong>in</strong>g.


Figure 1 Figure 2 Figure 3<br />

Figure 1: Phones of Inuktitut; [e], [A] and [o] are allophonically related to [i], [a], and [u].<br />

Figure 2: Output of Model 1. Dotted l<strong>in</strong>es: categories shifted by learned contextual rules.<br />

Figure 3: Output of Model 2 (contextual rules learned without knowledge of context).<br />

References<br />

de Boer, B., and P. Kuhl. 2003. Investigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>in</strong>fant-directed speech with a<br />

computer model. Acoustics Research Letters Onl<strong>in</strong>e 4.129–134.<br />

Boersma, P. How we learn variation, optionality, and probability. IFA Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs 21.37–42.<br />

Cohn, A. 1990. Phonetic and phonological rules of nasalization. UCLA dissertation.<br />

Denis, D., and M. Pollard. 2008. An Acoustic Analysis of The Vowel Space of Inuktitut.<br />

Presented at Inuktitut <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> Workshop, University of Toronto.<br />

Feldman, N., T. Griffiths, and J. Morgan. 2009. Learn<strong>in</strong>g Phonetic Categories by Learn<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

Lexicon. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of 31st Annual Conference of Cognitive Science Society 2208–2213.<br />

Ferguson, T. 1973. Bayesian analysis of nonparametric proble<strong>ms</strong>. Ann. of Stats 1.209–230.<br />

Liberman, M., and J. Pierrehumbert. 1984. Intonational <strong>in</strong>variance under changes <strong>in</strong> pitch<br />

range and length. In Language sound and structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.<br />

MacEachearn, S. 1999. Dependent nonparametric processes. ASA Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> Section<br />

on Bayesian Statistical Science 50–55.<br />

McMurray, B., R. Asl<strong>in</strong>, and J. Toscano. 2009. Statistical learn<strong>in</strong>g of phonetic categories:<br />

Insights from a computational approach. Developmental Science 12.369–78.<br />

Peperkamp, S., R. Le Calvez, J-P. Nadal, and E. Dupoux. 2006. The acquisition of allophonic<br />

rules: statistical learn<strong>in</strong>g with l<strong>in</strong>guistic constra<strong>in</strong>ts. Cognition 101.B31–B41.<br />

Port, R., and M. O’Dell. 1986. Neutralization of syllable-f<strong>in</strong>al voic<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> German. J. of<br />

Phonetics 13.455–471.<br />

Teh, YW, M. Jordan, M. Beal, and D. Blei. 2006. Hierarchical Dirichlet processes. Journal of<br />

<strong>the</strong> American Statistical Association 101.1566–1581.<br />

Tesar, B., J. Alderete, G. Horwood, N. Merchant, K. Nishitani, and A. Pr<strong>in</strong>ce. 2003. Surgery <strong>in</strong><br />

language learn<strong>in</strong>g. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> 22nd West Coast Conference on Formal <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>.<br />

Vallabha, G., J. McClelland, F. Pons, J. Werker, and S. Amano. 2007. Unsupervised learn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of vowel categories from <strong>in</strong>fant-directed speech. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> National Academy of<br />

Sciences of <strong>the</strong> United States of America 104.13273–8.<br />

Werker, J., and R. Tees. 1984. Cross-language speech perception: Evidence for perceptual<br />

reorganization dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> first year of life. Infant Behavior and Development 7.49–63.


Francesca Foppolo (Milano-Bicocca), Marco Marelli (Milano-Bicocca), Luisa Meroni (Utrecht) & Andrea Gualm<strong>in</strong>i (Utrecht)<br />

Pars<strong>in</strong>g Semantic Ambiguity: strategies and commitments<br />

Consider sentence (1) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scenario <strong>in</strong> Fig. 1:<br />

(1) The small square is <strong>the</strong> only one that is a policeman<br />

Sentence (1) is ambiguous depend<strong>in</strong>g on what referent is<br />

considered for one: ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> set of all geometrical<br />

figures/th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context (exhophoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation)<br />

or <strong>the</strong> set of squares (anaphoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation). The way<br />

we <strong>in</strong>terpret one has an effect on <strong>the</strong> truth value of <strong>the</strong><br />

whole sentence: (1) is True if we <strong>in</strong>terpret one<br />

anaphorically (amongst <strong>the</strong> squares, <strong>the</strong> small one is<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed <strong>the</strong> only one to be a policeman) but it is False if<br />

we <strong>in</strong>terpret one exophorically (<strong>in</strong> fact, amongst <strong>the</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context, <strong>the</strong> small square is not <strong>the</strong> only one<br />

to be a policeman).<br />

Fig.1<br />

Test<strong>in</strong>g children and adults with sentences similar to (1), Cra<strong>in</strong> et.al. (1994) concluded that<br />

����������� ������� �������� �� ��������� ������������ - ��<br />

exhophoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation) while �������� ������� ��� ��������� �������<br />

choose <strong>the</strong> weaker-anaphoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation). We <strong>in</strong>tend to argue aga<strong>in</strong>st this conclusion on <strong>the</strong> basis<br />

of two experimental studies <strong>in</strong> which we show that adults do not conform to a M<strong>in</strong>imal<br />

Commitment strategy (Exp.1) or to a Maximal Commitment strategy (Exp. 2).<br />

We conclude by propos<strong>in</strong>g a more general pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of process<strong>in</strong>g and ambiguity resolution that<br />

<strong>in</strong>structs <strong>the</strong> parser to consider <strong>the</strong> highest number of available referents .<br />

Our experimental studies. We tested two groups of Italian speak<strong>in</strong>g adults by means of two<br />

studies employ<strong>in</strong>g a Visual <strong>World</strong> Paradigm <strong>in</strong> which subjects were asked to judge a series of<br />

sentences (as True or False) relatively to a scenario while <strong>the</strong>ir eye-movements were recorded. The<br />

rationale beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> two experiments was <strong>the</strong> same: sentences were presented auditorily aga<strong>in</strong>st a<br />

visual scenario similar to <strong>the</strong> one <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> Fig. 1 display<strong>in</strong>g 4 sets of geometrical figures, letters or<br />

digits. We tested 30 were critical statements like (1) that conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> ambiguous expression è<br />

�����������<br />

(is <strong>the</strong> only one) that needed to be <strong>in</strong>terpreted. The scenario used <strong>in</strong> both experiments<br />

was identical, but <strong>the</strong> two experiments differed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence/absence of negation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

For example, (1) was given <strong>in</strong> Exp.1 aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> scenario <strong>in</strong> Fig. 1 and (5) was given <strong>in</strong> Exp. 2:<br />

(5) The small square is not <strong>the</strong> only one that is a policeman<br />

We also tested 36 unambiguous true and false control sentences �������������<br />

All/Three/None/Some<br />

of <strong>the</strong> N-(Adj) is do<strong>in</strong>g P������ varied with respect to <strong>the</strong> type of exploration strategy required to<br />

evaluate <strong>the</strong>m: (a) controls �������������������<br />

required <strong>the</strong> exploration of <strong>the</strong> whole scenario to be<br />

judged true or false: e.g., to evaluate (2) All <strong>the</strong> yellow numbers are k<strong>in</strong>gs one needs to check all <strong>the</strong><br />

yellow ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scenario to make sure that all of <strong>the</strong>m are k<strong>in</strong>gs; (b) controls ���������������<br />

required <strong>the</strong> exploration of only one of <strong>the</strong> quadrants <strong>in</strong> order to come up with a decision: e.g., to<br />

evaluate (3) Three crosses are play<strong>in</strong>g football, it suffices to check only <strong>the</strong> quadrant that conta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

crosses; (c) controls �������� ������ an exploration ��������� at random <strong>in</strong> order to f<strong>in</strong>d a<br />

counterexample and tell if <strong>the</strong> sentence was true or false: e.g., to evaluate (4) None of <strong>the</strong> blue<br />

letters are happy ��������������<br />

suffices to f<strong>in</strong>d a letter that is blue and happy and <strong>the</strong>n stop explor<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Crucially, <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical sentences presented <strong>in</strong> Experiment 2 reverses<br />

<strong>the</strong> entailment pattern between <strong>the</strong> two <strong>in</strong>terpretations, so that <strong>the</strong> anaphoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation becomes<br />

<strong>the</strong> strongest: if ambiguity resolution were based on <strong>the</strong> entailment relationship between <strong>the</strong>


alternative read<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong>n an opposite pattern of exploration should be expected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two<br />

experiments. In particular, if adults followed a M<strong>in</strong>imal Commitment strategy, as Cra<strong>in</strong> et al.<br />

suggest, <strong>the</strong>y should always select <strong>the</strong> weakest <strong>in</strong>terpretation, <strong>the</strong> one that makes <strong>the</strong> sentence True.<br />

This corresponds to <strong>the</strong> anaphoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> Exp. 1 (it is true that <strong>the</strong> small square is <strong>the</strong> only<br />

square that is a policeman) but to <strong>the</strong> exophoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> Exp. 2 (it is true that <strong>the</strong> small<br />

square is not <strong>the</strong> only th<strong>in</strong>g that is a policeman).<br />

Results. ������� acceptance rate of <strong>the</strong> critical sentences was below 10% <strong>in</strong> Exp. 1 and above 90%<br />

<strong>in</strong> Exp. 2. This shows that <strong>the</strong>y always <strong>in</strong>terpreted one exhophorically, <strong>in</strong>dependently of <strong>the</strong><br />

entailment pattern between <strong>in</strong>terpretations: i.e., <strong>the</strong>y do not conform to a M<strong>in</strong>imal or to a Maximal<br />

Commitment strategy. The pattern of exploration revelaed by <strong>the</strong> eye-movement record<strong>in</strong>gs is<br />

consistent with this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis: <strong>in</strong> both studies, towards <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> sentence, subjects followed<br />

an exploration pattern that ���������� ���� ��������� <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y had �������<br />

to look for a<br />

counterexample and all quadrants had equal probability to be looked at, and differed significantly<br />

����� ���� ���������� <strong>in</strong> which fixations ����������<br />

were concentrated on a s<strong>in</strong>gle quadrant (Fig. 2,<br />

based on Exp. 1 as an example).<br />

critical trials ����������������� ������������������������������<br />

Fig. 2. The proportion to looks to target/quadrant 1 (arbitrary chosen) are plotted as a function of <strong>the</strong> sentence timecourse:<br />

IP1 (from 0 to red l<strong>in</strong>e) correspond to <strong>the</strong> (Q)N+Adj segment (e.g. The small square); IP2 (<strong>in</strong> between <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es)<br />

corresponds to <strong>the</strong> critical segment is <strong>the</strong> only one that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical trials and to a short pause <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> controls; IP3:<br />

(from green l<strong>in</strong>e to <strong>the</strong> end) corresponds to <strong>the</strong> whole VP (e.g. is a policeman).<br />

Instead of focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> quadrant of <strong>the</strong> squares (anaphoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation), adults moved around<br />

to check for <strong>the</strong> truth/falsity of <strong>the</strong> exhophoric <strong>in</strong>terpretation, as if <strong>the</strong>y were scann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

scenario <strong>in</strong> search of a counterexample. This result was corroborated by a series of logistic<br />

regression models <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> likelihood of look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> target quadrant was modeled as a<br />

function of <strong>the</strong> strategy of exploration (cf. Table 1, based on Exp. 1 as an example): <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

period (IP4), after <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> sentence, <strong>the</strong> proportion of looks to target <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

��������������������������������������������������<br />

=.182).<br />

IP 1 IP 2 IP 3 IP 4<br />

Table 1 Estimate p Estimate p Estimate p Estimate p<br />

critical trials -.37 .0397 .71 .0001 -.34 .0037 -.58 .0001<br />

controls ����� -.97 .0269 -2.08 .0001 -1.08 .0001 -.35 .1820<br />

controls ��������� -.69 .0351 -1.79 .0001 -0.71 .0001 -.47 .0154<br />

controls ���������-1.04<br />

.0005 -.71 .0011 1.72 .0001 1.21 .0001<br />

Conclusions. We found no evidence of a bias that would be based on <strong>the</strong> truth value of <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

under consideration or <strong>the</strong> entailment relationship between <strong>the</strong>m: <strong>in</strong> both studies, adults <strong>in</strong>terpreted<br />

one exhophorically, always consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> whole scenario. This f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> conjunction with<br />

�������������������������������������������������������<br />

<strong>the</strong> need to postulate a preference for<br />

<strong>the</strong> strong read<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> same sentences <strong>in</strong> children, <strong>in</strong>vites us to consider whe<strong>the</strong>r such truth<br />

conditional properties play any role <strong>in</strong> ambiguity resolution. Instead, our f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs suggest that<br />

adults follow a more general pars<strong>in</strong>g strategy <strong>in</strong> solv<strong>in</strong>g semantic ambiguity: when a (visual/rich)<br />

context is given, <strong>the</strong> parser maximally exploits it.


Michael Freedman (Yale)<br />

Contextual Disambiguation of Have-Sentences<br />

Background: Have-sentences can encode relations that express k<strong>in</strong>ship (1a), part-whole (1b),<br />

possessor-possessee (1c), and conta<strong>in</strong>er-conta<strong>in</strong>ee (1d) relationships. They also seem to be able<br />

to encode completely context dependent relations (1e).<br />

(1) (a) KINSHIP: John has a sister. (Partee, 1999)<br />

(b) PART-WHOLE/INALIENABLE POSSESSION: John has a hand.<br />

(c) TRUE POSSESSION/CONTROL: John has a pen.<br />

(d) CONTAINER: That glass has w<strong>in</strong>e. (Gutierrez-Rexach, 2006)<br />

(e) ASSIGNMENT (BY CONTEXT): Eliza has <strong>the</strong> mirror (to wash). (Tham, 2004)<br />

Problem: A subset of have-sentences are ambiguous <strong>in</strong> what relation <strong>the</strong>y express (table 1). But<br />

it is clear that one read<strong>in</strong>g is available out-of-<strong>the</strong>-blue, which I will refer to as <strong>in</strong>herently salient.<br />

Because <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r read<strong>in</strong>g(s) need context to become salient; I will call <strong>the</strong>se contextually licensed.<br />

The questions that I aim to address are (1) what mechanism expla<strong>in</strong>s why certa<strong>in</strong> read<strong>in</strong>gs are <strong>in</strong>herently<br />

salient and (2) what is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction with context that expla<strong>in</strong>s when <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r (contextually<br />

licensed) read<strong>in</strong>gs become available.<br />

Sentence <strong>in</strong>herently salient contextually licensed<br />

John has a sister k<strong>in</strong>ship control, assignment(?)<br />

John has a d<strong>in</strong>osaur tail part-whole/control<br />

Eliza has a mirror. control assignment<br />

The dumpster has a hand part-whole conta<strong>in</strong>er<br />

Table 1: Have-sentences and <strong>the</strong>ir possible read<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

In this paper, I argue that a pragmatic filter can disambiguate <strong>the</strong> different read<strong>in</strong>gs of havesentences<br />

and that <strong>the</strong> amount of ambiguity present comes not only from <strong>the</strong> underspecification<br />

of <strong>the</strong> relation encoded by have but by <strong>the</strong> context dependence of some verbal complements.<br />

Analysis: Assume that have encodes a relation between <strong>in</strong>dividuals (cf. Beavers et al. (2008),<br />

Partee (1999)). Relational nouns <strong>the</strong>n need to be treated as properties (type 〈e, t〉) <strong>in</strong> order for <strong>the</strong><br />

ord<strong>in</strong>ary derivation of sentences with transitive verbs to take place. I treat relational nouns as this<br />

type (〈e, t〉) but with a free contextual argument, follow<strong>in</strong>g work on o<strong>the</strong>r relational predicates like<br />

local and w<strong>in</strong> (Condoravdi & Gawron (1996)). Concretely, have is treated as an underspecified<br />

relation fixed by an assignment function (as <strong>in</strong> (2d)) and a relational noun is represented as a relation<br />

that has a free variable as an argument (as <strong>in</strong> (2a)). A full compositional treatment of <strong>the</strong> sentence<br />

John has a sister is provided <strong>in</strong> (2):<br />

(2) (a) [sister]= λx.sister(x,y), where <strong>the</strong> value of y is fixed by an assignment function.<br />

(b) [a]= λPλQ∃z[P(z) ∧ Q(z)]<br />

(c) [a sister]= λQ∃z[sister(c,z) ∧ Q(z) ]<br />

(d) [have](type-raised) = λPλw[P(λv[π(w,v)])]<br />

where π is an underspecified relation fixed by an assignment function.<br />

(e) [have a sister]= λPλw[P(λv[π(w,v)])](λQ∃z[sister(c,z) ∧ Q(z) ])<br />

= λw[∃z[sister(c,z) ∧ π(w,z)]]<br />

(f) [John]= j<br />

(g) [John has a sister]= λw[∃z[sister(c,z) ∧ π(w,z)]](j)<br />

= ∃z[sister(c,z) ∧ π(j,z)]<br />

A pragmatic mechanism is necessary because simply posit<strong>in</strong>g a context variable makes no<br />

predictions on what relation <strong>the</strong> variable will express. I will assume a question-based model of<br />

discourse (QUD) (Roberts, 2006) <strong>in</strong> order to resolve <strong>the</strong> variables <strong>in</strong> have and <strong>in</strong> relational nouns;


<strong>in</strong> addition, I will have <strong>the</strong> discourse model track what elements (<strong>in</strong>dividuals, relations) are salient<br />

(similar to Grosz & Sidner, 1986). Salient <strong>in</strong>dividuals are <strong>the</strong> set of <strong>in</strong>dividuals and salient relations<br />

are <strong>the</strong> set of relations that have been <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> discourse ei<strong>the</strong>r explicitly or through<br />

<strong>the</strong> use of discourse questions. The QUD is <strong>the</strong> current question that needs to be addressed <strong>in</strong><br />

some way as <strong>the</strong> next “move” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discourse. In addition, I assume that <strong>the</strong>re is a default relation<br />

that have expresses when <strong>the</strong>re is no context; CONTROL is <strong>the</strong> default when <strong>the</strong> subject is animate.<br />

This relation is a reasonable default because it is closest to <strong>the</strong> core notion of possession. I will go<br />

through three cases to illustrate how <strong>the</strong> system works:<br />

Case 1 (In context): In a standard discourse <strong>the</strong> resolution of have and relational nouns is determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>tly by what is salient and what <strong>the</strong> current question is. The variable associated with have<br />

resolves to a salient relation, if <strong>the</strong>re is a relational noun, <strong>the</strong> variable associated with it resolves<br />

to a salient <strong>in</strong>dividual, and <strong>the</strong> sentence as a whole addresses <strong>the</strong> current question under discussion.<br />

In (3), <strong>the</strong> QUD is “where are <strong>the</strong> victim’s ar<strong>ms</strong>”, <strong>the</strong> salient relations are <strong>the</strong> hand-relation (from<br />

<strong>the</strong> utterance) and <strong>the</strong> conta<strong>in</strong>er relation (based on <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> locative <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> QUD), and <strong>the</strong><br />

only salient <strong>in</strong>dividual is <strong>the</strong> victim. π is resolved to <strong>the</strong> conta<strong>in</strong>er-relation because <strong>the</strong> relation is<br />

salient and because with that relation <strong>the</strong> QUD is partially answered (<strong>the</strong> subquestion “where is<br />

one of <strong>the</strong> victim’s hands” is answered); c resolves to <strong>the</strong> victim because <strong>the</strong> victim is salient and<br />

because it is coherent as part of a response that partially answers <strong>the</strong> QUD. This example shows<br />

how a CONTAINER read<strong>in</strong>g for have can be contexutally licensed.<br />

(3) Scenario: Two police detectives John and Mary are at a crime scene<br />

<strong>in</strong> an alley. A murder victim has been dismembered and <strong>the</strong> detectives are look<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong><br />

victim’s rema<strong>in</strong>s. John asks “where are his ar<strong>ms</strong>?” Mary replies “that dumpster has a hand”.<br />

(4)<br />

QUD: Where are <strong>the</strong> victim’s ar<strong>ms</strong>?<br />

Salient sets: hand(x,y), conta<strong>in</strong>s(x,y)<br />

Salient <strong>in</strong>dividuals: <strong>the</strong> victim<br />

QUD relevant = conta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

⇒ c = <strong>the</strong> victim, π = conta<strong>in</strong>s(x,y)<br />

Case 2 (Out-of-<strong>the</strong>-blue): In out-of-<strong>the</strong>-blue scenarios, <strong>the</strong>re is no QUD and no salient <strong>in</strong>dividuals<br />

or relations prior to <strong>the</strong> first utterance of <strong>the</strong> discourse. In a sentence without a relational noun,<br />

<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of have will assume a default value of CONTROL (for animates) or CONTAINER (for<br />

<strong>in</strong>animates). For <strong>in</strong>stance, if person A says to person B out-of-<strong>the</strong>-blue “I have a pen” <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no QUD, and no salient relations. Person B can give mean<strong>in</strong>g to person B’s utterance by giv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a value to π which comes from what rema<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> “bleached” default lexical mean<strong>in</strong>g of have<br />

(CONTROL). This example shows why have expresses a CONTROL relation when <strong>the</strong>re is no prior<br />

discourse context and <strong>the</strong> subject is animate.<br />

Case 3 (Inherently salient w/ relational noun complement): If <strong>the</strong>re is a relational noun <strong>in</strong> object<br />

position, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> relation associated with <strong>the</strong> relational noun gets added to <strong>the</strong> list of salient<br />

relations and becomes a suitable relation for have to express and so π is resolved to that relation.<br />

The resolution of <strong>the</strong> variable associated with <strong>the</strong> relational noun will be to an <strong>in</strong>dividual that is<br />

salient <strong>in</strong> that utterance (i.e. <strong>the</strong> subject). So, if out-of-<strong>the</strong>-blue Speaker A says to Speaker B “I have<br />

a sister”, <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of have resolves to <strong>the</strong> sister relation. The c variable resolves to <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

because<strong>the</strong> subject is <strong>the</strong> only salient <strong>in</strong>dividual. This example shows why have takes <strong>the</strong> relation<br />

of its complement if <strong>the</strong>re is no discourse context and <strong>the</strong> complement is a relational noun.<br />

Selected References: Beavers, J., S. Wechsler, and E. Ponvert. (2008) Possession of a controlled substantive: Light<br />

have and verbs of possession. Condoravdi, C. & Gawron, J.M. (1996). The context-dependency of implicit arguments.<br />

Grosz, B. & Sidner, L. (1986) Attentions, Inentions, and <strong>the</strong> Structure of Discourse. Gutierrez-Rexach, J. (2006).<br />

Beyond <strong>the</strong> (<strong>in</strong>)def<strong>in</strong>iteness restriction: A unified semantics for have. Partee, B. (1999). Weak NP’s <strong>in</strong> HAVE Sentences.<br />

Roberts, C. (1996) Information Structure <strong>in</strong> Discourse. Tham, S. (2004) The Def<strong>in</strong>iteness Effect <strong>in</strong> English Have<br />

Sentences.


Long­distance
Anaphora
<strong>in</strong>
Mandar<strong>in</strong>,
<strong>the</strong>
PCC,
and
Cyclic
Agree
<br />

Mandar<strong>in</strong>
conta<strong>in</strong>s
a
reflexive
form,
ziji,
that
can
function
as
a
local
reflexive.
However,
<br />

ziji
can
also
take
an
antecedent
outside
its
local
doma<strong>in</strong>.
As
shown
<strong>in</strong>
(1a‐e),
ziji
can
be
<br />

bound
 by
 <strong>the</strong>
 closest
 subject
 or
 <strong>the</strong>
 matrix
 subject
 (Cole,
 et
 al.,
 2006
 and
 references
<br />

<strong>the</strong>re<strong>in</strong>).
Such
long‐distance
b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
is
constra<strong>in</strong>ed
by
a
block<strong>in</strong>g
effect,
such
that
subject
<br />

DPs
that
differ
<strong>in</strong>
person
features
appear
to
block
higher
subject
DPs
from
b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
ziji.
<br />

However,
a
difference
<strong>in</strong>
person
features
is
not
a
sufficient
condition
for
<strong>the</strong>
block<strong>in</strong>g
<br />

effect.
 Instead,
 we
 see
 that
 subjects
 <strong>in</strong>
 a
 1>3
 configuration
 allow
 long‐distance
<br />

antecedents
but
subjects
<strong>in</strong>
a
3>1
configuration
block
long‐distance
antecedents.
Thus,
<br />

<strong>the</strong>
 <strong>in</strong>terference
 pattern
 that
 emerges
 <strong>in</strong>
 <strong>the</strong>
 block<strong>in</strong>g
 effect
 is
 not
 symmetrical
 (see
<br />

examples
(1a‐g)).

<br />


<br />

1)
<br />

a)

 Zhangsani
zhidao
Lisij
bu


xihuan
zijii/j
 e)
 Nii





zhidao
Lisij

bu


xihuan
zijii/j
<br />


 Zhagshan

know


Lisi

not

like






self
 
 You



know


Lisi


not

like






self
<br />

‘Zhangsan
 knew
 that
 Lisi
 did
 not
 like
 ‘You
 knew
 that
 Lisi
 did
 not
 like


<br />

me/hi<strong>ms</strong>elf’
<br />

you/hi<strong>ms</strong>elf
<br />

b)
 Woi
zhidao
Lisij
bu


xihuan
zijii/j
 f)
 Lisii



zhidao

Woj



bu


xihuan
ziji*i/j
<br />


 I






know


Lisi

not

like






self
<br />


 Lisi




know



I









not

like






self
<br />

‘I
 knew
 that
 Lisi
 did
 not
 like
 ‘Lisi
 knew
 that
 I
 did
 not
 like
<br />

me/hi<strong>ms</strong>elf
<br />

*him/myself’
<br />

c)
 Woi





zhidao
Nij



bu


xihuan
zijii/j
 g)
 Lisii





zhidao
Nij



bu


xihuan
ziji*i/j
<br />


 I











know


you

not

like






self
 
 Lisi






know


you

not

like






self
<br />

‘I
 knew
 that
 you
 did
 not
 like
 ‘Lisi
 knew
 that
 you
 did
 not
 like
<br />

me/yourself’
<br />

*him/yourself’
<br />

d)
 Nii




zhidao
Woj
bu


xihuan
zijii/j
 
<br />


 You


know


I






not

like






self
<br />

‘You
 knew
 that
 I
 did
 not
 like
<br />

you/myself’
<br />


<br />

Strik<strong>in</strong>gly,
this
<strong>in</strong>terference
pattern
replicates
a
pattern
of
<strong>in</strong>tervention
that
is
known
as
<br />

<strong>the</strong>
 person­case
 constra<strong>in</strong>t.
 Anagnostopoulou
 characterizes
 <strong>the</strong>
 PCC
 such
 that
 “[i]n
 a
<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation
of
a
weak
direct
object
and
an
<strong>in</strong>direct
object
[clitic,
agreement
marker,
or
<br />

weak
pronoun],
if
<strong>the</strong>re
is
a
third
person
it
has
to
be
<strong>the</strong>
direct
object”
(2005,
p.
203).
<br />

Compare
Tables
1
and
2.
<br />


<br />

INDIRECT

 DIRECT

 PCC
 
 HIGHEST
SUBJECT
 LOWEST
SUBJECT
 ZIJI
<br />

OBJECT
<br />

1
<br />

OBJECT
<br />

3
 �
<br />


<br />

PERSON
<br />

1
<br />

PERSON
<br />

3
<br />

LDR
<br />

�
<br />

1
<br />

2
<br />

2
<br />

1
<br />

�
<br />

�
<br />


 1
<br />

2
<br />

2
<br />

1
<br />

�
<br />

�
<br />

2
 3
 �
 
 2
 3
 �
<br />

3
 1
 �
<br />

3
 1
 �
<br />

3
 2
 �
 
 3
 2
 �
<br />

Table
1
–
Interference
pattern
for
PCC
 
 







Table
2
–
Interference
pattern
for
ziji
<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g
an
analysis
<strong>in</strong>
Cole,
et
al.
(2006),
I
propose
that
long‐distance
b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
of
ziji
is
<br />

<strong>the</strong>
result
of
covert
head
movement
and
that
ziji
is
sensitive
to
person
hierarchies
as
<br />

conceived

<strong>in</strong>
Bejar
and
Rezac
(2009).
These
two
facts
restrict
<strong>the</strong>
configurations
that
<br />

license
<strong>the</strong>
long‐distance
b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
of
ziji.
<br />


<br />

Ia<strong>in</strong> Gibl<strong>in</strong> (MIT)


2)
 [IP
Zhangsan
[I
zijii
]
[VP
yiwei
[IP
Lisi
[I
t’i
]
[VP
pip<strong>in</strong>g‐le
ti
]
]
]
]
<br />


 




Zhangsan



self









th<strong>in</strong>k






Lisi

















criticize‐Perf
<br />

In
 (2)
 above,
 each
 I0 
 agrees
 with
 its
 specifier
 and
 ziji
 must
 <strong>the</strong>refore
 agree
 with
 <strong>the</strong>
<br />

subject
 upon
 adjunction
 to
 I0 .
 
 However,
 if
 ziji’s
 ϕ‐features
 are
 structured
 so
 <strong>the</strong>y
 are
<br />

sensitive
to
<strong>the</strong>
person
hierarchies
of
Bejar
and
Rezac
(2009,
see
Table
3
below)
we
can
<br />

generate
<strong>the</strong>
block<strong>in</strong>g
effect
and
its
asymmetrical
structure.
<br />


<br />

Table 2<br />

Person specifications<br />

C Y C L I C A G R E E 43<br />

A: Person specifications B: Shorthand 1�2�3 C: Shorthand 2�1�3<br />

3rd 2nd 1st 3rd 2nd 1st 3rd 2nd 1st<br />


<br />


<br />

Table
3
–
Bejar
and
Rezac
person
hierarchy
/
articulated
probe
<br />

Let
us
assume
that
ziji
is
a
partially
articulated
probe
that
searches
for
[participant]
and
<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore
seeks
to
check
[3][2].
In
1/2
>
3
configurations
movement
of
ziji
to
<strong>the</strong>
lowest
<br />

I0 
 checks
 <strong>the</strong>
 [3]
 segment
 of
 <strong>the</strong>
 anaphor
 <strong>the</strong>refore
 allow<strong>in</strong>g
 ziji
 to
 be
 valued
 by
 I0 .
<br />

However,
this
leaves
an
unchecked
[2].
Thus,
<strong>the</strong>
unchecked
[2]
on
<strong>the</strong>
anaphor
licenses
<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r
movement
of
ziji
to
<strong>the</strong>
higher
I0 
<strong>in</strong>
search
of
a
[+participant]
argument.
If
<strong>the</strong>
<br />

higher
I0 
has
obta<strong>in</strong>ed
[+participant]
features
through
agreement
with
<strong>the</strong>
subject,
<strong>the</strong>n
<br />

ziji
can
adjo<strong>in</strong>
to
<strong>the</strong>
higher
I0 
and
valuation
can
take
place.
Thus,
a
higher
argument
can
<br />

be
 [+participant]
 and
 a
 lower
 argument
 can
 be
 [‐participant].
 However,
 <strong>the</strong>
 converse
<br />

does
 not
 hold.
 If
 ziji
 first
 adjo<strong>in</strong>s
 to
 an
 I0 
 that
 is
 [+participant]
 both
 of
 ziji’s
 person
<br />

features
 ([3]
 and
 [2])
 will
 be
 checked
 leav<strong>in</strong>g
 no
 residue
 that
 would
 license
 fur<strong>the</strong>r
<br />

movement
(unless
<strong>the</strong>
higher
I0 
agrees
for
[+participant]).
Thus,
a
higher
[3]
argument
<br />

is
<strong>in</strong>accessible
because
<strong>the</strong>
anaphor
has
been
marked
as
[+participant]
and
<strong>the</strong>
higher
I0 [�] [�] [�] [3] [3] [3] [3] [3] [3]<br />

[participant] [participant] [2] [2] [1] [1]<br />

[speaker] [1] [2]<br />

(structure) [F] entails a feature (structure) [F′] if and only if [F′] is a subset (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g identity)<br />

of <strong>the</strong> least set conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g [F]. For example, be<strong>in</strong>g specified as [speaker] entails be<strong>in</strong>g specified as<br />

[participant] and as [�].<br />


<br />

is
[‐participant].

<br />

The
proposed
analysis
has
some
welcome
consequences.
Firstly,
it
expla<strong>in</strong>s
<strong>the</strong>
block<strong>in</strong>g
<br />

effect.
Secondly,
it
provides
a
pr<strong>in</strong>cipled
explanation
of
<strong>the</strong>
asymmetry
<strong>in</strong>
<strong>the</strong>
block<strong>in</strong>g
<br />

effect
 that
 is
 not
 expla<strong>in</strong>ed
 by
 <strong>the</strong>
 head
 movement
 approach
 alone.
 Thirdly,
 it
<br />

demonstrates
 that
 AGREE
 based
 approaches
 to
 b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
 offer
 pr<strong>in</strong>cipled
 empirical
<br />

coverage
 and
 can
 help
 expla<strong>in</strong>
 some
 of
 <strong>the</strong>
 more
 recalcitrant
 phenomena
 of
 b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory.
<br />

References
<br />

Anagnostopoulou,
E.
(2005).
Strong
and
weak
person
restrictions:
A
feature
check<strong>in</strong>g
analysis.
<br />

In
 L.
 Heggie
 and
 F.
 Ordonez
 (Eds.),
 Clitics
 and
 Affixation
 (pp.
 199‐235).
 A<strong>ms</strong>terdam:
 John
<br />

Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.
<br />

5 These entailments translate <strong>in</strong>to degrees of privative feature specification<br />

through a heuristic of logical underspecification, where �-values are differentiated only by <strong>the</strong><br />

presence versus absence of features, as <strong>in</strong> table 2 (A). This requires specify<strong>in</strong>g default <strong>in</strong>terpretations<br />

for underspecified representations: for example, [�] is common to all persons, but a bare<br />

[�] feature is <strong>in</strong>terpreted as 3rd person.<br />

(6) Entailment: [speaker] N [participant] N [�]<br />

We adopt <strong>the</strong>se feature specifications, but for convenience we employ a shorthand from here on:<br />

we write [�] as [3], [participant] as [2], and [speaker] as [1], and we refer to each of [3], [2],<br />

and [1] as a segment, mean<strong>in</strong>g ‘feature <strong>in</strong> a hierarchical feature structure’. The representations<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g to table 2 (A) <strong>in</strong> this abbreviated system are given <strong>in</strong> table 2 (B). The notation is<br />

convenient because <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation can be transparently read by <strong>in</strong>spect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> bottommost<br />

segment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> feature bundle. It is important, however, that <strong>the</strong>se segments not be read as person<br />

categories. For example, [1] <strong>in</strong> table 2 (B) does not refer to <strong>the</strong> category of 1st person; ra<strong>the</strong>r, it<br />

refers to [speaker]. It is only <strong>the</strong> feature structure as a whole that corresponds to a traditional<br />

category like 1st person.<br />

The system assumes limited variation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> selection of features (see Harley and Ritter<br />

2002). Of relevance below will be that some languages differentiate 1st and 2nd persons by<br />

specify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> latter as [addressee] ra<strong>the</strong>r than by specify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> former as [speaker], and by<br />

contrast <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g a bare [participant] as 1st person. This is shown <strong>in</strong> table 2 (C).<br />

In light of this feature-<strong>the</strong>oretic approach to �-specification, match<strong>in</strong>g requirements can be<br />

relativized to specific �-structures by manipulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> specifications of a probe: <strong>the</strong> more highly<br />

articulated a probe is, <strong>the</strong> more highly specified a DP must be to match all of a probe’s features<br />

(cf. Béjar 2003). (7)–(9) show this for <strong>the</strong> three possible articulations of <strong>the</strong> probe: a flat probe<br />

that is just [u�] ([u3] <strong>in</strong> our notation) <strong>in</strong> (7), a partially articulated probe <strong>in</strong> (8), and a fully<br />

articulated probe <strong>in</strong> (9). For each probe, a DP as highly specified as (or more highly specified<br />

Bejar,
S.
and
Rezac,
M.
(2003).
Person
licens<strong>in</strong>g
and
<strong>the</strong>
derivation
of
PCC
effects.
In
Y.
Roberge
<br />

and
 A.
 T.
 Perez‐Leroux
 (Eds.),
 Romance
 l<strong>in</strong>guistics:
 Theory
 and
 acquisition
 (pp.
 49‐62).
<br />

Anderson’s (1992) [�me, �you].<br />

A<strong>ms</strong>terdam:
John
Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.
<br />

5 The entailment relation between feature segments is <strong>in</strong>tegral to our formalization of <strong>the</strong> operations Match and<br />

Value, as we will show directly. This excludes feature syste<strong>ms</strong> that do not encode <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic entailment relations, like<br />

Cole,
P.,
Hermon,
G.,
and
Huang,
C.‐T.
J.
(2006).
Long‐Distance
B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g
<strong>in</strong>
Asian
Languages,
The
<br />

Blackwell
Companion
to
Syntax.
Vol.
3,
Ch.
39.
London:
Blackwell.
<br />


Yael Greenberg & Keren Khrizman (Bar Ilan)<br />

Bixlal: A general streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g operator <strong>in</strong> Hebrew<br />

Basic observations: bixlal is <strong>the</strong> Hebrew translation of <strong>the</strong> NPI at all, as <strong>in</strong> (1). However,<br />

Migron (2003) shows that, unlike at all, bixlal can also appear <strong>in</strong> positive (and o<strong>the</strong>r UE)<br />

constructions (as <strong>in</strong> (2),(4),(5)). In addition, we get different <strong>in</strong>terpretations of bixlal depend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on whe<strong>the</strong>r it is stressed ((1)-(2)) or not ((3)-(5)):<br />

(1) dani lo gavoha [bixlal]F (“Danny is not tall at all‟)<br />

(2) A: Yosi is tall! B: ve-dani [bixlal]F gavoha (“And Danny is clearly tall / even taller”)<br />

(3)A: Are <strong>the</strong>y married? (B: hem bixlal lo [makirim]F!) (“They don‟t even [know]F each o<strong>the</strong>r”)<br />

(4) A: Do <strong>the</strong>y know each o<strong>the</strong>r? B: hem bixlal [nesuim]F! (“They are even [married]F!”)<br />

(5) A:R<strong>in</strong>a is from Jerusalem B: lo,hi bixlal mi-[Tel Aviv]Contrastive F (“No, she is actually from<br />

[Tel Aviv]Contrastive F")<br />

Analysis Follow<strong>in</strong>g a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary suggestion <strong>in</strong> Migron (2003), we suggest that bixlal p<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicates that p is stronger than its contextually salient alternatives, where its particular<br />

effects depend on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between (a) <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g relation (b) <strong>the</strong><br />

nature and placement of focus and (c) <strong>the</strong> polarity of <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

We start with (1)-(4), <strong>in</strong> which p is stronger than q iff p entails q and q does not entail p.<br />

When focus is on <strong>the</strong> predicate (as <strong>in</strong> (3)-(4)) we get standard “Roothian” alternatives to p. With<br />

positive and negative cases (as <strong>in</strong> (4), (3) respectively) <strong>the</strong> context has to conta<strong>in</strong> a salient<br />

alternative which is weaker or stronger than p, respectively. In contrast, when bixlal itself is<br />

focused <strong>the</strong> alternatives are different <strong>in</strong>terpretations of p. For example, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> negative (or DE)<br />

(1) p is “Danny is not tall under <strong>the</strong> most liberal precision standard”, and <strong>the</strong> alternatives are of<br />

<strong>the</strong> form “Danny is not tall under a stricter precision standard” (as <strong>in</strong> Krifka 1995)).<br />

Unlike Migron‟s view, we show that bixlal is also felicitous with non-entailment,<br />

evaluative scales, where p is stronger than q s<strong>in</strong>ce it is considered more significant than q, as <strong>in</strong><br />

(6) (cf. Beaver & Clark 2008 on only and Amaral & del Prete (2010) on almost):<br />

(6) moshe zaxa be dekel ha zahav ve yosi bixlal zaxa [ba oskar]F<br />

„Moshe won <strong>the</strong> Golden Palm and Yosi even won <strong>the</strong> [Oscar]F.‟<br />

We discuss two potential mechanis<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of stressed bixlal. (a) <strong>the</strong> stress on <strong>the</strong><br />

operator <strong>in</strong>duces an alternative operator (cf. Beck (2006), Fery (to appear)). This direction is<br />

supported by <strong>the</strong> existence of sentences like (7):<br />

(7) efSar liknot Sam dagim [bixlal]F ve-dgey yam [bifratF]<br />

"You can buy <strong>the</strong>re fish <strong>in</strong> general, and sea fish <strong>in</strong> particular"<br />

But s<strong>in</strong>ce (a) cannot account for <strong>the</strong> range of read<strong>in</strong>gs expressed by bixlal we suggest (b) The<br />

stress <strong>the</strong> operator <strong>in</strong>dicates no stress on any o<strong>the</strong>r element <strong>in</strong> p (cf. Egg & Zimmerman 2011)<br />

and hence no “Roothian” alternatives. But s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g semantics of bixlal makes<br />

reference to alternatives, we end up with different alternative versions of p. We support (b) with<br />

e.g. <strong>the</strong> behavior of <strong>the</strong> Hebrew stressed stam (Orenste<strong>in</strong> & Greenberg (2010)).<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g now to (5), which <strong>in</strong>volves contrastive focus, and <strong>in</strong> which p is nei<strong>the</strong>r stronger<br />

nor weaker than q, we show that <strong>the</strong> presence of bixlal <strong>in</strong> such cases <strong>in</strong>dicates „significant<br />

contrast” between p and its q. E.g. bixlal <strong>in</strong> (5) <strong>in</strong>dicates that be<strong>in</strong>g from Tel Aviv is<br />

significantly <strong>in</strong>compatible with be<strong>in</strong>g from Jerusalem. Thus, for example, <strong>in</strong> a context where this<br />

<strong>in</strong>compatibility is not significant (e.g. <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>ternational forum where each participant has to say<br />

where he or she is from) <strong>the</strong> use of bixlal <strong>in</strong> (5) is odd.


To capture this 'stronger contrast' use we rely on Umbach‟s (2007) idea that contrast as<br />

<strong>in</strong>volves both similarity and dissimilarity, and make use of Morzycki‟s (2011) alternative-based<br />

model for captur<strong>in</strong>g degrees of (im)precision based on similarity, (orig<strong>in</strong>ally developed to<br />

analyze metal<strong>in</strong>guistic comparatives). In this system, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation function is relativized to<br />

contexts and degrees of precision (which are based on degrees of similarity). E.g. [[tel aviv]] d,C<br />

= {fl: f �d,C tel aviv} (l is location}, i.e. <strong>the</strong> set of locations sufficiently similar (similar to a<br />

degree d) <strong>in</strong> C to Tel Aviv, Where d is a real number <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terval [0,1].<br />

Us<strong>in</strong>g this system, we propose that us<strong>in</strong>g standard contrastive focus on an element <strong>in</strong> p <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> presence of an alternative q <strong>in</strong> a context c, <strong>the</strong> speaker <strong>in</strong>dicates that <strong>the</strong> degree of precision<br />

w.r.t p is true is not necessarily 1 (i.e. <strong>the</strong> speaker can consider "He is from [Aviv]Contrastive F even<br />

if Danny lives close to Tel Aviv), but that this degree of precision is higher than <strong>the</strong> degree w.r.t.<br />

q is true (e.g. <strong>in</strong> (5) „Tel Aviv‟ is taken as not „similar enough‟ to „Jerusalem‟), thus mak<strong>in</strong>g q<br />

false <strong>in</strong> c. Crucially, <strong>the</strong> addition of bixlal makes <strong>the</strong> contrast significant. This is captured by<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> degree of precision w.r.t p is true to be much higher than <strong>the</strong> degree of precision w.r.t.<br />

q is true (so p is considered highly dissimilar from q), Thus, bixlal leads aga<strong>in</strong> to streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

but not of p (relative to q), but of <strong>the</strong> contrast created by us<strong>in</strong>g p+contrastive focus <strong>in</strong> C. It may<br />

thus be seen here as a streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g operator on a speech act (cf. Cohen & Krifka (to appear)).<br />

We compare our analysis of bixlal to Anderssen‟s (2006) analysis of <strong>the</strong> similar German<br />

uberhaupt <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of widen<strong>in</strong>g, where, e.g. <strong>the</strong> German counterpart of (8) <strong>in</strong>volves widen<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

<strong>the</strong> comparative class needed for fix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> standard associated with <strong>the</strong> adjective:<br />

(8) A: Danny is tall for his age B: hu [bixlal]F gavoha („He is tall <strong>in</strong> general‟).<br />

We show, however that bixlal is felicitous also <strong>in</strong> cases where no doma<strong>in</strong> is relevant (e.g. (3-5)),<br />

as well as <strong>in</strong> cases where <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> doesn‟t change (9), or even gets narrower (10):<br />

(9) biSvil yalda bat 10, r<strong>in</strong>a lo gvoha [bixlal]F (‘For a ten years old girl, R<strong>in</strong>a is not tall at all’)<br />

(10) ba-balSanut hu tov, ve-be-semantika hu [bixlal]F tov!(‘He is good at l<strong>in</strong>guistics, and he is<br />

even better / very good at semantics’)<br />

This, as well as similar data with multidimensional adjectives (Sassoon 2010), <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

that widen<strong>in</strong>g is just one of <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g can be satisfied with bixlal.<br />

Moreover, unlike e.g. any (under Kadmon & Landman 1993, Chierchia (2006), streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g<br />

see<strong>ms</strong> lexically associated with bixlal and not triggered by <strong>in</strong>formaitvity-based considerations.<br />

This conclusion is fur<strong>the</strong>r supported by <strong>the</strong> compatibility of bixlal with nonentailment scales,<br />

which do not <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>in</strong>formativity. Thus, bixlal can be seen as a lexicalization of an emphatic<br />

operator (perhaps similar to Krifka‟s EMPHATIC ASSERT operator).<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, given Beaver & Clark's (2008) (B&C), model nonstressed bixlal is predicted to<br />

conventionally associate with focus, s<strong>in</strong>ce it can be taken to impose an order<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> set of<br />

alternatives <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> CQ and to <strong>in</strong>dicate that p is stronger than a salient alternative <strong>in</strong> this set.<br />

Empirically, however, unlike rak („only‟) and tamid („always‟), which behave as predicted <strong>in</strong><br />

B&C‟s tests (<strong>the</strong>y pattern as conventionalized and free, respectively), <strong>the</strong> behavior of bixlal is<br />

not consistent with e.g. extraction and reduced pronouns. We exam<strong>in</strong>e potential explanations for<br />

this behavior, and connect it to <strong>the</strong> fact that, unlike rak, bixlal operates on a completely different<br />

scale of alternatives when stressed.


Daniel Gutzmann (Frankfurt) & Kathar<strong>in</strong>a Hartmann (Humboldt)<br />

Dissociat<strong>in</strong>g verum from focus<br />

The term verum focus as it is commonly used refers to a special k<strong>in</strong>d of H*L accent that <strong>in</strong>stead of<br />

focus<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> accent bear<strong>in</strong>g expression, is used to focus a covert operator called verum that provides<br />

<strong>the</strong> truth value/polarity of <strong>the</strong> propositional content of a sentence (Höhle 1992). While this focus<br />

accent <strong>the</strong>sis, or fat as we call this approach henceforth, may be plausible for languages like German<br />

or English, we argue that it is not so if typological more diverse languages are taken <strong>in</strong>to consideration<br />

as well. Instead, we suggest an alternative <strong>the</strong>sis, which we call <strong>the</strong> lexical operator <strong>the</strong>sis or lot.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> fat, verum focus is what <strong>the</strong> term suggests: it is an ord<strong>in</strong>ary focus accent on<br />

<strong>the</strong> covert verum operator (Bür<strong>in</strong>g 2006; Höhle 1992; Zimmermann & Hole 2008). In order for <strong>the</strong><br />

fat to work properly, verum must be present <strong>in</strong> every sentence and <strong>the</strong> accent focusses it. In order<br />

to ensure that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of a verum accent, verum has no efficient contribution to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of a sentence, it has to be rendered as an identity function on truth values/propositions, <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> reverse of negation (Zimmermann & Hole 2008). The fat can be summarized as follows.<br />

(fat) verum focus ∶= covert propositional identity function + focus mark<strong>in</strong>g<br />

In contrast, <strong>the</strong> lot does not assume an omnipresent identity function. Instead, velum is rendered as<br />

a conversational operator (cf. Gutzmann & Castroviejo Miró 2011; Romero & Han 2004) for different<br />

formalizations of this idea) that, by convention, is realized by an accent.<br />

(lot) verum focus ∶= conversational operator realized by accent<br />

In languages like German and English, this happens to be realized by a pitch accent just like focus<br />

is. However, this ra<strong>the</strong>r is a k<strong>in</strong>d of homonymie. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> lot, verum focus is no focus at<br />

all, despite <strong>the</strong> traditional term.<br />

Both <strong>the</strong>ories make different predictions. (i) Means of focus/verum mark<strong>in</strong>g. S<strong>in</strong>ce verum focus<br />

is focus, <strong>the</strong> fat predicts that verum focus is marked by <strong>the</strong> same means as focus, whereas <strong>the</strong> lot<br />

does not predict that <strong>the</strong>re is a necessary overlap between verum and focus mark<strong>in</strong>g strategy. (ii) Cooccurrences<br />

of focus and verum. If a language exhibits multiple foci, <strong>the</strong> FAT predicts that verum and<br />

focus can also co-occur. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> co-occurrence of verum and focus is not to be expected<br />

if a languages prohibits multiple foci. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> LOT does not predict such a correlation and,<br />

ceteris paribus, all four comb<strong>in</strong>ations should be possible (Of course, <strong>the</strong>re could be o<strong>the</strong>r reasons<br />

why one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r comb<strong>in</strong>ation is not possible or widespread). (iii) Association with focus. S<strong>in</strong>ce,<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> fat, <strong>the</strong> verum operator is an ord<strong>in</strong>ary focus, it should be possible to have focus<br />

sensitive operators to be associated with verum focus. The lot excludes this possibility.<br />

While it is hard to differentiate between <strong>the</strong> two <strong>the</strong>ses on <strong>the</strong> basis of German or English alone,<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to account languages that differ from <strong>the</strong> well-studied languages can help to evaluate <strong>the</strong>m<br />

properly. We will present arguments for Chadic languages that favor <strong>the</strong> lot over <strong>the</strong> fat.<br />

Ad (i). In contrast to <strong>in</strong>tonational languages like German or English, that do not exhibit formal<br />

differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mark<strong>in</strong>g of focus and verum, <strong>the</strong> realization of verum differs considerably from <strong>the</strong><br />

mark<strong>in</strong>g of constituent focus <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Chadic languages. In Bura, for <strong>in</strong>stance, subject focus is marked<br />

by <strong>the</strong> subsequent focus marker án (Hartmann & Zimmermann t.a.), cf. (1a). In contrast, verum is<br />

marked by <strong>the</strong> particle ku, as <strong>in</strong> (1b).<br />

(1) a. subject focus: án<br />

[P<strong>in</strong>dar]F án sá mbal.<br />

P. FM dr<strong>in</strong>k beer<br />

“P<strong>in</strong>dar drank beer.”<br />

b. verum: ku<br />

P<strong>in</strong>dár ku sá mbal.<br />

P. VERUM dr<strong>in</strong>k beer<br />

“P<strong>in</strong>dar did dr<strong>in</strong>k beer.”<br />

Chadic languages exhibit quite a variety <strong>in</strong> focus mark<strong>in</strong>g. Crucially, focus mark<strong>in</strong>g formally differs<br />

1


from verum mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> all languages we <strong>in</strong>vestigated so far (South Marghi, Bura (Central Chadic),<br />

Hausa, Bole, Ngizim (West Chadic)).<br />

Ad (ii). Like English or German, Bura allows for multiple focus and/or question mark<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(2) a. Ga masta mi ama ri?<br />

2SG.S buy what where Q<br />

b.<br />

“What did you buy where?”<br />

Iya masta [kwara ni]F [akwa kwasuku]F, iya masta …<br />

1SG.S buy donkey DEF at market 1SG.S buy<br />

“I bought <strong>the</strong> donkey at <strong>the</strong> market, I bought …”<br />

However, contrary to what <strong>the</strong> fat predicts, verum cannot co-occur with wh-questions and focus <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Chadic languages, see Bura aga<strong>in</strong> for illustration.<br />

(3) a. Wán (*ku) sá mbal? *subj wh + verum<br />

b. [P<strong>in</strong>dár]F án (*ku) sá mbal. *subj foc + verum<br />

<strong>in</strong>tended: “P<strong>in</strong>dar did dr<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> beer.”<br />

While <strong>the</strong> English and German pattern does not conflict with <strong>the</strong> fat, <strong>the</strong> Chadic data is at odds<br />

with it and favors <strong>the</strong> lot. We leave it for fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>the</strong> availability of <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g two<br />

configurations.<br />

Ad (iii). Focus sensitive particles are generally impossible <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> verum operator<br />

ku <strong>in</strong> Bura as shown <strong>in</strong> (4) (Hartmann, Jacob & Zimmermann 2008: 35). The focus sensitive particle<br />

daci, which may associate at a distance (Hartmann & Zimmermann 2008), nei<strong>the</strong>r associates with<br />

<strong>the</strong> contrastively focused verb, nor with <strong>the</strong> verum operator itself. This would be unexpected given<br />

<strong>the</strong> fat.<br />

(4) Mwala ní adí tsá ní wá ama tsá (*ku) buhá ní daci.<br />

woman DEF EXIST hit 3SG NEG but 3SG VERUM push 3SG only<br />

“The woman didn’t hit him, but she only pushed him”.<br />

We conclude that both analyses of verum are <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple able to account for <strong>the</strong> observed facts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tonational languages. The Chadic languages, however, do not show evidence <strong>in</strong> favour of a focus<br />

accent analysis of verum. Instead <strong>the</strong>y support a lexical analysis of verum as an epistemic conversational<br />

operator, an approach that disassociates verum from <strong>the</strong> notion of focus. If we generalize<br />

<strong>the</strong>se f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g to languages like English or German – which gave rise to <strong>the</strong> focus analysis <strong>in</strong> first place<br />

– <strong>the</strong> accent pattern traditionally associated with verum focus is not licensed by <strong>the</strong> focus status of<br />

<strong>the</strong> covert verum operator. Instead, <strong>the</strong> accent itself is <strong>the</strong> realization of <strong>the</strong> lexical operator. That is,<br />

verum focus is no focus at all.<br />

Bür<strong>in</strong>g, Daniel. 2006. Intonation und Informationsstruktur.<br />

Grammatik und darüber h<strong>in</strong>aus. In Hardarik Blühdorn, Eva<br />

Bre<strong>in</strong>dl & Ulrich Hermann Waßner eds., Text — Verstehen,<br />

144–163. Berl<strong>in</strong> and New York: Walter de Gruyter.<br />

Gutzmann, Daniel & Elena Castroviejo Miró. 2011. The dimensions<br />

of verum. In Olivier Bonami & Patricia Cabredo-<br />

Hofherr eds., Empirical Issues <strong>in</strong> Syntax and Semantics 8,<br />

143–165.<br />

Hartmann, Kathar<strong>in</strong>a, Peggy Jacob & Malte Zimmermann. 2008.<br />

Focus asymmetries <strong>in</strong> Bura. In Sh<strong>in</strong>shiro Ishihara, S. Petrova<br />

& Anne Schwarz eds., Interdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary Studies on Information<br />

Structure 10, 45–92. Potsdam: Universitätsverlag Potsdam.<br />

2<br />

Hartmann, Kathar<strong>in</strong>a & Malte Zimmermann. 2008. Not only<br />

“only” but “too” too. Alternative sensitive particles <strong>in</strong> Bura.<br />

Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of S<strong>in</strong>n und Bedeutung 12. 196–211.<br />

Hartmann, Kathar<strong>in</strong>a & Malte Zimmermann. t.a. Focus mark<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> Bura. Semantic uniformity matches syntactic heterogeneity.<br />

Natural Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistic Theory.<br />

Höhle, Tilman N. 1992. Über Verum-Fokus im Deutschen. In<br />

Joachim Jacobs ed., Informationsstruktur und Grammatik,<br />

112–141. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.<br />

Romero, Maribel & Chung-hye Han. 2004. On negative yes/no<br />

questions. <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> and Philosophy 27(5). 609–658.<br />

Zimmermann, Malte & Daniel Hole. 2008. “Predicate focus,<br />

verum focus, verb focus. Similarities and difference”. Talk at<br />

<strong>the</strong> Potsdam-London IS Meet<strong>in</strong>g. 12. 12. 2008.


When Maria is considered to be he. Gender mismatch effects dur<strong>in</strong>g pronoun resolution<br />

Pronoun resolution is an <strong>in</strong>tegral part of sentence comprehension. To accomplish this task, <strong>the</strong><br />

parser uses various sources of <strong>in</strong>formation, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g syntactic, semantic and pragmatic <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

(for an overview see Garnham, 2001). With regard to syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation, we can<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guish two k<strong>in</strong>ds of constra<strong>in</strong>ts: phrase-structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts which restrict <strong>the</strong> set of candidate<br />

antecedents <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of phrase-structure geometry (e.g., B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky,<br />

1981) and morpho-syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts which restrict <strong>the</strong> set of candidate antecedents <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong><br />

of feature compatibility. The onl<strong>in</strong>e-application of both types of constra<strong>in</strong>ts has been attested <strong>in</strong><br />

prior studies (e.g. Badecker & Straub, 2002; Kennison, 2003; Sturt, 2003; van Gompel & Liversedge,<br />

2003; Kazan<strong>in</strong>a, Lau, Lieberman, Yoshida & Phillips, 2007). The exact tim<strong>in</strong>g, however,<br />

rema<strong>in</strong>s an open issue, and <strong>in</strong> particular <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts constra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

search for an antecedent from <strong>the</strong> onset on or only later <strong>in</strong> a second step evaluat<strong>in</strong>g candidates.<br />

The present study, which focuses on person, gender and number agreement, addresses two ma<strong>in</strong><br />

questions: (i) Do agreement requirements exclude featurally <strong>in</strong>appropriate NPs immediately or<br />

only at a later stage? (ii) Are <strong>the</strong>re differential effects of person versus gender agreement? The<br />

study makes use of a mismatch paradigm: <strong>the</strong> pronoun is preceded by an NP which matches<br />

or mismatches <strong>the</strong> pronoun <strong>in</strong> agreement features. In contrast to previous studies (e.g., Kennison,<br />

2003), <strong>the</strong> mismatch sentences do not represent <strong>in</strong>coherent discourses lack<strong>in</strong>g a proper<br />

antecedent for <strong>the</strong> pronoun. As shown <strong>in</strong> (1), <strong>the</strong> pronoun is sandwiched between two potential<br />

antecedents – one, <strong>the</strong> ‘distractor’, preced<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pronoun and ano<strong>the</strong>r one, <strong>the</strong> actual antecedent,<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g it.<br />

(1)<br />

Als<br />

When<br />

Distractor<br />

Maria<br />

M.<br />

Jana Häussler (Potsdam) & Markus Bader (Frankfurt)<br />

hörte,<br />

heard<br />

dass<br />

that<br />

er<br />

he<br />

abreist,<br />

departs<br />

war<br />

was<br />

der Mann<br />

<strong>the</strong> man<br />

Pronoun Antecedent<br />

schon<br />

already<br />

weg<br />

away<br />

The cataphoric pronoun is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a fronted adjunct clause, for which Gordon & Hendrick<br />

(1997) have shown that cataphoric reference is highly acceptable. In <strong>the</strong> experiments <strong>the</strong> fronted<br />

adjunct clause is complex itself consist<strong>in</strong>g of a matrix clause conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> distractor and<br />

an embedded clause conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pronoun. The actual antecedent occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> clause<br />

<strong>the</strong>reafter.<br />

We present two self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g experiments that <strong>in</strong>vestigate sentences follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> schema<br />

<strong>in</strong> (1). Both experiments vary <strong>the</strong> feature specifications of <strong>the</strong> distractor (1st person pronoun, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

proper name or mascul<strong>in</strong>e proper name). Experiment 1 fur<strong>the</strong>rmore varies <strong>the</strong> pronoun,<br />

which was ei<strong>the</strong>r er (‘he’) or sie (‘she’). Experiment 2 concentrates on <strong>the</strong> number ambiguous<br />

pronoun sie (‘she/<strong>the</strong>y’) and varies its number specification signaled by subject-verb agreement<br />

on <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g verb, cf. (2).<br />

(2) Als Maria erfuhr, . . . (‘When Maria heard’)<br />

a. dass sie abreisen muss, hatte die Tante die Stadt längst verlassen.<br />

that she depart must.SG had.SG <strong>the</strong> aunt <strong>the</strong> town already left<br />

‘When Maria heard that she had to depart <strong>the</strong> aunt had already left <strong>the</strong> town.’<br />

b. dass sie abreisen müssen, hatten die Tanten die Stadt längst verlassen.<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y depart must.PL had.PL <strong>the</strong> aunts <strong>the</strong> town already left<br />

‘When Maria heard that <strong>the</strong>y had to depart <strong>the</strong> aunts had already left <strong>the</strong> town.’<br />

1


<strong>Read<strong>in</strong>g</strong> times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronoun region are prolonged when pronoun and distratcor mismatch <strong>in</strong><br />

gender. In Experiment 1, <strong>the</strong> effect starts on <strong>the</strong> pronoun itself and lasts through <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

embedded clause; <strong>in</strong> Experiment 2, <strong>the</strong> effect is slightly delayed and starts only immediately<br />

after <strong>the</strong> pronoun. We <strong>in</strong>terpret this mismatch penalty as an <strong>in</strong>dication for <strong>the</strong> parser’s attempt to<br />

l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> pronoun to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>appropriate distractor. Despite <strong>the</strong> feature <strong>in</strong>compatibility and although<br />

<strong>the</strong> pronoun occurs <strong>in</strong> a configuration where it could well be (and <strong>in</strong> fact is) a cataphor, <strong>the</strong> parser<br />

yields to <strong>the</strong> pressure of establish<strong>in</strong>g an antecedent as soon as possible. In a way, this pressure<br />

overrules <strong>the</strong> agreement constra<strong>in</strong>t and lets <strong>the</strong> parser ignore <strong>the</strong> alternative offered by b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts, namely establish<strong>in</strong>g a cataphoric b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g relation. At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong> agreement<br />

violation is noticed as reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> prolonged read<strong>in</strong>g times. Hence, <strong>the</strong> agreement constra<strong>in</strong>t<br />

is active but it does not guide <strong>the</strong> parser’s first choice. Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, this argues for a twostep<br />

model: first a referential l<strong>in</strong>k is established and only <strong>in</strong> a second step its appropriateness<br />

is evaluated. However, gender and person features are treated differently. Notably, a mismatch<br />

effect occurs only <strong>in</strong> case of a gender mismatch but not with a person conflict. Apparently,<br />

<strong>the</strong> first-person pronoun distractor is not considered a potential antecedent for <strong>the</strong> third-person<br />

pronoun. We conclude that person features restrict <strong>the</strong> set of candidate antecedents immediately.<br />

We will discuss our f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong> feature delay hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (van Gompel &<br />

Liversedge, 2003) and <strong>the</strong> active search hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (Kazan<strong>in</strong>a et al., 2007).<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Experiment 2 provides evidence for <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong> parser’s association<br />

with a once established antecedent is really strong. Remember that <strong>the</strong> pronoun sie is number<br />

ambiguous. Disambiguation is achieved by subject-verb agreement with <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g verb<br />

(muss/müssen <strong>in</strong> (2)). While read<strong>in</strong>g times for this verb do not show any difference between<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural <strong>in</strong> sentences with a 1st-person distractor, disambiguation towards plural<br />

causes a process<strong>in</strong>g disruption <strong>in</strong> sentences with a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e distractor. To our view this suggests<br />

that just adjust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pronoun’s number feature is basically costless whereas break<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>the</strong><br />

l<strong>in</strong>k to a seem<strong>in</strong>g antecedent is particularly hard.<br />

Literatur<br />

Badecker, W. & Straub, K. (2002). The process<strong>in</strong>g role of structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of pronouns and anaphors. Journal of Experimental Psychology 28, 748–769.<br />

Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. Dordrecht: Foris.<br />

Garnham, A. (2001). Mental models and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of anaphora. Hove: Psychology<br />

Press.<br />

Gordon, P. C. & Hendrick, R. (1997). Intuitive knowledge of l<strong>in</strong>guistic co-reference. Cognition<br />

62, 325–370.<br />

Kazan<strong>in</strong>a, N., Lau, E. F., Lieberman, M., Yoshida, M. & Phillips, C. (2007). The effect of<br />

syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of backwards anaphora. Journal of Memory and Language<br />

56, 384–409.<br />

Kennison, S. M. (2003). Comprehend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pronouns her, him, and his: Implications for <strong>the</strong>ories<br />

of referential process<strong>in</strong>g. Journal of Memory and Language 49, 335–352.<br />

Sturt, P. (2003). The time-course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> reference resolution.<br />

Journal of Memory and Language 48, 542–562.<br />

van Gompel, R. P. & Liversedge, S. P. (2003). The <strong>in</strong>fluence of morphological <strong>in</strong>formation on<br />

cataphoric pronoun assignment. Journal of Experimental Psychology 29, 128–139.<br />

2


Claire Halpert (MIT)<br />

Structural case and <strong>the</strong> nature of vP <strong>in</strong> Zulu<br />

Recent work has demonstrated that <strong>in</strong> Icelandic and Faroese, a nom<strong>in</strong>al can move around a head<br />

before <strong>the</strong> head probes (Holmberg and Hroársdóttir 2004; Sigur�sson and Holmberg 2008, Asar<strong>in</strong>a<br />

2011). As a result of this order of movement and prob<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> trace of <strong>the</strong> moved nom<strong>in</strong>al does<br />

not act as an <strong>in</strong>tervener. I show that we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong>dependent evidence for this type of order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> two<br />

syntactic puzzles <strong>in</strong> Zulu: (1) <strong>the</strong> ‘conjo<strong>in</strong>t/disjo<strong>in</strong>t’ alternation (van der Spuy 1993; Buell 2005)<br />

and (2) <strong>the</strong> distribution of augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>als (Buell 2011). I argue for a unified account of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

two puzzles, draw<strong>in</strong>g on recent work that argues for <strong>the</strong> ability of syntactic operations to be countercyclic<br />

and asymmetrical without yield<strong>in</strong>g a crash (Ndayiragije 1999, Legate 2005, Prem<strong>in</strong>ger 2009,<br />

2010, 2011). This analysis also suggests that nom<strong>in</strong>als <strong>in</strong> Zulu are subject to <strong>the</strong> Case Filter (contra<br />

Harford Perez 1985, Diercks to appear, a. o. on <strong>the</strong> lack of case effects <strong>in</strong> Bantu).<br />

Puzzle 1: Conjo<strong>in</strong>t/disjo<strong>in</strong>t. In certa<strong>in</strong> tenses, Zulu verbs alternate between a ‘conjo<strong>in</strong>t’ form<br />

(marked by Ø <strong>in</strong> present) and a ‘disjo<strong>in</strong>t’ form (marked by -ya- <strong>in</strong> present). This alternation is<br />

syntactically conditioned: <strong>the</strong> conjo<strong>in</strong>t form is used if vP conta<strong>in</strong>s overt material o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong><br />

verb and <strong>the</strong> disjo<strong>in</strong>t form is used if not (van der Spuy 1993; Buell 2005, 2006):<br />

(1) uSipho u- *(ya)- dla (2) ku- (*ya)- dla uSipho (3) uSipho u- (*ya)- dla iqanda<br />

1Sipho 1s- *(YA)- eat 17s- (*YA)- eat 1Sipho 1Sipho 1s- (*YA)- eat 5egg<br />

‘Sipho is eat<strong>in</strong>g.’<br />

‘SIPHO’s eat<strong>in</strong>g.’<br />

‘Sipho is eat<strong>in</strong>g an egg.’<br />

Puzzle 2: Augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>al distribution. Nom<strong>in</strong>als <strong>in</strong> Zulu are typically marked with an<br />

<strong>in</strong>itial vowel (<strong>the</strong> ‘augment’) that reflects noun class. In a subset of environments that permit<br />

augmented nom<strong>in</strong>als, this vowel may be omitted. The omission of <strong>the</strong> augment is subject to various<br />

conditions (see Buell 2011), but <strong>the</strong> ones I focus on here are structural: augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>als must<br />

appear <strong>in</strong>side vP, and are limited to certa<strong>in</strong> configurations with<strong>in</strong> vP.<br />

(4) a. SVO with augmentless object<br />

c. �VSO +augment -augment<br />

umuntu a- ka-dli qanda<br />

a- ku-dli muntu iqanda<br />

1person NEG1Seat NEG egg<br />

NEG17Seat NEG 1person 5egg<br />

‘A/<strong>the</strong> person didn’t eat any egg.’<br />

‘NOBODY is eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>/an/any egg.’<br />

b. *VSO -augment -augment<br />

d. *VSO +augment -augment<br />

*a-ku-dl-i muntu qanda<br />

a- ku-dli umuntu qanda<br />

NEG-17S-eat-NEG 1person egg<br />

NEG17Seat NEG 1person 5egg<br />

Solution. The analysis depends on three components–failure to agree, asymmetrical case relationships,<br />

and <strong>the</strong> ability of an argument to move around a head before that head probes.<br />

Recent work by Prem<strong>in</strong>ger (2009, 2010, 2011) suggests that it is not obligatory for a prob<strong>in</strong>g<br />

head to undergo Agreement <strong>in</strong> order for a derivation to converge. Prem<strong>in</strong>ger argues, however, that<br />

Agree itself is not optional: heads probe obligatorily and so will always Agree if a goal is present.<br />

If a probe fails to f<strong>in</strong>d a goal, <strong>the</strong> derivation will still converge as long as prob<strong>in</strong>g was attempted.<br />

We can understand <strong>the</strong> Zulu conjo<strong>in</strong>t/disjo<strong>in</strong>t pattern <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of Prem<strong>in</strong>ger’s proposal: <strong>the</strong> head<br />

responsible for <strong>the</strong> alternation is an (unrelativized) probe that searches <strong>the</strong> vP for an XP to agree<br />

with. When <strong>the</strong> vP is empty, and thus lacks a goal, <strong>the</strong> derivation still converges, as predicted by<br />

Prem<strong>in</strong>ger. In Zulu we see a morphological marker of this failure: where Agree does not occur, <strong>the</strong><br />

prob<strong>in</strong>g head spells out as -ya-, ra<strong>the</strong>r than Ø.<br />

I propose that augmented nom<strong>in</strong>als, which exhibit no structural restrictions, are <strong>in</strong>herently cased<br />

<strong>in</strong> Zulu. Augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>als, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, do display structural restrictions <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with<br />

classic case effects. I argue that this structurally-restricted distribution is evidence for structural<br />

case assignment with<strong>in</strong> vP. In l<strong>in</strong>e with Ndayiragije (1999), <strong>the</strong> case probe can check even DPs that<br />

1


don’t need case, such as augmented nom<strong>in</strong>als. However, while for Ndayiragije Bantu nom<strong>in</strong>als<br />

generally don’t require case, and thus <strong>the</strong> case prob<strong>in</strong>g is always driven by <strong>the</strong> prob<strong>in</strong>g head <strong>in</strong><br />

Bantu languages, I argue that augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>als do require case <strong>in</strong> Zulu and must be checked<br />

to prevent a crash. The result of <strong>the</strong> possibility for asymmetrical probe-goal relationships is <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g: <strong>the</strong> case-licen<strong>in</strong>g head does not specifically probe for an augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>al and will<br />

not cause a crash regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r it f<strong>in</strong>ds any XP to check. Augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>als that are<br />

not checked, however, do cause a crash and thus only surface <strong>in</strong> particular configurations.<br />

With <strong>the</strong>se concepts <strong>in</strong> place, we can understand <strong>the</strong> mechanism driv<strong>in</strong>g conjo<strong>in</strong>t/disjo<strong>in</strong>t alternations<br />

and augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>al distribution. Both phenomena depend on a head, L, that is<br />

immediately above vP (because vP-<strong>in</strong>ternal subjects are <strong>in</strong> its prob<strong>in</strong>g doma<strong>in</strong>) and that probes for<br />

<strong>the</strong> highest XP. We can understand <strong>the</strong> patterns <strong>in</strong> (4) <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of this structure: <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g head<br />

probes vP and checks <strong>the</strong> highest XP, which is <strong>the</strong> object <strong>in</strong> (4a) and <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> (4b,c,d). In<br />

(4a), <strong>the</strong> object is augmentless but is licensed through Agree with <strong>the</strong> functional head. Similarly,<br />

<strong>the</strong> augmentless subjects <strong>in</strong> (4b,c) Agree with and are licensed by <strong>the</strong> head. In (4c,d) <strong>the</strong> construction<br />

is ungrammatical because of <strong>the</strong> presence of a lower augmentless nom<strong>in</strong>al: <strong>the</strong> object. Here,<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject <strong>in</strong>tervenes and prevents <strong>the</strong> object from be<strong>in</strong>g licensed, caus<strong>in</strong>g a crash. As discussed<br />

above, all of <strong>the</strong> for<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> (4) use conjo<strong>in</strong>t morphology because <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g head is able to Agree.<br />

In cases where noth<strong>in</strong>g appears <strong>in</strong> vP, <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g head fails to Agree, but <strong>the</strong> derivation still<br />

converges, with <strong>the</strong> head spell<strong>in</strong>g out as -ya-. The proposed structure is schematized below <strong>in</strong> (5):<br />

(5) LP<br />

L(icenser) vP<br />

S<br />

augment<br />

optional<br />

v o VP<br />

V O<br />

augment<br />

necessary<br />

(6) LP<br />

L<br />

ya<br />

tS<br />

vP<br />

v o VP<br />

V<br />

prob<strong>in</strong>g<br />

fails!<br />

The tim<strong>in</strong>g of operations. Both puzzles described here are sensitive to syntactic movement. The<br />

head L o treats constructions <strong>in</strong> which elements move out of vP dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> derivation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same<br />

way as constructions <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> vP is empty throughout. This is a familiar pattern from Icelandic<br />

and Faroese, where dative experiencers are able to move around a number probe before it probes<br />

(Holmberg & Hróarsdóttir 2004, a.o.). In Icelandic, however, we f<strong>in</strong>d optionality <strong>in</strong> agreement,<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicative of both orders of movement and prob<strong>in</strong>g. If operations are freely ordered with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

phase (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2005), this is an expected result. In Zulu, however, we only see <strong>the</strong> counter-cyclic<br />

movement-before-prob<strong>in</strong>g order. I propose that this pattern is due to <strong>the</strong> Activity Condition: nom<strong>in</strong>als<br />

<strong>in</strong> Zulu cannot undergo A movement after enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to a case-check<strong>in</strong>g relationship with<br />

L (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2000, 2001). While recent work has suggested that Bantu languages lack both case<br />

and Activity effects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> TP doma<strong>in</strong> (Carstens 2011, Carstens and Diercks to appear, Diercks to<br />

appear), I argue that we f<strong>in</strong>d both case and Activity at work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower part of <strong>the</strong> clause <strong>in</strong> Zulu.<br />

Selected References: Buell, L. 2005. Issues <strong>in</strong> Zulu Morphosyntax. PhD diss. Carstens, V. 2011.<br />

Hyperactivity and Hyperagreement <strong>in</strong> Bantu. L<strong>in</strong>gua. Diercks, M. to appear. Parameteriz<strong>in</strong>g case<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory: evidence from Bantu. Syntax. Holmberg, A. & T. Hroársdóttir 2004. Agreement and<br />

movement <strong>in</strong> Icelandic rais<strong>in</strong>g constructions. L<strong>in</strong>gua. Ndayiragije, J. 1999. Check<strong>in</strong>g economy.<br />

LI. Prem<strong>in</strong>ger, O. 2009. Break<strong>in</strong>g agreements: dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g agreement and clitic doubl<strong>in</strong>g by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir failures. LI. Van der Spuy, A. 1993. Dislocated noun phrases <strong>in</strong> Nguni. L<strong>in</strong>gua.<br />

2


Bart Hollebrandse, Petra Hendriks & Jacolien van Rij (Gron<strong>in</strong>gen)<br />

Eye gaze patterns reveal subtle discourse effects on object pronoun resolution<br />

Discourse coherence plays a major role <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g sentences. This paper shows<br />

that adults are sensitive to very subtle <strong>in</strong>formation from discourse. To do this, we use<br />

<strong>the</strong> well-known phenomenon of Delayed Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple B Effect (Chien and Wexler, 1990;<br />

Koster, 1993) and show that children are capable of circumvent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> DPBE on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of subtle discourse <strong>in</strong>formation.<br />

Issue Spenader, Smits & Hendriks (2009) found that coherent discourse helps <strong>the</strong><br />

DPBE-child to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> correct referent for a pronoun. The discourse-<strong>in</strong>troduction of a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle referent made <strong>the</strong> effect disappear. By add<strong>in</strong>g a condition <strong>in</strong> which we varied<br />

<strong>the</strong> order of referents as potentials antecedents for object pronouns we are zoom<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>to subtle discourse prom<strong>in</strong>ence effects such as first-mention bias (cf subject<br />

pronouns <strong>in</strong> Arnold, Eisenband, Brown-Schmidt & Trueswell (2000)).<br />

Our Study We have not only collected accuracy as a measure, but also eye-gaze.<br />

It is especially eye-gaze which can give us subtle onl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> resolution of<br />

pronouns and <strong>the</strong> discourse effects on it. We tested <strong>the</strong> Agent–Patient order, <strong>the</strong> order<br />

Patient-Agent and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduction of a s<strong>in</strong>gle referent (1)-(3).<br />

(1) Double Topic Agent-Patient Condition<br />

Hier zie je een olifant en een d<strong>in</strong>o. De olifant heeft hem met een hamer geslagen.<br />

here see you an elephant and a d<strong>in</strong>osaur. The elephant has him with a hammer hit<br />

“Here you see an elephant and a d<strong>in</strong>osaur. The elephant has hit him with a<br />

hammer.”<br />

(2) S<strong>in</strong>gle Topic Condition<br />

Hier zie je een d<strong>in</strong>o. De olifant heeft hem met een hamer geslagen.<br />

here see you a d<strong>in</strong>osaur. The elephant has him with a hammer hit<br />

“Here you see a d<strong>in</strong>osaur. The elephant has hit him with a hammer.”<br />

(3) Double Topic Patient-Agent Condition<br />

Hier zie je een d<strong>in</strong>o en een olifant. De olifant heeft hem met een hamer geslagen.<br />

here see you a d<strong>in</strong>oaur and an elephant. The elephant has him with a hammer hit<br />

“Here you see a d<strong>in</strong>osaur and an elephant. The elephant has hit him with a<br />

hammer.”<br />

Participants and Design 33 Dutch children between <strong>the</strong> ages 4;2 and 6;5 (mean=<br />

5;4) were tested on <strong>the</strong> conditions (1) - (3), as well as 37 adults, us<strong>in</strong>g a Picture-<br />

Verification task. Each participant saw 48 ite<strong>ms</strong> (16 ite<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g two referents,<br />

divided equally <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two orders and test<strong>in</strong>g pronouns and reflexives; 16 ite<strong>ms</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>gle referents, test<strong>in</strong>g pronouns and reflexives; 16 fillers). All ite<strong>ms</strong><br />

were tested <strong>in</strong> matched and mismatched cases, but participants saw only one variant<br />

of each item.<br />

Results The data was analyzed by compar<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>ear mixed-effects models<br />

(<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> maximum random effects structure supported by <strong>the</strong> data) to test <strong>the</strong><br />

effects of Context, Match and Group. In addition to a significant ma<strong>in</strong> effect of Match<br />

(χ2()=), show<strong>in</strong>g that children are more likely to say yes than no, we found a marg<strong>in</strong>al<br />

effect of <strong>in</strong>troduction of reference (χ2(1)= 18.621; p < .001) on children’s off-l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

performance (yes/no-answers) on <strong>the</strong> task: children perform more adult-like <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

S<strong>in</strong>gle Topic condition than <strong>the</strong> Agent-Patient Condition (β=0.860, SE=0.376, zvalue=2.288,<br />

p=.022), and perform better <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Patient-Agent Condition than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Agent-Patient Condition (β=-0831, SE=0.476, z-value=-1.747, p=.081). This shows<br />

that children are <strong>in</strong>deed capable of resolv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> DPBE by use of discourse clues.


Adults show ceil<strong>in</strong>g performance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> offl<strong>in</strong>e answers. However, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir gazebehavior,<br />

adults show an effect of Context (see Figure 1). Adults look more at <strong>the</strong><br />

patient <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Agent-Patient order (1) than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two referent <strong>in</strong>troductions,<br />

whereas children do not show differences <strong>in</strong> gaze behavior between <strong>the</strong> different<br />

conditions. In <strong>the</strong> second 500 <strong>ms</strong> b<strong>in</strong> (500-100 <strong>ms</strong> from <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> anaphor) of<br />

<strong>the</strong> mismatch-ite<strong>ms</strong> we found a marg<strong>in</strong>al significant <strong>in</strong>teraction of Context and<br />

AgeGroup (χ2(2)=5.40; p=.067).<br />

Conclusions Our f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs support two important po<strong>in</strong>ts: 1. Children are sensitive<br />

to very subtle effects of discourse prom<strong>in</strong>ence such as topicality and <strong>the</strong> first mention<br />

bias. This is shown <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir offl<strong>in</strong>e data, but data of younger children alludes to onl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

differences as well. 2. The adult onl<strong>in</strong>e data clearly shows a different gaze pattern for<br />

<strong>the</strong> Agent-Patient <strong>in</strong>troduction than for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ones. This onl<strong>in</strong>e f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g supports<br />

<strong>the</strong> idea that different referent <strong>in</strong>troductions, <strong>the</strong> Agent-Patient order, have an effect<br />

on pronoun resolution.<br />

patient<br />

equal<br />

agent<br />

patient<br />

equal<br />

agent<br />

Adults<br />

0 500 1000 1500<br />

Children<br />

0 500 1000 1500<br />

Figure 1: Eye gaze for pronoun resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mismatched case (0 <strong>in</strong>dicates onset<br />

of <strong>the</strong> pronoun).<br />

Arnold, J. E., Eisenband, J. G., Brown-Schmidt, S. & Trueswell, J. C. (2000). The<br />

rapid use of gender <strong>in</strong>formation: evidence of <strong>the</strong> time course of pronoun<br />

resolution from eyetrack<strong>in</strong>g. Cognition, 76, B13–B26.<br />

Chien, Y. C., & Wexler, K. (1990). Children's Knowledge of Locality Conditions <strong>in</strong><br />

B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g as Evidence for <strong>the</strong> Modularity of Syntax and Pragmatics. Language<br />

Acquisition, 1(3), 225-295.<br />

Koster, C. (1993). Errors <strong>in</strong> anaphora acquisition. Doctoral dissertation, Utrecht<br />

University, Utrecht, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands.<br />

Spenader, J., Smits, E. J., & Hendriks, P. (2009). Coherent discourse solves <strong>the</strong><br />

Pronoun Interpretation Problem. Journal of Child Language, 36(1), 23-52.<br />

CAP<br />

CPA<br />

S<br />

CAP<br />

CPA<br />

S


Elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g rightward movement: Extraposition as flexible l<strong>in</strong>earisation of adjuncts<br />

Traces were <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong>to syntactic <strong>the</strong>ory to serve two purposes: <strong>the</strong>y allowed displaced<br />

elements to be construed as semantically related to <strong>the</strong>ir pre-movement positions, and allowed<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> locality of movement to be stated. These concerns perta<strong>in</strong> not only to <strong>the</strong><br />

more canonical <strong>in</strong>stances of leftward movement, but also to apparent <strong>in</strong>stances of rightward<br />

movement: <strong>the</strong> relative clause must be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a modifier of ‘book’ <strong>in</strong> (1), and must be<br />

ruled to have violated some constra<strong>in</strong>t on locality <strong>in</strong> (2).<br />

(1) A book appeared [which was written by Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky]<br />

(2) * It was believed [that a book appeared] by everybody [which was written by Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky]<br />

The locality constra<strong>in</strong>ts on rightward movement have long been known to differ from those on<br />

leftward movement, rais<strong>in</strong>g significant <strong>the</strong>oretical issues: (i) why should <strong>the</strong>re be two k<strong>in</strong>ds of<br />

movement? and (ii) why should <strong>the</strong> two k<strong>in</strong>ds correlate so precisely with <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ear direction<br />

of <strong>the</strong> displacement? We propose an account of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretive and locality properties of this<br />

extraposition phenomenon that does not <strong>in</strong>volve movement or traces. We <strong>in</strong>stead rely only on<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependently-motivated derivational flexibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduction of adjuncts proposed by<br />

Hunter (2010), <strong>the</strong>reby unify<strong>in</strong>g extraposition of adjuncts with <strong>the</strong> well-known flexibility <strong>in</strong> (3)<br />

and with <strong>the</strong> anti-reconstruction properties of adjuncts discussed by Lebeaux (1988) <strong>in</strong> (4).<br />

(3) a. Read a book quietly (is what) John did (‘quietly’ <strong>in</strong>terpreted and l<strong>in</strong>earised as part of VP)<br />

b. Read a book (is what) John did quietly (‘quietly’ <strong>in</strong>terpreted but not l<strong>in</strong>earised as part of VP)<br />

(4) a. * Which argument that Johni is a genius did hei believe?<br />

b. Which argument that Johni made did hei believe?<br />

A central assumption of Hunter’s analysis is that each maximal projection is a spellout doma<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Hence a derivation is naturally partitioned <strong>in</strong>to “chunks”. Dur<strong>in</strong>g each chunk C, <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

a s<strong>in</strong>gle syntactic head X such that every merge step <strong>in</strong> C establishes ei<strong>the</strong>r a complement or<br />

a specifier of X. At <strong>the</strong> end of this chunk, spellout applies and produces an atomic word-like<br />

object, lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternal syntax but with <strong>the</strong> semantics, phonology, and formal features of <strong>the</strong> derivedXP,<br />

which can participate <strong>in</strong> a subsequent chunk of <strong>the</strong> derivation. Under this conception,<br />

“adjunction” of an elementAtakes place whenAis <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> derivational workspace<br />

but never merged. As before, semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretation and l<strong>in</strong>earization of A take place at <strong>the</strong><br />

po<strong>in</strong>t of spellout, but, because of <strong>the</strong> absence of merger, <strong>the</strong>se processes proceed without <strong>the</strong><br />

benefit of <strong>the</strong> configurational guidance that governs <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation and l<strong>in</strong>earization of arguments,<br />

e.g. <strong>the</strong> UTAH and <strong>the</strong> LCA. Hunter (2010) argues that this derivational dichotomy<br />

is supported by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretive and order<strong>in</strong>g flexibility found <strong>in</strong> adjuncts but not arguments.<br />

Typically, adjunction ofAtoXP takes place dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> chunk where its semantic associateXP<br />

is constructed. This is what takes place <strong>in</strong> (3a): ‘quietly’ is <strong>in</strong>troduced dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> derivational<br />

chunk of <strong>the</strong> VP it modifies and is spelled out at <strong>the</strong> conclusion of this chunk, concatenat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘quietly’ at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> VP. This allows front<strong>in</strong>g of ‘read a book quietly’.<br />

Note though that because adjunction<br />

of A to XP does not require<br />

reference to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal syntax of<br />

XP, <strong>the</strong>re is an alternative: A can<br />

be <strong>in</strong>troduced and spelled out dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> next higher chunk, say with head<br />

Y . Because spellout has access not<br />

Tim Hunter & Robert Frank (Yale)<br />

John<br />

VP<br />

read [a book]DP<br />

TP<br />

quietly<br />

quietly<br />

T [read a book]VP<br />

spellout<br />

−−−−−−→ read a book quietly<br />

spellout<br />

−−−−−−→ John read a book quietly<br />

only to Y , but also to <strong>the</strong> units merged as Y ’s complement and specifier, spellout can <strong>in</strong>terpret<br />

A as semantically modify<strong>in</strong>g one of <strong>the</strong>se units, say XP; with regard to l<strong>in</strong>earisation, we assume<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are two options: ei<strong>the</strong>r (i) <strong>the</strong> adjunct A may be concatenated to <strong>the</strong> edge of<br />

its hostXP, which reproduces <strong>the</strong> effects of Lebeaux’s (1988) counter-cyclic adjunction, or (ii)<br />

<strong>the</strong> adjunct A may be concatenated to <strong>the</strong> edge of <strong>the</strong> entire Y P chunk’s output, an operation<br />

we will call “outer adjunction”. Outer adjunction is responsible for (3b): ‘quietly’ is <strong>in</strong>troduced<br />

dur<strong>in</strong>g T’s chunk, <strong>in</strong>terpreted at spellout as semantically modify<strong>in</strong>g T’s complement, namely


VP, but concatenated to <strong>the</strong> edge of TP. Because spellout applied to VP dur<strong>in</strong>g a prior chunk, it<br />

functions as a unit and can be subsequently fronted without <strong>the</strong> adjunct ‘quietly’.<br />

On this account, extraposition amounts to <strong>the</strong> outer<br />

adjunction of a DP modifier at <strong>the</strong> phrase immediately<br />

TP who knew his bro<strong>the</strong>r<br />

conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> host, i.e. VP for objects, or TP for subjects.<br />

This expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> strict locality properties observed<br />

by Balt<strong>in</strong> (1981): material extraposed from sub-<br />

some<br />

would [ride with Fred]VP<br />

ject position can (and must) be stranded under VP front<strong>in</strong>g/ellipsis, as shown <strong>in</strong> (5), whereas<br />

material extraposed from object position cannot be, as shown <strong>in</strong> (6).<br />

(5) [Some ] would ride with Fred [who knew his bro<strong>the</strong>r].<br />

a. Ride with Fred, some would who knew his bro<strong>the</strong>r. (RC stranded by front<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

b. * Ride with Fred who knew his bro<strong>the</strong>r, some would. (RC brought along by front<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

(6) John said that he would call [people ] up [who are from Boston], and . . .<br />

a. * . . . call people up he did who are from Boston. (RC stranded by front<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

b. . . . call people up who are from Boston he did. (RC brought along by front<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

As a result, elements extraposed from objects<br />

will <strong>in</strong> general precede those extraposed from sub-<br />

CP which were on <strong>the</strong> table<br />

jects; but if <strong>the</strong> object undergoes movement to a<br />

position higher than <strong>the</strong> subject, this gives rise to<br />

an additional derivational option for late adjunc-<br />

[which books]DP<br />

did [someone pick up . . . ]TP<br />

tion. The adjunct can be <strong>in</strong>troduced at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t where <strong>the</strong> object merges <strong>in</strong>to a higher specifier,<br />

giv<strong>in</strong>g rise to <strong>the</strong> possibility of <strong>the</strong> object modifier appear<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> far right.<br />

(7) a. ? Which book did someone pick up [which was on <strong>the</strong> table] [who didn’t really<br />

want to]?<br />

b. Which book did someone pick up [who didn’t really want to] [which was on <strong>the</strong><br />

table]?<br />

Fox and Nissenbaum (1999) note that extraposition obviates Condition C effects, but strik<strong>in</strong>gly,<br />

this obviation is restricted to adjuncts; see (8). This recalls <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>in</strong> (4) discussed<br />

by Lebeaux. S<strong>in</strong>ce our outer adjunction and counter-cyclic adjunction are <strong>in</strong>stances of <strong>the</strong> same<br />

mechanism (differ<strong>in</strong>g only <strong>in</strong> questions of l<strong>in</strong>earisation), this is as we would expect.<br />

(8) a. * I gave himi an argument [that supports Johni’s <strong>the</strong>ory] yesterday<br />

b. I gave himi an argument yesterday [that supports Johni’s <strong>the</strong>ory]<br />

c. * I gave him an argument yesterday [that this sentence supports John’s <strong>the</strong>ory]<br />

This <strong>in</strong>teracts <strong>in</strong> just <strong>the</strong> expected way with possibility of outer adjunction to non-base positions<br />

as <strong>in</strong> (7): extraposition from moved objects can obviate Condition C effects even <strong>in</strong> cases<br />

<strong>in</strong>duced by a subject b<strong>in</strong>der, as shown <strong>in</strong> (9) (from Culicover and Rochemont (1990)).<br />

(9) a. * Hei <strong>in</strong>vited several girls to <strong>the</strong> party that Johni dated <strong>in</strong> high school.<br />

b. How many girls did hei <strong>in</strong>vite to <strong>the</strong> party that Johni dated <strong>in</strong> high school.<br />

However, our implementation of counter-cyclic adjunction differs from Lebeaux’s <strong>in</strong> a crucial<br />

respect: it correctly predicts that anti-reconstruction should be sensitive to <strong>the</strong> depth of<br />

embedd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a manner similar to extraposition, as <strong>in</strong> (10) (Landau, 2007).<br />

(10) a. Food that Maryi cooks, shei knows I would never eat.<br />

b. * Eat food that Maryi cooks, shei knows I never would. (cf. (6a))<br />

Note f<strong>in</strong>ally that we have considered only right-adjuncts; <strong>the</strong>re should <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be similar<br />

phenomena with left-adjuncts. We will suggest that floated quantifiers constitute such a case.<br />

Balt<strong>in</strong>, M. (1981). Strict bound<strong>in</strong>g. In Baker, C. L. and McCarthy, J., editors, The Logical Problem of Language<br />

Acquisition. MIT Press.<br />

Culicover, P. W. and Rochemont, M. S. (1990). Extraposition and <strong>the</strong> complement pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry.<br />

Fox, D. and Nissenbaum, J. (1999). Extraposition and Scope: A case for overt QR. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of WCCFL 18.<br />

Hunter, T. (2010). Relat<strong>in</strong>g Movement and Adjunction <strong>in</strong> Syntax and Semantics. PhD <strong>the</strong>sis, U. of Maryland.<br />

Landau, I. (2007). Constra<strong>in</strong>ts on Partial VP-front<strong>in</strong>g. Syntax, 10(2):127–164.<br />

Lebeaux, D. (1988). Language acquisition and <strong>the</strong> form of <strong>the</strong> grammar. PhD <strong>the</strong>sis, UMass Amherst.


Laura Kal<strong>in</strong> (UCLA) & Coppe van Urk (MIT)<br />

A novel aspect split <strong>in</strong> Senaya<br />

Summary: This paper adds to <strong>the</strong> typology of aspect-based case/agreement splits by present<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> unusual system of <strong>the</strong> Neo-Aramaic dialect of Senaya. In Senaya, a nom<strong>in</strong>ativeaccusative<br />

system <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> imperfective alternates with what resembles an antipassive <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

perfective. We argue that this system can be derived from <strong>the</strong> assumption that imperfective<br />

aspect <strong>in</strong>troduces additional structure, developed <strong>in</strong> recent work on split ergativity (Laka<br />

2006; Coon 2010; Coon & Prem<strong>in</strong>ger 2011). Specifically, we argue that <strong>in</strong> Senaya imperfective<br />

aspect <strong>in</strong>troduces an additional case assigner not present <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective. We extend<br />

our analysis to o<strong>the</strong>r dialects of Neo-Aramaic <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> addition of <strong>the</strong> same φ-probe <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> imperfective results <strong>in</strong> a complete reversal of agreement.<br />

The data: Most nor<strong>the</strong>astern dialects of Neo-Aramaic display aspect-based split ergativity,<br />

with an ergative agreement alignment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective but an accusative one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imperfective (Doron & Khan 2010). In Senaya, however, this aspect-based split surfaces<br />

<strong>in</strong> an unusual way. As <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r Neo-Aramaic languages, <strong>the</strong>re are two sets of agreement<br />

morphemes — <strong>the</strong> so-called L-suffixes and S-suffixes. In <strong>the</strong> imperfective, an S-suffix on <strong>the</strong><br />

verb references <strong>the</strong> subject (1a-b), while def<strong>in</strong>ite objects are marked by an L-suffix (1b):<br />

(1)a. Axnii damx-ox. b. Aanii xazy-ii-lan<br />

we sleep.impf-1pl.S <strong>the</strong>y see.impf-3pl.S-1pl.L<br />

‘We sleep.’<br />

‘They see us.’<br />

In <strong>the</strong> perfective, however, someth<strong>in</strong>g closer to an antipassive is found, as <strong>the</strong> examples <strong>in</strong><br />

(2a-b) illustrate. The subject is marked on <strong>the</strong> verb with an L-suffix (<strong>the</strong> object marker of<br />

<strong>the</strong> imperfective), while objects cannot be marked and are <strong>the</strong>refore obligatorily <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite:<br />

(2)a. Axnii dmex-lan.<br />

b. Axnii xa yaala xzee-lan.<br />

we sleep.perf-1pl.L we one child see.perf-1pl.L<br />

‘We slept.’<br />

‘We saw a child.’<br />

Imperfective aspect <strong>in</strong>volves a locative head: Dixon (1994) observes that if a system<br />

has an aspect-based split, it is <strong>the</strong> perfective side of <strong>the</strong> split that displays an ergative<br />

pattern. To account for this generalization, it has been proposed that imperfective and/or<br />

progressive aspect may <strong>in</strong>troduce complex structure that disturbs <strong>the</strong> usual mechanis<strong>ms</strong> of<br />

case assignment, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form of a biclausal structure (Laka 2006; Coon 2010) or an<br />

additional phase boundary (Coon & Prem<strong>in</strong>ger 2011). Coon (2010) relates this to work<br />

by Demirdache & Uribe-Etxebarria (2000, 2007), who propose that aspect is encoded us<strong>in</strong>g<br />

spatiotemporal relations. They argue that nonperfective aspects make use of prepositional,<br />

locative relations, such as WITHIN, BEFORE, and AFTER; perfective aspect, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

hand, cannot be expressed this way, aris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stead as a default when Asp is empty. As such,<br />

nonperfective aspects <strong>in</strong>volve a locative predicate absent from perfective.<br />

The proposal: We assume <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of aspect-based splits outl<strong>in</strong>ed above and propose<br />

that, <strong>in</strong> Senaya, <strong>the</strong> prepositional locative head selected by imperfective Asp <strong>in</strong>troduces<br />

a φ-probe, whose reflex <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> morphology is an S-suffix. This P head agrees<br />

with and assigns case to <strong>the</strong> subject. As a result, <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary case/agreement pattern is<br />

disturbed, s<strong>in</strong>ce it enables <strong>the</strong> φ-probe on T (a morphological L-suffix) to license a def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

object. In addition, we assume that, aside from T and P under Asp, <strong>the</strong>re is no locus of<br />

agreement or case assigner <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> verbal sp<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> Senaya. As such, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective, only<br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite objects are licit, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite objects may pseudo-<strong>in</strong>corporate <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> verb as<br />

NPs and hence do not require case (Dayal 2011, Massam 2001).


Derivations: Perfective (<strong>in</strong>)transitive(3): NolocativePhead; Tprobes<strong>the</strong>subject, valu<strong>in</strong>g<br />

case/agr., seen as an L-suffix. No case/agr. locus is available to license a def<strong>in</strong>ite object.<br />

Imperfective <strong>in</strong>transitive (4): The P head under Asp probes and f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> subject, valu<strong>in</strong>g<br />

case/agr., seen as an S-suffix. T probes but f<strong>in</strong>ds no active argument. Imperfective transitive<br />

(4): Same as above, but T probes <strong>the</strong> object; agreement with T spells out as an L-suffix.<br />

(3)<br />

(4)<br />

T<br />

[nom]<br />

L-suffix<br />

DP subj<br />

v<br />

V (NP <strong>in</strong>def obj )<br />

T<br />

[nom]<br />

L-suffix Asp<br />

P<br />

[loc]<br />

S-suffix<br />

DP subj<br />

v V (DPobj )<br />

Extension to agreement reversal dialects: The analysis outl<strong>in</strong>ed here can be extended<br />

straightforwardly to so-called “extended ergative” dialects of Neo-Aramaic (Doron & Khan<br />

2010), e.g., Christian Barwar. In <strong>the</strong>se dialects, <strong>the</strong> perfective base can host agreement with<br />

an object, an S-suffix, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a complete reversal of agreement from <strong>the</strong> imperfective:<br />

(5)a. Tpít-le<br />

sneeze.perf-3<strong>ms</strong>.L<br />

‘He sneezed.’<br />

b. Qtil-á-le.<br />

kill.perf-3fs.S-3<strong>ms</strong>.L<br />

‘He killed her.’<br />

c. Mtăm@zz-a.<br />

clean.impf-3fs.S<br />

‘She cleans.’<br />

d. Qatl-á-le.<br />

kill.impf-3fs.S-3<strong>ms</strong>.L<br />

‘She kills him.’ (Khan 2008)<br />

The morpheme -le (3<strong>ms</strong>) marks <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>ative argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective, (5a,b), but<br />

<strong>the</strong> accusative one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> imperfective, (5d). The morpheme -a (3fs) marks <strong>the</strong> accusative<br />

argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective, (5b), but <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>ative one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> imperfective, (5c,d).<br />

The difference between <strong>the</strong>se dialects and Senaya, we argue, is <strong>the</strong> mechanism underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

L-suffixes. In Senaya, L-suffixes result from φ-agreement, evidenced by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

trigger stress shift, as true affixes do <strong>in</strong> Senaya. In C. Barwar and similar dialects, however,<br />

L-suffixes are clitics (Doron & Khan 2010). Follow<strong>in</strong>g Anagnostopoulou (2003) and Rezac<br />

(2011) among o<strong>the</strong>rs, we assume: (i) φ-probes split <strong>in</strong>to number and person, (ii) person<br />

probes before number, and (iii) clitic-doubled arguments are ignored by subsequent probes.<br />

Ifweposit, <strong>the</strong>n, that<strong>the</strong>personprobeonT<strong>in</strong>extendedergativedialects<strong>in</strong>discrim<strong>in</strong>ately<br />

triggers clitic-doubl<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> first argument encountered, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong> differences<br />

between Senaya and <strong>the</strong>se dialects fall out naturally. In <strong>the</strong> perfective, T licenses both<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject, by means of its person probe (⇒ clitic-doubl<strong>in</strong>g), and <strong>the</strong> object, by means<br />

of its number probe (⇒ agreement). In <strong>the</strong> imperfective, <strong>the</strong> φ-probe on P licenses <strong>the</strong><br />

subject, such that it is <strong>the</strong> object that gets clitic-doubled by person on T. Importantly,<br />

this account expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> object is limited to third person <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfective:<br />

this is a standard Person Case Constra<strong>in</strong>t (PCC) effect (Bonet 1991), and <strong>the</strong> above is<br />

straightforwardlycompatiblewi<strong>the</strong>xist<strong>in</strong>g accountsof<strong>the</strong>PCC(e.g., BéjarandRezac2003).<br />

Selected references: Coon, J.2010. Complementation <strong>in</strong> Chol: A <strong>the</strong>ory of split ergativity.<br />

Doctoral dissertation, MIT. – Doron, E., & G. Khan. 2010. The typology of morphological<br />

ergativity <strong>in</strong> Neo-Aramaic. <strong>ms</strong>. – Rezac, M. 2011. Phi-features and <strong>the</strong> modular architecture<br />

of language. Dordrecht: Spr<strong>in</strong>ger.


Laura Kertz (Brown)<br />

Referential Process<strong>in</strong>g Influences <strong>the</strong> Resolution of Verbal Anaphors<br />

Interest <strong>in</strong> verb phrase ellipsis has rebounded <strong>in</strong> recent years, as various proposals have<br />

sought to ref<strong>in</strong>e predictions from l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>the</strong>ory by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g process<strong>in</strong>g-based assumptions.<br />

The long-stand<strong>in</strong>g Surface/Deep Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis of Hankamer & Sag (1976) holds that verb phrase<br />

ellipsis (like o<strong>the</strong>r surface anaphors) is governed by a parallelism constra<strong>in</strong>t which does not<br />

apply to deep/proform anaphora. Under this approach, parallelism is implicated <strong>in</strong> both <strong>the</strong><br />

licens<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>terpretation of elliptical anaphors. It has been demonstrated that non-parallel verb<br />

phrase ellipses, for example, take longer to read and are rated less acceptable than comparable<br />

parallel structures. It is well-known, however, that <strong>the</strong> parallelism effect under ellipsis is<br />

unreliable and that parallelism effects are observed even for deep anaphors.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong>re is scant evidence to demonstrate that parallelism actually constra<strong>in</strong>s possible<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations for an ellipsis. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> auxiliary verb govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ellipsis<br />

site can force ei<strong>the</strong>r a parallel or a non-parallel <strong>in</strong>terpretation, as <strong>in</strong> (1).<br />

(1) The accident was <strong>in</strong>vestigated by <strong>the</strong> police, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>surance company did/was too.<br />

Indeed Garnham & Oakhill (1987) show that when <strong>the</strong> auxiliary is ambiguous, <strong>the</strong> preference for<br />

a parallel <strong>in</strong>terpretation competes with a preference for choos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> most plausible antecedent.<br />

If it is not <strong>the</strong> case that parallelism constra<strong>in</strong>s possible <strong>in</strong>terpretations, <strong>the</strong> question emerges:<br />

What role does parallelism play <strong>in</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g ellipsis?<br />

A recent proposal (Arregui et al 2006) holds that non-parallel antecedents <strong>in</strong>duce extra<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g costs associated with syntactic repair at <strong>the</strong> ellipsis site. Similarly, Kim et al (2010)<br />

argue that parallelism effects arise as a function of pars<strong>in</strong>g heuristics that favor canonical<br />

(parallel) VP antecedents. Both of <strong>the</strong>se proposals seek to reconcile a categorical licens<strong>in</strong>g<br />

mechanism with an <strong>in</strong>herently gradient performance model. An alternative view holds that<br />

parallelism effects under ellipsis are epiphenomenal. Kehler (2000, 2002), for example, argues<br />

that parallelism effects arise as an <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>the</strong> establishment of discourse coherence<br />

relations and processes support<strong>in</strong>g ellipsis resolution, while Kertz (2010) argues that parallelism<br />

effects follow from general <strong>in</strong>formation structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> alignment of contrastive<br />

arguments. Each of <strong>the</strong>se latter two proposals makes <strong>the</strong> specific prediction that parallelism<br />

effects arise <strong>in</strong> ellipses where <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> target clause is contrastive with a syntactically<br />

non-parallel argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent clause.<br />

The current study tested this prediction by compar<strong>in</strong>g effects of <strong>the</strong> referential status of <strong>the</strong><br />

subject noun phrase preced<strong>in</strong>g an ellipsis on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of that ellipsis. Stimuli used for <strong>the</strong><br />

study featured ei<strong>the</strong>r a lexical NP (<strong>the</strong> firefighters) which contrasted with an argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

preced<strong>in</strong>g clause or a pronoun (it) which was co-referent with an argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g<br />

clause. The referential status of <strong>the</strong> pronoun was crossed with <strong>the</strong> form of <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

(parallel vs. non-parallel). A sample stimulus set is shown <strong>in</strong> (2)-(3).<br />

(2) The rangers didn’t <strong>in</strong>spect <strong>the</strong> campsite as thoroughly as<br />

<strong>the</strong> firefighters did. [lexical NP, parallel] / it could have been. [pronoun, non-parallel]<br />

(3) The campsite wasn’t <strong>in</strong>spected by <strong>the</strong> rangers as thoroughly as<br />

<strong>the</strong> firefighters did. [lexical NP, non-parallel] / it could have been. [pronoun, parallel]<br />

A parallel discourse relationship was made explicit by <strong>the</strong> use of an equative adverbial<br />

construction. Thus participants were not faced with <strong>the</strong> task of determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> coherence<br />

relation obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g between <strong>the</strong> antecedent and <strong>the</strong> target. Interpretation of <strong>the</strong> ellipsis, however,


did require properly identify<strong>in</strong>g co-referent/contrastive arguments across <strong>the</strong> two clauses. For<br />

pronouns, coreference was unambiguously signaled by number mark<strong>in</strong>g; for lexical NPs, we<br />

predicted that identification of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended contrast between <strong>the</strong> firefighters and <strong>the</strong> rangers<br />

would be dependent on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> rangers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent occurred <strong>in</strong> a parallel (subject)<br />

position. We fur<strong>the</strong>r predicted that successful identification of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended contrast <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

parallel condition would lead to facilitation at <strong>the</strong> auxiliary verb region, where ellipsis resolution<br />

is <strong>in</strong>itiated.<br />

Sixteen stimulus sets like (2)-(3) were tested <strong>in</strong> an offl<strong>in</strong>e magnitude estimation task (n=36).<br />

Stimuli were adapted to <strong>in</strong>clude a spill-over region follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ellipsis for a self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

task (n=48). Statistical analysis was conducted on log-transformed ratios of stimulus to modulus<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ME task and on both raw and residual read<strong>in</strong>g times trimmed to 3sd by region for <strong>the</strong> SPR<br />

task. (Results for raw and residual analyses were identical.) For all analyses, a mixed effects<br />

analysis with forward model selection for <strong>in</strong>clusion of random effects was conducted.<br />

Offl<strong>in</strong>e results showed an <strong>in</strong>teraction where non-parallel structures were dispreferred<br />

compared to parallel structures, but that difference was greater with lexical NPs. Onl<strong>in</strong>e, no<br />

statistically reliable effects of parallelism were observed. At <strong>the</strong> subject NP region, a crossover<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction was observed where lexical NPs were read more slowly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> parallel condition<br />

while pronouns were read more quickly. At <strong>the</strong> auxiliary verb region an effect of subject type<br />

only was observed. No reliable effects were observed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> post-ellipsis spill-over region.<br />

0.2<br />

0<br />

-0.2<br />

-0.4<br />

Offl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

Acceptability<br />

parallel non-parallel<br />

lexical NP pronoun<br />

550<br />

500<br />

450<br />

400<br />

350<br />

300<br />

<strong>the</strong> firefighters<br />

it<br />

<strong>Raw</strong> <strong>Read<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>Times</strong> (<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

did<br />

could have been<br />

after <strong>the</strong><br />

after <strong>the</strong><br />

lexical NP<br />

parallel<br />

lexical NP<br />

non-parallel<br />

pronoun<br />

parallel<br />

pronoun<br />

non-parallel<br />

Consistent with f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>, e.g. Birch & Rayner (1997), we <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased read<strong>in</strong>g times<br />

for <strong>the</strong> lexical NPs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> parallel condition as evidence that readers treated <strong>the</strong>se NPs as<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guistically focused constituents, i.e. readers recognized <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended contrast between <strong>the</strong> two<br />

arguments. Identification of focus <strong>in</strong> this region had a downstream effect of reduc<strong>in</strong>g process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

time at <strong>the</strong> ellipsis. In <strong>the</strong> non-parallel, lexical NP condition, this facilitative effect was not<br />

observed, and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronoun conditions, no effects of parallelism were seen.<br />

These results thus confirm <strong>the</strong> prediction that parallelism <strong>in</strong>teracts with referential process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

for contrastive noun phrases, which can <strong>in</strong> turn <strong>in</strong>fluence verbal anaphor resolution. This<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction was also seen to <strong>in</strong>fluence offl<strong>in</strong>e acceptability. While <strong>the</strong> results are not <strong>in</strong>compatible<br />

with models that would reta<strong>in</strong> a categorical licens<strong>in</strong>g mechanism for ellipsis, <strong>the</strong> results do show<br />

that parallelism constra<strong>in</strong>ts on process<strong>in</strong>g are weak/violable and crucially <strong>in</strong>teract <strong>in</strong> a<br />

predictable manner with o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of <strong>the</strong> discourse context.


Ezra Keshet (Michigan)<br />

Scopal Effects of Embedded Coherence Relations<br />

Researchers s<strong>in</strong>ce Hobbs (1979) have proposed that an important part of understand<strong>in</strong>g a mult-­‐<br />

sentence discourse is understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> (often unspoken) relationship between <strong>the</strong> various<br />

sentences (see also Kehler 2002 and Asher and Lascarides 2003). For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> two<br />

sentences of (1) below are not understood as be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dependent of one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Instead,<br />

speakers tend to <strong>in</strong>fer a relationship between paraphraseable as <strong>in</strong> (2):<br />

(1) John ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish. He got horrible food poison<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(2) John got horrible food poison<strong>in</strong>g because he ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish.<br />

Such connections between sentences <strong>in</strong> a discourse are known as coherence relations. In (1),<br />

<strong>the</strong> second sentence is understood to be <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> first, and <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> coherence<br />

relation <strong>in</strong> effect here is called <strong>the</strong> Result relation.<br />

This phenomenon immediately raises <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g questions about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between<br />

grammar and context: for <strong>in</strong>stance, what is <strong>the</strong> grammatical status of such coherence relations?<br />

Are <strong>the</strong>y due to purely pragmatic reason<strong>in</strong>g, or is <strong>the</strong>re some syntactic component responsible<br />

for such <strong>in</strong>ferences? Do <strong>the</strong>y only hold at <strong>the</strong> sentence level, or can <strong>the</strong>y affect sentence-­‐<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal mean<strong>in</strong>g? Rohde, Levy, and Kehler (2011) take a stab at this last question, exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

cases like (3), a s<strong>in</strong>gle sentence whose <strong>in</strong>ternal clauses seem to exhibit <strong>the</strong> same potential for<br />

coherence relations as <strong>the</strong> separate sentences of (1). Example (3) is usually understood as <strong>in</strong><br />

(4), thus exhibit<strong>in</strong>g an Explanation relation between <strong>the</strong> matrix clause and <strong>the</strong> relative clause.<br />

(3) John detests <strong>the</strong> coworkers who are arrogant and rude.<br />

(4) John detests <strong>the</strong> coworkers who are arrogant and rude because <strong>the</strong>y are arrogant and<br />

rude.<br />

Rohde et al (2011) show experimentally that such sentence-­‐<strong>in</strong>ternal coherence relations can<br />

<strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of a purely syntactic phenomenon, namely where to attach a<br />

prepositional phrase. This suggests that whe<strong>the</strong>r coherence is pragmatic or <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> grammar, it<br />

plays a role <strong>in</strong> sentence-­‐<strong>in</strong>ternal mean<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

This paper takes a step fur<strong>the</strong>r and suggests that coherence relations arise due to a covert<br />

syntactic operator, which can <strong>in</strong>teract with scopal elements such as quantifiers. Take (5), for<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance, which see<strong>ms</strong> to have a sentence-­‐<strong>in</strong>ternal Result relation between <strong>the</strong> relative clause<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong> matrix sentence:<br />

(5) Everyone who ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish got horrible food poison<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Imag<strong>in</strong>e that party guests A, B, and C all ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish and got food poison<strong>in</strong>g. The crucial<br />

observation is that <strong>the</strong> coherence <strong>in</strong>fe������������������������������<br />

������������������������������������������������<br />

shellfish <strong>in</strong>gestion r���������������������������������������<br />

<strong>in</strong> ���������������������������������������������<br />

�����������������������������������������������<br />

thought to lead to his or her own poison<strong>in</strong>g. Some similar examples:


(6) Everyone who John detested was arrogant and rude. [Explanation]<br />

(7) No one who drank pomegranate juice regularly got cancer. [Result]<br />

(8) No one who John detests is ever nice to him. [Explanation]<br />

I propose to capture <strong>the</strong>se connections with a set of covert syntactic operators that presuppose<br />

a relationship between <strong>the</strong> event represented by <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>the</strong>y appear <strong>in</strong> and a<br />

contextually previous event (assum<strong>in</strong>g that events may be states or dynamic events). For<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> structure I propose for (1) is given <strong>in</strong> (9), and a few relevant operator def<strong>in</strong>itions<br />

are given below:<br />

(9) [[John ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish] =e1] [[Result(e1) [He got food poison<strong>in</strong>g]] =e2]<br />

(10) ������������������������������������������<br />

(11) ����������������������������������<br />

����������������������������<br />

�������������������������������<br />

(12) �������������������������������������������<br />

����������������������������������������<br />

An example like (5) arises when such operators scope below a quantifier, as shown below:<br />

(13) [Everyone whox [[x ate <strong>the</strong> shellfish] =e1]]x [[Result(e1) [x got food poison<strong>in</strong>g]] =e2]]<br />

Here, <strong>the</strong> variable e1 is an e-­‐type pronoun rang<strong>in</strong>g over events where different <strong>in</strong>dividuals x eat<br />

shellfish. The Result operator that scopes below <strong>the</strong> quantification DP relates each such event<br />

to <strong>the</strong> event where <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>dividual x gets food poison<strong>in</strong>g. (I named all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

variables <strong>in</strong> (13) x s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y all end up pick<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>dividual.)<br />

If such operators exist, <strong>the</strong>y should <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple give rise to scope ambiguities, and this is exactly<br />

what I propose happens <strong>in</strong> (14):<br />

(14) John is arrogant and rude. Everyone he works with detests him.<br />

One read<strong>in</strong>g of (14) is that each <strong>in</strong>dividual coworker happens to detest John for <strong>the</strong> same<br />

reason � namely that he is arrogant and rude. Co-­‐worker A detests him for this reason, co-­‐<br />

worker B detests him for this reason, etc. I argue that this read<strong>in</strong>g arises when a Result<br />

operator scopes below <strong>the</strong> quantificational DP Everyone he works with analogously to structure<br />

(13). However, <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r read<strong>in</strong>g of (14) � one where <strong>the</strong> fact that John is arrogant and<br />

rude expla<strong>in</strong>s why every one of his co-­‐workers detests him. Perhaps co-­‐workers A and B detest<br />

arrogant people, and C and D detest rude people. It is because John is arrogant and rude that<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole office detests him. I argue that this read<strong>in</strong>g arises when a Result operator scopes<br />

above <strong>the</strong> quantificational DP.<br />

This new evidence suggests a close connection between coherence relations and grammar.<br />

After mak<strong>in</strong>g this argument, <strong>the</strong> paper concludes by exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction of such<br />

coherence operators with o<strong>the</strong>r scopal operators, such as modals, and by look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> effect<br />

this analysis might have on a <strong>the</strong>ory of anaphora.


Arnout Koornneef & Eric Reuland (Utrecht)<br />

Grammar and Process<strong>in</strong>g Economy<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> relation between grammar and <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

system concerns <strong>the</strong> resolution of anaphoric dependencies. What is <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong><br />

various sub-components of <strong>the</strong> language system (syntax, logical form, discourse) and<br />

how can <strong>the</strong>ir roles be dist<strong>in</strong>guished as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of an utterance develops<br />

through time? We know that at least two fundamentally different types of <strong>in</strong>terpretive<br />

processes must be dist<strong>in</strong>guished <strong>in</strong> anaphora resolution (leav<strong>in</strong>g aside lexical and<br />

strictly syntactic encod<strong>in</strong>g): Coreference (cont<strong>in</strong>gently assign<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same value to<br />

two expressions) and Variable B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g (VB) (Heim 1982, Re<strong>in</strong>hart 1983, Reuland<br />

2001, 2011). VB is encoded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> grammatical system and sensitive to particular<br />

structural conditions (e.g. c-command), but <strong>the</strong> former is freely available, modulo a<br />

regulatory pr<strong>in</strong>ciple such as Re<strong>in</strong>hart and Grodz<strong>in</strong>sky (1993)’s Rule I, or Reuland<br />

(2011)’s Rejection is F<strong>in</strong>al. The operative pr<strong>in</strong>ciple here is an economy preference for<br />

b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g over co-reference. For details about <strong>the</strong> economy metric, based on <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

that cross-modular steps carry a cost, see Reuland (2001, 2011).<br />

This ties <strong>in</strong> with a debate <strong>in</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g studies. A consistent f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> offl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

studies on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of ambiguous VP-ellipses is that bound-variable (BV)<br />

based <strong>in</strong>terpretations are preferred over coreferential <strong>in</strong>terpretations, see Frazier and<br />

Clifton 2000 (F&C) for an overview.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> basis of such results – see also Avrut<strong>in</strong> (1999), and Vasic´ et al. (2006)<br />

for a more recent result <strong>in</strong> agrammatic aphasics - F&C formulate and test, us<strong>in</strong>g selfpaced<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g and questionnaires, <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>in</strong> (1):<br />

(1) LF only/first hypo<strong>the</strong>sis: Bound-variable <strong>in</strong>terpretations are preferred because<br />

<strong>the</strong> perceiver need only consult <strong>the</strong> LF representation (not <strong>the</strong> discourse<br />

representation) <strong>in</strong> order to identify <strong>the</strong> bound-variable analysis of <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

F&C f<strong>in</strong>d two proble<strong>ms</strong> with (1): i. With some qualifications, a BV-preference also<br />

appears to obta<strong>in</strong> across sentence boundaries, as <strong>in</strong> (2), which accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>m is<br />

<strong>in</strong>compatible with <strong>the</strong> conception of LF. ii. They f<strong>in</strong>d a preference for a co-referential<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> only-sentences as <strong>in</strong> (3b).<br />

(2) The clown loves his cat. The acrobat does too.<br />

(3) a. Only Alfred th<strong>in</strong>ks (that) he is a good cook.<br />

b. Only Alfred th<strong>in</strong>ks that Alfred is a good cook (coreference)<br />

c. The only person who th<strong>in</strong>ks of hi<strong>ms</strong>elf as a good cook is Alfred. (BV).<br />

As we will briefly show, problem i. is resolved by us<strong>in</strong>g an explicit <strong>the</strong>ory of ellipsis,<br />

as <strong>in</strong> Elbourne (2008). Our paper <strong>the</strong>refore focuses on ii. We will consider not only<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>the</strong> processor assigns, but also <strong>the</strong> process lead<strong>in</strong>g to this<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. For <strong>the</strong> latter one needs on-l<strong>in</strong>e evidence, which so far is almost absent.<br />

In a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of two experiments (i. a questionnaire; and ii. an eyetrack<strong>in</strong>g<br />

experiment) we show that <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g preference is not solely an offl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

phenomenon, but can be detected <strong>in</strong> real-time measures of language comprehension.<br />

Contra F&C we found that <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g preference of <strong>the</strong> language processor shows up<br />

<strong>in</strong> ambiguous structures with <strong>the</strong> only-operator as well.<br />

In both experiments short stories were presented conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a critical sentence that<br />

was ambiguous between a sloppy and a strict read<strong>in</strong>g. There were 4 categories:<br />

[Sloppy-bias, only-operator], [Strict-bias, only-operator], [Sloppy-bias, ellipsis],<br />

[Strict-bias, ellipsis]. For space reasons we only illustrate <strong>the</strong> type of story we used:<br />

(4) Lisa and Anouk love <strong>the</strong> music channel MTV. They were very happy when <strong>the</strong>y<br />

were selected for <strong>the</strong> show ‘‘Pimp My Room,’’ <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>ir roo<strong>ms</strong> were<br />

redecorated. Only Lisa th<strong>in</strong>ks that her pimped room has a touch of class. Oh<br />

well, to each <strong>the</strong>ir owntaste. (sloppy bias)


The aim of experiment i. was two-fold: a. to pretest materials for experiment ii; and b.<br />

to provide a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary check on <strong>the</strong> solidity of F&C’s questionnaire f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

There were 20 participants. The materials were 36 short stories. The stories were<br />

directly followed by two <strong>in</strong>ferences that were consistent with ei<strong>the</strong>r a sloppy or a<br />

strict <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The participants had to rate both <strong>in</strong>ferences, and <strong>in</strong>dicate which<br />

one <strong>the</strong>y preferred. F<strong>in</strong>ally, participants rated <strong>the</strong> stories on difficulty and plausibility.<br />

Overall, <strong>the</strong> results revealed that it was easier to create a bias towards a sloppy<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g, which is consistent with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of ambiguity <strong>the</strong><br />

parser prefers a bound-variable dependency over a coreferential dependency.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, planned pairwise comparisons showed that <strong>the</strong> proper <strong>in</strong>ference of<br />

strict-biased stories <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> only-condition was relatively difficult to obta<strong>in</strong>. In addition,<br />

<strong>the</strong>se stories were also rated more difficult and less plausible than strict biased stories<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ellipsis condition. In all, <strong>the</strong>se rat<strong>in</strong>gs suggest that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> stories with <strong>the</strong> onlyoperator,<br />

<strong>the</strong> strict read<strong>in</strong>g is less accessible, which is <strong>in</strong>consistent with an account <strong>in</strong><br />

which <strong>the</strong> preference for a bound-variable dependency is stronger <strong>in</strong> ambiguous<br />

ellipses than <strong>in</strong> ambiguous only-structures.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> eye-track<strong>in</strong>g experiment <strong>the</strong> pretested stimuli were presented to 32<br />

healthy adults who did not participate <strong>in</strong> experiment i. Our model predicts that readers<br />

prefer a BV <strong>in</strong>terpretation regardless of <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g discourse. That<br />

is, <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>itially assign a sloppy <strong>in</strong>terpretation, which requires back-track<strong>in</strong>g once all<br />

discourse <strong>in</strong>formation is processed.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> ellipsis region (note, though, that this region is absent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> onlyconditions)<br />

<strong>the</strong> regression-path measure revealed a clear advantage for sloppy<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations, show<strong>in</strong>g reliably that <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g preference is not solely an offl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

phenomenon, but is also observable <strong>in</strong> onl<strong>in</strong>e measures of language comprehension.<br />

The results are consistent with <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>in</strong> strict-biased stories readers<br />

experience proble<strong>ms</strong>, because <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>itially try to <strong>in</strong>tegrate a sloppy <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong>to<br />

a strict context. Before mov<strong>in</strong>g on, <strong>the</strong>y have to change <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>terpretation to resolve<br />

this <strong>in</strong>consistency and longer regressions-path durations are <strong>the</strong>refore expected.<br />

The second sentence region revealed a clear contrast between first-pass and<br />

second-pass eye movement measures. The second-pass durations were almost twice<br />

as long for <strong>the</strong> strict-biased stories. Apparently, readers need to reexam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> second<br />

sentence (conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> critical manipulation) longer if <strong>the</strong>y process a strict-biased<br />

story. This was true for both ellipses and only-structures. Hence, <strong>the</strong> preference for<br />

sloppy <strong>in</strong>terpretations reflects a more general property of <strong>the</strong> language processor.<br />

These results give a clearer picture of what happens while readers encounter<br />

<strong>the</strong> sloppy-strict ambiguity, and support our economy based model. There were some<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs, shedd<strong>in</strong>g light on <strong>the</strong> details of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation process<br />

which we will discuss if time permits.<br />

Selected References<br />

Avrut<strong>in</strong>, S. 1999. Development of <strong>the</strong> syntax-discourse <strong>in</strong>terface. Dordrecht: Kluwer<br />

Elbourne, P. 2008. Ellipsis Sites as Def<strong>in</strong>ite Descriptions. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 39, 191-<br />

220<br />

Frazier, L., & Clifton, C. 2000. On bound variable <strong>in</strong>terpretations: The LF-only<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Journal of Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic Research, 29, 125–139<br />

Koornneef, A.W. 2008. Eye-catch<strong>in</strong>g Anaphora. Utrecht: LOT dissertation<br />

Reuland, E. 2011. Anaphora and Language Design. MIT Press<br />

Vasic´, N., Avrut<strong>in</strong>, S., & Ruigendijk, E. 2006. Interpretation of pronouns <strong>in</strong> VPellipsis<br />

constructions <strong>in</strong> Dutch Broca’s and Wernicke’s aphasia. Bra<strong>in</strong> and Language,<br />

96, 191–206.


Hadas Kotek (MIT)<br />

Wh-Front<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a Two-Probe System<br />

The study of wh-movement has dist<strong>in</strong>guished among several types of wh-front<strong>in</strong>g languages that<br />

permit dist<strong>in</strong>ct patterns of overt and covert movement, <strong>in</strong>stantiated for example by <strong>the</strong> Slavic<br />

languages, English and German (Beck 2006). In this talk I extend <strong>the</strong> cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic typology of<br />

multiple questions by argu<strong>in</strong>g that Hebrew <strong>in</strong>stantiates a new k<strong>in</strong>d of wh-front<strong>in</strong>g language, unlike<br />

any that are presently discussed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature. I will show that Hebrew dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between two<br />

k<strong>in</strong>ds of wh-phrases—those that are headed by a wh-word (wh-headed phrases: what, who, [ DP which X],<br />

where ...) and those that conta<strong>in</strong> a wh-word but are headed by some o<strong>the</strong>r element (wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

phrases: [ NP N of wh], [ PP P wh] …). Wh-headed phrases are privileged <strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y can be targeted by<br />

Agree/Attract operations that ignore mere wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrases <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same structure.<br />

To establish <strong>the</strong> privileged status of wh-headed phrases, I exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> behavior of multiple questions<br />

<strong>in</strong> Hebrew. I first observe that, as with D-l<strong>in</strong>ked wh-phrases <strong>in</strong> English, <strong>the</strong>re is a correlation <strong>in</strong><br />

Hebrew between apparent superiority violations and <strong>in</strong>tervention effects (Pesetsky 2000). I add a<br />

third correlate to this f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, concern<strong>in</strong>g possible read<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> questions:<br />

(1) a. Superiority-Obey<strong>in</strong>g Questions (SOQs) never exhibit <strong>in</strong>tervention effects; <strong>the</strong>y may have<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle-pair answers as well as pair-list answers.<br />

b. Superiority-Violat<strong>in</strong>g Questions (SVQs) are grammatical but <strong>the</strong>y are sensitive to Beck<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervention effects; <strong>the</strong>y may only have pair-list answers but not s<strong>in</strong>gle-pair answers.<br />

I will show that <strong>the</strong>se facts can be captured with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of Q-particles under standard<br />

assumptions about superiority and <strong>in</strong>tervention effects (Pesetsky 2000, Beck 2006, Cable 2010). In<br />

<strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivation of SOQs, all wh-phrases move to Spec,CP by LF. In <strong>the</strong> derivation<br />

of SVQs <strong>the</strong> higher wh-phrase is left <strong>in</strong> situ, allow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> lower wh-phrase to be <strong>the</strong> first element<br />

attracted to Spec,CP. Intervention effects arise when a focus-sensitive element occurs between <strong>the</strong><br />

wh-<strong>in</strong>-situ and <strong>the</strong> head with which it Agrees. I adopt an economy pr<strong>in</strong>ciple on LFs based on <strong>the</strong><br />

work of Fox (2000) which, toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> work of Dayal (2002) on <strong>the</strong> presuppositions of s<strong>in</strong>glepair<br />

and pair-list answers, can expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> distribution of read<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

The evidence for <strong>the</strong> existence of two k<strong>in</strong>ds of wh-phrases <strong>in</strong> Hebrew comes from <strong>the</strong> same three<br />

sources: superiority, <strong>in</strong>tervention effects and read<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> questions. We observe <strong>the</strong> special status<br />

of wh-headed phrases when a wh-headed phrase occurs structurally lower <strong>in</strong> a question than a whconta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

phrase. I argue that <strong>in</strong> that case, certa<strong>in</strong> operations target <strong>the</strong> lower wh-headed phrase and<br />

entirely overlook <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> higher wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase. This allows <strong>the</strong> question to be<br />

derived from a structure <strong>in</strong> which no wh-phrase rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> situ at LF; <strong>the</strong> first operation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

derivation is one that only targets wh-headed phrases and a subsequent operation is one that can<br />

target <strong>the</strong> (higher) wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase. This derivation correctly predicts that such questions are<br />

not sensitive to Beck <strong>in</strong>tervention effects and have s<strong>in</strong>gle-pair (as well as pair-list) answers.<br />

One example of <strong>the</strong> privileged status of wh-headed phrases is illustrated by <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imal pairs <strong>in</strong> (2ac).<br />

These example conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> optional object marker et—analyzed here as a preposition—on <strong>the</strong><br />

direct object of read. When et is present, <strong>the</strong> phrase et ma is headed by et and is hence a wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

phrase; when et is absent, bare ma is a wh-headed phrase. Questions with <strong>the</strong> (based-generated)<br />

configuration [wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase 1] ≫ [wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase 2] behave as expected: <strong>the</strong> SOQ is<br />

grammatical, (2a), but <strong>the</strong> SVQ is ungrammatical when an <strong>in</strong>tervener (here: negation) is present,<br />

(2b). In <strong>the</strong> configuration [wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase 1] ≫ [wh-headed phrase 2] we f<strong>in</strong>d that <strong>the</strong> SVQ is<br />

unexpectedly not sensitive to <strong>the</strong> presence of an <strong>in</strong>tervener, (2c), and that it can have a s<strong>in</strong>gle-pair<br />

answer as well as a pair-list answer, just like <strong>the</strong> superiority-obey<strong>in</strong>g question.<br />

(2) Unexpected lack of <strong>in</strong>tervention effect <strong>in</strong> superiority-violat<strong>in</strong>g question<br />

a. [et mi] ha-mora lo šixne’a [ likro (et) [ma] ]?<br />

OM who <strong>the</strong>-teacher neg persuaded to.read OM what


‘Who did <strong>the</strong> teacher not persuade to read what?’<br />

b. *[et ma] ha-mora lo šixne’a [et mi] [ likro ___ ]?<br />

OM what <strong>the</strong>-teacher neg persuaded OM who to.read<br />

c. ? [ma] ha-mora lo šixne’a [et mi] [ likro ___ ]?<br />

what <strong>the</strong>-teacher neg persuaded OM who to.read<br />

‘What did <strong>the</strong> teacher not persuade whom to read?’<br />

The sensitivity of <strong>in</strong>terrogative prob<strong>in</strong>g operations to material <strong>in</strong>side QP is unexpected <strong>in</strong> Cable's Q<strong>the</strong>ory<br />

framework, given <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>in</strong> (3a). I will propose two m<strong>in</strong>imal, yet significant, additions<br />

to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. First, I adopt a f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed structure of QP <strong>in</strong> Hebrew-type wh-front<strong>in</strong>g languages: I<br />

propose that when Q is merged with XP, it immediately attracts <strong>the</strong> next lower head, X. After X<br />

head-moves to Q, <strong>the</strong>y both project and become co-heads of <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g phrase. The derivation of<br />

wh-<strong>in</strong>-situ languages and of English/German-type wh-front<strong>in</strong>g languages proceeds as <strong>in</strong> Cable (2010):<br />

if X projects we derive a wh-<strong>in</strong>-situ language like Japanese or Korean. If Q projects we derive <strong>the</strong><br />

familiar English/German-type wh-front<strong>in</strong>g language <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal structure of QP is opaque<br />

to <strong>the</strong> outside derivation. If both X and Q project we derive a Hebrew-type wh-front<strong>in</strong>g language, <strong>in</strong><br />

which not only Q but also X is visible to outside prob<strong>in</strong>g. Crucially, we predict that a wh-word<br />

projects to <strong>the</strong> QP level when it is <strong>the</strong> head of XP but not when it is buried somewhere with<strong>in</strong> XP.<br />

We can thus dist<strong>in</strong>guish between wh-headed phrases (3bi) and wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrases (3bii).<br />

(3) a. proposal <strong>in</strong> Cable (2010) b. proposed new QP structure for Hebrew-type wh-front<strong>in</strong>g languages:<br />

for all wh-front<strong>in</strong>g languages (i) wh-headed phrases (ii) wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrases<br />

QwhP<br />

QP<br />

X+QP<br />

XP<br />

XP<br />

XP<br />

Q<br />

Q<br />

Q<br />

wh<br />

…<br />

X<br />

… wh …<br />

… wh …<br />

Moreover, I propose that our <strong>the</strong>ory must have a wh-probe <strong>in</strong> addition to <strong>the</strong> Q-probe. The Q-probe<br />

operates <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> familiar way, target<strong>in</strong>g any k<strong>in</strong>d of wh-phrase. The wh-probe, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, only<br />

targets wh-headed phrases and cannot detect <strong>the</strong> presence of wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrases. This proposal, I<br />

argue, <strong>in</strong>corporates all of <strong>the</strong> advantages of Cable’s orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>the</strong>ory but is empirically superior <strong>in</strong><br />

provid<strong>in</strong>g a natural explanation for an <strong>in</strong>tricate set of data that is o<strong>the</strong>rwise unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed. In addition,<br />

I suggest that this proposal is conceptually more appeal<strong>in</strong>g than <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>the</strong>ory s<strong>in</strong>ce it allows for<br />

all <strong>in</strong>terrogative phrases <strong>in</strong> a question to undergo syntactic Agreement, whereas <strong>in</strong> Cable’s <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

some phrases trigger <strong>in</strong>terrogative semantics but are <strong>in</strong>visible to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise correspond<strong>in</strong>g syntax.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, I show that <strong>the</strong> complicated system of <strong>in</strong>terrogative prob<strong>in</strong>g that emerges from <strong>the</strong> addition<br />

of a second probe <strong>in</strong>teracts <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g ways with locality restrictions: Superiority reemerges when a<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ite clause-boundary is <strong>in</strong>troduced between <strong>the</strong> two wh-phrases. In this configuration, superiority<br />

can be violated just <strong>in</strong> case a lower wh-headed phrase is moved over a wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g phrase, see (4ab).<br />

Surpris<strong>in</strong>gly, we <strong>the</strong>n observe <strong>in</strong>tervention effects for <strong>the</strong> question <strong>in</strong> (4b), and <strong>the</strong> only possible<br />

answer is pair-list. I will show how my proposal can be extended to account for <strong>the</strong>se facts.<br />

(4) Superiority effect reemerges when wh’s separated by clause boundary, and <strong>the</strong> exception to <strong>the</strong> rule<br />

a. *[et ma] ha-mora šixne’a [et mi] [ CP še-Yosi kara ___ ]?<br />

OM what <strong>the</strong>-teacher persuaded OM who that-Yosi read<br />

b. ? [ma] ha-mora šixne’a [et mi] [ CP še-Yosi kara ___ ]?<br />

what <strong>the</strong>-teacher persuaded OM who that-Yosi read<br />

‘What did <strong>the</strong> teacher persuade whom that Yosi read?’<br />

Selected references: Beck, S. 2006. Intervention effects follow from focus <strong>in</strong>terpretation. NALS � Cable,<br />

S. 2010. The grammar of Q: Q-particles, wh-movement and pied-pip<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford Uni. Press. � Dayal, V. 2002.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gle-pair vs. multiple-pair answers: Wh <strong>in</strong>-situ and scope. LI � Fox, D. 2000. Economy and semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. MIT Press. � Pesetsky, D. 2000. Phrasal movement and its k<strong>in</strong>. MIT Press.


Ivona Kučerová (McMaster)<br />

Case Independence and Split Ergativity: Toward a Unified Theory of Case Assignment<br />

Two recent proposals, Coon and Prem<strong>in</strong>ger 2011 (henceforth, C&P) and Kučerová 2011 (henceforth, K),<br />

argued that case assignment is sensitive to <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure. While C&P, follow<strong>in</strong>g Coon<br />

2010, concentrated on <strong>the</strong> Ergative/Absolutive (E/A) case syste<strong>ms</strong>, more precisely, on <strong>the</strong> syntactic source<br />

of split ergativity, K <strong>in</strong>vestigated emergence of Accusative(Acc)assignment<strong>in</strong>syntacticenvironmentslack<strong>in</strong>g<br />

an external argument and Nom<strong>in</strong>ative (Nom) case. The goal of this paper is to unify <strong>the</strong> two proposals<br />

and argue that cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically case assignment is sensitive to <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure. More<br />

precisely, <strong>the</strong> actual case assignment reflects which heads are strong phase heads and as such constitute<br />

Spell-out doma<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> given syntactic structure (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2001,Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky2005,Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky2008).Consequently,<br />

case assignment splits are predicted not to be restricted to E/A syste<strong>ms</strong> but should be <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

available <strong>in</strong> N/A syste<strong>ms</strong> as well. Data from Arabic copular clauses confirm this prediction.<br />

C&P: C&P observed that tense and person related <strong>in</strong>stances of split ergativityhavetwoproperties<strong>in</strong>common:<br />

(i) Structures that exhibit <strong>the</strong> split case system are syntactically larger than <strong>the</strong> structures that exhibit<br />

<strong>the</strong> regular E/A pattern. (ii) The split pattern is best characterized as a lack of morphological mark<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong>re are no dist<strong>in</strong>ct morphological case end<strong>in</strong>gs. Instead, <strong>the</strong> split pattern exhibits a lack of overt<br />

case end<strong>in</strong>gs. Based on <strong>the</strong>se two empirical generalizations, <strong>the</strong>yproposedthatsplitergativityisalackof<br />

case assignment due to a non-local configuration, i.e., <strong>the</strong> two relevant DPs end up be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> two separate<br />

case doma<strong>in</strong>s, one of which is not local with respect to <strong>the</strong> Erg case assigner. The emerg<strong>in</strong>g morphological<br />

pattern is best characterized as default case result<strong>in</strong>g from lackoffeaturecheck<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

K: Karguedthatview<strong>in</strong>gAccasacasedependentonNomoron<strong>the</strong>presence of an external argument is<br />

empirically <strong>in</strong>adequate s<strong>in</strong>ce we can f<strong>in</strong>d Acc <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of an external argument or an argument receiv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Nom. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to her, Acc is assigned only if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is spelled-out with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP<br />

phase. If v does not trigger Spell-out, Acc is not available. KadoptsRichard’sDist<strong>in</strong>ctnessConditionon<br />

L<strong>in</strong>earization (Richards 2003, 2006) accord<strong>in</strong>g to which vP can be spelled out only if it can be l<strong>in</strong>earized.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> condition to be satisfied <strong>the</strong> merge of v and its complement cannot be <strong>the</strong> maximal projection of v<br />

but <strong>the</strong> vP must be fur<strong>the</strong>r extended. The required extension is usuallyachievedbymergeofanexternal<br />

argument but <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is <strong>in</strong>dependent of it. K discuses data from Polish, Ukra<strong>in</strong>ian, and North Russian<br />

<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> required extension is achieved <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stances of have-Perfect. Even though <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

external argument, <strong>the</strong> ‘transitivity’-like extension is achieved by add<strong>in</strong>g a structure semantically associated<br />

with sub<strong>in</strong>terval properties and <strong>in</strong> some languages morphologically realized as have. Ascanbeseen<strong>in</strong>(1)<br />

from North Russian dialects, an <strong>in</strong>ternal argument can get ei<strong>the</strong>r Nom or Acc; crucially, <strong>the</strong> case assignment<br />

is <strong>in</strong>dependent of agreement: <strong>in</strong> both cases, <strong>the</strong> verbal agreement shows morphological default. However,<br />

once <strong>the</strong> have-Perfect <strong>in</strong>terpretation is enforced, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument must be realized as Acc, (2).<br />

(1) North Russian (Danylenko, 2006, p. 255–256, (18), orig<strong>in</strong>ally from Kuz’m<strong>in</strong>a 1993, 135–137):<br />

a. (u njego) syn<br />

(bylo)<br />

otpravleno<br />

at him son.NOM.SG.M. be.N.SG.AUX.PRET. send-away.N.SG.PPP<br />

‘His son has been sent away (by him).’<br />

b. (u njego) parnja<br />

(bylo)<br />

uvedeno<br />

at him fellow.ACC.SG.M. be.N.SG.AUX.PRET. take-away.N.SG.PPP<br />

(2)<br />

‘The guy has been taken away (by him).’<br />

North Russian (Kucerova 2011)<br />

a. *Vot uˇze tre goda kak u nego syn v amerku uvezeno.<br />

here already three years how by him son.NOM to America taken away<br />

b. Vot uˇze tre goda kak u nego syna v amerku uvezeno.<br />

here already three years how by him son.ACC=GEN to america taken away<br />

‘It has been three years s<strong>in</strong>ce his son has been taken away to America.’<br />

1


Proposal: What <strong>the</strong>se two proposals have <strong>in</strong> common is <strong>the</strong> observation that creat<strong>in</strong>g a locality boundary<br />

changes <strong>the</strong> case assignment properties. In <strong>the</strong> N/A system creat<strong>in</strong>g a locality boundary yields emergence of<br />

aspecialmorphologicalmark<strong>in</strong>g(Acc<strong>in</strong>steadof<strong>the</strong>expectedNom).In<strong>the</strong>E/Asystem,creat<strong>in</strong>galocality<br />

boundary yields loss of a special morphological mark<strong>in</strong>g (default or Abs <strong>in</strong>stead of <strong>the</strong>expectedErg).The<br />

question is whe<strong>the</strong>r we can unify <strong>the</strong>se two observations. Crucially, it has been argued that E/A and N/A<br />

languages are not syntactically identical. In particular, <strong>the</strong> v <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> E/A pattern is ei<strong>the</strong>r defective or entirely<br />

miss<strong>in</strong>g (e.g., Marantz 1984, Nash 1995, 1995, Alexiadou 2001). We argue that consequently, vP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

regular E/A pattern is not a spell-out doma<strong>in</strong>. If we assume, follow<strong>in</strong>g most of <strong>the</strong> current literature that Erg<br />

is assigned by a T head (Infl) while Acc is assigned by v <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g empirical generalization emerges:<br />

(3) A special morphological mark<strong>in</strong>g (Erg, Acc) arises only if <strong>the</strong>m<strong>in</strong>imalspell-outdoma<strong>in</strong>thatconta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

an <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is <strong>the</strong> spell-out doma<strong>in</strong> that conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> head responsible for <strong>the</strong> special<br />

morphological mark<strong>in</strong>g (T for Erg and v for Acc).<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, Acc is possible only if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is spelled-out with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP spell-out doma<strong>in</strong><br />

and Erg is possible only if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal argument is not spelled out with<strong>in</strong> vP but <strong>in</strong>stead it is spelled-out <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> next phase. Crucially, we have to ensure that Erg would be assign only if <strong>the</strong>re is more than one DP<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g spelled out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same doma<strong>in</strong>. Let’s assume that someth<strong>in</strong>g like (4) holds. (A parallel condition<br />

might be needed for enforc<strong>in</strong>g Acc/Dat dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> double-object constructions but we leave <strong>the</strong> issue of<br />

Dat aside for now.)<br />

(4) Case Dist<strong>in</strong>ctness Condition: Erg is assigned only if <strong>the</strong>re is more than one DP spelled-out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

same Spell-out doma<strong>in</strong> as <strong>the</strong> head assign<strong>in</strong>g Erg.<br />

Predictions: Under <strong>the</strong> current proposal, splits <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of loos<strong>in</strong>g a special mark<strong>in</strong>g depend on <strong>the</strong> size<br />

of <strong>the</strong> syntactic doma<strong>in</strong> (as <strong>in</strong> C&P and K). In contrast to C&P, wepredictthatthistypeofcasesplitshould<br />

not be restricted to E/A but should be equally possible <strong>in</strong> N/A syste<strong>ms</strong>. In particular, we predict that if <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is only one DP <strong>in</strong> a clause, this DP will be assigned Nom if vP is a weak phase (or not a phase at all) or it is<br />

go<strong>in</strong>g to be assigned Acc if it is spelled out with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP phase. This prediction see<strong>ms</strong> to be borne out, for<br />

example, <strong>in</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Russian dialects, as we saw <strong>in</strong> (2).<br />

If <strong>the</strong>re is more than one DP <strong>in</strong> a clause, <strong>the</strong> prediction is that none of <strong>the</strong> DPs will get Acc if both DPs will<br />

be spelled out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same phase, more precisely with<strong>in</strong> CP phase. If such a structure gets <strong>in</strong>dependently<br />

extended and <strong>the</strong> two DPs get spelled out <strong>in</strong> two separate phases, <strong>the</strong> prediction is that <strong>the</strong> higher one should<br />

be assigned Nom, while <strong>the</strong> lower one should be assigned Acc. Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, this prediction is borne out <strong>in</strong><br />

Arabic nom<strong>in</strong>al copular clauses. In particular, nom<strong>in</strong>al copular clauses <strong>in</strong> Arabic show dist<strong>in</strong>ct case pattern<br />

depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> tense of <strong>the</strong> copular clause. As can be seen <strong>in</strong> (5-a), copula-less small clauses show no Acc<br />

assignment. Crucially, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ergative split pattern what weseehereisnotaspecialmark<strong>in</strong>gbutalackof<br />

mark<strong>in</strong>g. If <strong>the</strong> structure gets extended, which is presumably <strong>the</strong>caseofPastandFuture<strong>in</strong>(5-b)–(5-c),<strong>the</strong><br />

lower DP gets spelled out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP phase, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ct case assignment of <strong>the</strong> two DPs.<br />

(5) a. Hassan Tabiib<br />

Hassan.NOM doctor.NOM<br />

‘Hassan is a doctor.’<br />

b. kaan Hassan Tabiib-an<br />

was Hassan.NOM doctor.ACC.INDEF<br />

‘Hassan was a doctor.’<br />

c. Sayakuunu Hassan<br />

be.FUT Hassan.NOM<br />

Tabiib-an<br />

doctor.ACC.INDEF<br />

‘Hassan will be a doctor.’<br />

Conclusion: Case assignment reflects Spell-out properties of a given syntactic structure. Crucially, creat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

aphaseboundaryalternatescasepatternsnotonly<strong>in</strong>E/Alanguages but <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> N/A pattern as well.<br />

2


Dave Kush (Maryland)<br />

On-l<strong>in</strong>e use of relational structural <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g anaphora: evidence from English<br />

and H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

We present results from three experiments that show <strong>the</strong> parser makes rapid use of relational structural<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> memory retrieval.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> on-l<strong>in</strong>e implementation of grammatical constra<strong>in</strong>ts are an important tool for<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g how speakers encode and navigate hierarchical syntactic representations <strong>in</strong> memory.<br />

On-l<strong>in</strong>e sensitivity to a structural relation implies that this relation is mentally encoded, and that it is<br />

employed by <strong>the</strong> parser’s dependency-build<strong>in</strong>g mechanis<strong>ms</strong>. Here we <strong>in</strong>vestigate an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g tension<br />

that arises when compar<strong>in</strong>g different recent f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> psychol<strong>in</strong>guistics. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, a grow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

body of evidence motivates a parser that relies on parallel access mechanis<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> content addressable<br />

memory [1]. Evidence comes from effects of <strong>in</strong>terference from grammatically illicit licensers [2,3],<br />

and from non-effects of syntactic dependency length [4,5]. Importantly, relational notions such as ccommand<br />

are difficult to exploit <strong>in</strong> such memory architectures, as <strong>the</strong>y are properties of configurations<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong>herent properties of <strong>in</strong>dividual nodes (‘content’). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong><br />

apparent immunity-to-<strong>in</strong>terference of local anaphoric b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g suggest that dependencies that obey ccommand<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts can be accurately implemented on-l<strong>in</strong>e [6,7,8,9,10]. However, f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs on English<br />

local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g may be mislead<strong>in</strong>g. English reflexive anaphors require a clause-mate antecedent, and <strong>the</strong>y<br />

follow <strong>the</strong> verb, and so grammatically accurate retrieval might be achieved simply by retriev<strong>in</strong>g a coargument<br />

of <strong>the</strong> immediately preced<strong>in</strong>g verb. Here we present results from three experiments <strong>in</strong> English<br />

and H<strong>in</strong>di that avoid this confound by test<strong>in</strong>g (i) non-local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g relations that unambiguously <strong>in</strong>volve<br />

c-command constra<strong>in</strong>ts, and (ii) local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g relations <strong>in</strong> a verb-f<strong>in</strong>al language that must be established<br />

before verb <strong>in</strong>formation is encountered.<br />

Experiments 1 & 2 <strong>in</strong>vestigated <strong>the</strong> parser’s sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> c-command constra<strong>in</strong>t on boundvariable<br />

pronouns. Unlike local reflexive licens<strong>in</strong>g, this constra<strong>in</strong>t on bound-variable pronouns<br />

applies across an unbounded distance, and hence provides a strong test of <strong>the</strong> parser’s use of relational<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> retrieval. We focused on <strong>the</strong> contrast<strong>in</strong>g ability of clauses headed by but and when to host<br />

bound variable pronouns <strong>in</strong> (1-2). The contrast reflects <strong>the</strong> lower attachment site of when-clauses, which<br />

allows any janitor to c-command <strong>the</strong> underl<strong>in</strong>ed pronoun. Importantly, coreference does not require ccommand,<br />

so replac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantified NP with a referential NP (<strong>the</strong> janitor) elim<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong> contrast.<br />

(1) Kathy didn’t th<strong>in</strong>k that any janitor liked his job, when he had to clean up after <strong>the</strong> prom.<br />

(2) *Kathy didn’t th<strong>in</strong>k that any janitor liked his job, but he had to clean up after <strong>the</strong> prom.<br />

The experiments manipulated <strong>the</strong> type of antecedent (quantificational vs. referential) and <strong>the</strong> structural<br />

relation between <strong>the</strong> antecedent and <strong>the</strong> critical pronoun (WHEN/b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g vs. BUT/no-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g). 24<br />

sets of ite<strong>ms</strong> were distributed across 4 lists <strong>in</strong> a Lat<strong>in</strong> Square design and comb<strong>in</strong>ed with 64 fillers.<br />

In Experiment 1 (self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g, n=24) immediate sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> c-command constra<strong>in</strong>t was<br />

demonstrated <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>teraction of antecedent-type and structural relation at <strong>the</strong> pronoun (p < .05) 1 , due<br />

to slower read<strong>in</strong>g times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantifier/no-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g condition. In Experiment 2 (eye-track<strong>in</strong>g, n = 24)<br />

<strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>teraction was found at <strong>the</strong> post-pronoun region (p < .05) <strong>in</strong> re-read, second-pass and total<br />

time measures. This shows that <strong>the</strong> parser is able to rapidly exploit c-command <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> on-l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

dependency formation.<br />

Experiment 3 turned to H<strong>in</strong>di for an additional test of whe<strong>the</strong>r structure-sensitive anaphor<br />

1 All data were fit to a l<strong>in</strong>ear mixed-effects model with subject and item as random effects. P-values were<br />

estimated us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pvals.fnc() function <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> LanguageR library [11].


process<strong>in</strong>g is cont<strong>in</strong>gent on a verb-based retrieval heuristic, or whe<strong>the</strong>r it is <strong>the</strong> product of general<br />

availability of relational <strong>in</strong>formation. H<strong>in</strong>di reciprocals must be locally licensed [12], like <strong>the</strong>ir English<br />

counterparts, but s<strong>in</strong>ce H<strong>in</strong>di is an SOV language <strong>the</strong>y appear pre-verbally, thus mak<strong>in</strong>g antecedentretrieval<br />

through mediation by <strong>the</strong> verb’s argument structure impossible.<br />

The design of <strong>the</strong> experiment used <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terference logic of previous reflexive studies.<br />

Reciprocals must be bound by a plural-marked, c-command<strong>in</strong>g NP, thus <strong>the</strong> relevant cue for retrieval<br />

is [+plural]. The experiment manipulated plural-mark<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> matrix subject and on a potential<br />

<strong>in</strong>terfer<strong>in</strong>g NP <strong>in</strong> a pre-nom<strong>in</strong>al relative clause that l<strong>in</strong>early preceded <strong>the</strong> reciprocal. The structure of a<br />

test-sentence is given <strong>in</strong> (3) below. When NP1 (<strong>the</strong> matrix subject) is plural it can b<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> reciprocal.<br />

NP2, embedded <strong>in</strong>side an RC (boundaries marked with brackets), cannot grammatically b<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong><br />

reciprocal, regardless of its number.If relational <strong>in</strong>formation is used <strong>in</strong> local licens<strong>in</strong>g, we predict no<br />

effect of plural-mark<strong>in</strong>g on NP2. If verb-mediated retrieval is required to block <strong>in</strong>terference, we expect<br />

<strong>in</strong>terference <strong>in</strong> conditions <strong>in</strong> which NP2 is plural.<br />

(3) NP1{sg/pl} [ ... NP2{sg/pl} ...] ... Reciprocal... {AdvP} V.<br />

An example sentence is given <strong>in</strong> (4). The matrix subject doctor(s) (underl<strong>in</strong>ed below) can b<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong><br />

reciprocal ek-dusre when plural. The potential <strong>in</strong>terferer NP patient(s) (italicized) is embedded <strong>in</strong>side<br />

a pre-verbal RC <strong>the</strong> nurse who took care of <strong>the</strong> patients, thus remov<strong>in</strong>g its ability to c-command (and<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore b<strong>in</strong>d) <strong>the</strong> reciprocal.<br />

(4) Us/un doctor(on)-ne [us/un mariz(on)-ko dekhbal karne wali nurse] ke station me<br />

That/those doctor(s)-ERG that/those patients(s)-ACC care do<strong>in</strong>g RP nurse GEN station <strong>in</strong><br />

ek-dusre ke-saath gupt-ruup-se bat kii.<br />

one-ano<strong>the</strong>r with secretly chat did.<br />

`That/those doctor(s) talked secretly with one ano<strong>the</strong>r at <strong>the</strong> station of <strong>the</strong> nurse who was look<strong>in</strong>g after<br />

<strong>the</strong> patient(s).'<br />

24 sets of ite<strong>ms</strong> were distributed across 4 lists <strong>in</strong> a Lat<strong>in</strong> Square design and comb<strong>in</strong>ed with 50 filler<br />

ite<strong>ms</strong>. The experiment (n=30, native-speakers of H<strong>in</strong>di from Northwestern India, ages 18-26) revealed<br />

immediate sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>t on reciprocal licens<strong>in</strong>g. A ma<strong>in</strong> effect of Subject-Number was<br />

observed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> region immediately follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> reciprocal phrase (p


Locality <strong>in</strong> Agreement: A New Approach<br />

Aim. The goal of this talk is to propose a new approach to syntactic structure-build<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that is based upon <strong>the</strong> idea that syntactic derivations are driven by a specificity pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

on merge and agreement. The approach has <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g property that it correctly<br />

derives relative locality effects (i.e., locality effects <strong>in</strong> Merge and Agree that are due to<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervention) without actually <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g closeness-based pr<strong>in</strong>ciples such as <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imal<br />

L<strong>in</strong>k Condition. This talk first presents <strong>the</strong> new <strong>the</strong>ory and some of its assets and applications,<br />

but<strong>the</strong>n focusesonaparticular empirical doma<strong>in</strong>: <strong>in</strong>tervention-driven agreement<br />

alternations such as complementarity effects (e.g. complementarity <strong>in</strong> Breton agreement)<br />

and cases of (seem<strong>in</strong>g) optional alternation (e.g. defective <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> Icelandic).<br />

Theoretical Background. Specificity is arguably one of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> basic concepts of<br />

morphological <strong>the</strong>ory, where is used to resolve competitions between <strong>the</strong> markers of a<br />

language which arise due to underspecification of <strong>in</strong>flectional markers (Subset Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple).<br />

I would like to propose that structure build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> syntactic derivations, too, is driven by<br />

specificity. The syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>t relevant to <strong>the</strong> local decisions made is <strong>the</strong> General<br />

Specificity Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, an extension of Maximize Match<strong>in</strong>g Effects (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2001:15):<br />

(1) General Specificity Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple: A Probe undergoes a syntactic operation with <strong>the</strong><br />

most specific match<strong>in</strong>g goal. Specificity is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by card<strong>in</strong>ality of morphosyntactic<br />

features: a set Q is more specific than a set H iff |Q| > |H|.<br />

The GSP has <strong>the</strong> effect that with more than one potential Goal be<strong>in</strong>g available <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

search space of a Probe, <strong>the</strong> Probe always agrees first with <strong>the</strong> Goal with which it can<br />

satisfy <strong>the</strong> highest number of features, even if it is not <strong>the</strong> closest available goal.<br />

Analysis. Let me briefly sketch a specificity-driven derivation for two different Agreement<br />

phenomena: complementarity <strong>in</strong> Breton agreement, and defective <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong><br />

Icelandic. Breton shows a complementarity effect <strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong> φ-features of a phonologically<br />

null NP are coded by φ-agreement morphology on <strong>the</strong> verb (=‘rich agreement’),<br />

whereas <strong>the</strong> φ-features of a phonologically overt NP are not coded by φ-agreement morphology<br />

on <strong>the</strong> target (‘<strong>in</strong>variant agreement’ [=frozen 3sg agreement or bare stem]):<br />

(2) a. Gant<br />

with<br />

o mamm e karf-ent /*karf-e pro bez-añ<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r r would.love-3pl /*would.love-3sg 3pl be-<strong>in</strong>f<br />

‘They would like to be with <strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r’<br />

b. Gant<br />

with<br />

Antje Lahne (Konstanz)<br />

o mamm e *karf-ent /karf-e Azenor ha Iona bez-añ<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r r *would.love-3pl /would.love-3sg Azenor and Iona be-<strong>in</strong>f<br />

‘Azenor and Iona would like to be with <strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r’<br />

Jouitteau & Rezac (2006) analyse <strong>the</strong> complementarity as a locality effect. The start<strong>in</strong>g<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>the</strong> analysis is <strong>the</strong> observation that v <strong>in</strong> Breton has nom<strong>in</strong>al properties. It is thus<br />

assumed to bear <strong>in</strong>terpretable 3sg φ-features. Consequently, when I probes for φ-features<br />

<strong>in</strong> its search space, <strong>the</strong>n v <strong>in</strong>tervenes between I and <strong>the</strong> external argument, which is conta<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vP. I must <strong>the</strong>refore value its unvalued features with φ-features of v, which<br />

results <strong>in</strong> 3sg (‘frozen’) agreement on I. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong> external argument<br />

is an affixal pro, <strong>the</strong>n it <strong>in</strong>corporates <strong>in</strong>to T and thus contributes its φ-features to <strong>the</strong><br />

feature set of T (i.e., it becomes a bound pronoun), which surfaces as rich agreement.<br />

While fully agree<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>corporation analysis, I argue that <strong>the</strong> alleged A-over-A<br />

effect is actually a Specificity effect: The GSP has <strong>the</strong> effect that <strong>the</strong> current probe I has<br />

to handle its selectional feature [•cat:v•] by merg<strong>in</strong>g with a v-type element; due to <strong>the</strong><br />

1


GSP, Agree between I and v must <strong>in</strong>volve handl<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> maximal number of match<strong>in</strong>g<br />

features. Thus, if I has more features (φ-features: [*pers*], [*num*]) that it can value<br />

with a feature of v, <strong>the</strong>n it must value it with v. This is illustrated <strong>in</strong> (3).<br />

(3) a. b.<br />

I ′<br />

I o<br />

[•v•, *φ*]<br />

x<br />

vP<br />

DP v ′<br />

v o ...<br />

I o<br />

[•v•, *φ*]<br />

I ′<br />

vP<br />

DP v ′<br />

v o ...<br />

A second type of data that can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by means of specificity are cases of apparant<br />

<strong>in</strong>decisiveness, namely when <strong>the</strong>re aretwo goalsthat <strong>the</strong>probecanagreewith <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>same<br />

number of features. I argue that this constellation leads to alternation. One example is<br />

defective <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> Icelandic (Holmberg & Hróarsdóttir 2004):<br />

(4) Mér f<strong>in</strong>nst/f<strong>in</strong>nast tölvurnar ljótar<br />

me.dat f<strong>in</strong>d.sg/f<strong>in</strong>d.pl computers:def.nom.pl ugly<br />

‘I consider <strong>the</strong> computers ugly’<br />

In brief, <strong>the</strong> approach to <strong>the</strong>se data is that I o has three k<strong>in</strong>ds of prob<strong>in</strong>g features: <strong>the</strong><br />

EPP feature, <strong>the</strong> set of phi-features, and <strong>the</strong> case feature [∗nom∗]. However, <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

constituent that I o can handle all three features with – it cannot use <strong>the</strong> EPP feature on<br />

<strong>the</strong> lower DP tölvurnar (as it is an argument of <strong>the</strong> embedded predicate), and nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

can it assign nom<strong>in</strong>ative case to <strong>the</strong> dative subject mér – but it is possible to use two<br />

of <strong>the</strong> three features on one goal, and <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g feature on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r goal. There<br />

are two possible orders <strong>in</strong> which this can be done. I would like to propose that <strong>the</strong><br />

order of operations is optional, and that both orders are attested: one order leads to <strong>the</strong><br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement option, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r leads to plural agreement. The features [•D•] and<br />

[*nom*] cannot be handled toge<strong>the</strong>r, as <strong>the</strong> EPP feature cannot be used on <strong>the</strong> lower<br />

DP. This leaves two possible feature comb<strong>in</strong>ations: One possibility is to handle two of <strong>the</strong><br />

three features, [•D•] and [n:�], with <strong>the</strong> dative argument, and subsequently us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g feature [*case:nom*] on <strong>the</strong> lower DP. As a result, I shows s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement.<br />

The second possibility is to use [*case:nom*] and [n:�] on <strong>the</strong> lower DP, and <strong>the</strong>n handle<br />

[•D•] with <strong>the</strong> quirky subject. The verb consequently shows plural agreement.<br />

Consequences. The new approach yields new <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gs of locality <strong>in</strong><br />

Agreement: Agreement alternations arise due to extremely local decisions about feature<br />

handl<strong>in</strong>g made dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> derivation; <strong>the</strong>se decisions are driven by <strong>the</strong> need of probes to<br />

match with a goal as fully as possible, disregard<strong>in</strong>g structural distances. Optionalities<br />

arise when this need can be resolved <strong>in</strong> more than one way. L<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>sight to <strong>the</strong><br />

f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs presented at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> talk, I would like to go one step fur<strong>the</strong>r and<br />

propose that Specificity, not Closeness, is <strong>the</strong> core pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that drives derivations and<br />

yields relative locality <strong>in</strong> Merge and Agree.<br />

References. Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, Noam (2001): Derivation by Phase. In: M. Kenstowicz, ed.,<br />

Ken Hale: A Life <strong>in</strong> Language. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., pp. 1-52. Holmberg,<br />

Anders & Thorbjörg Hróarsdóttir (2004): Agreement and movement <strong>in</strong> Icelandic rais<strong>in</strong>g<br />

constructions, L<strong>in</strong>gua 114(5), 651-673. Jouitteau, Mélanie & Milan Rezac (2006): Deriv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> Complementarity Effect: Relativized M<strong>in</strong>imality <strong>in</strong> Breton Agreement, L<strong>in</strong>gua<br />

116(11), 1915-1945.<br />

2


Mohamed Lahrouchi (CNRS/Paris 8)<br />

Phasal Spellout and <strong>the</strong> glide – high vowel alternation <strong>in</strong> Berber<br />

Berber languages present a wealth of <strong>in</strong>tricate phonological alternations <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

glides and high vowels, some of which still resist standard phonological analyses. These<br />

alternations shed light on <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>ter-modular communication, which many current<br />

<strong>in</strong>terface <strong>the</strong>ories address.<br />

Glides typically appear <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate vic<strong>in</strong>ity of a vowel, <strong>in</strong> complementary<br />

distribution with <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g high vowels. Based on this k<strong>in</strong>d of observations, standard<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories analyse glides and high vowels as phonetic reflexes of <strong>the</strong> same underly<strong>in</strong>g segments.<br />

The examples <strong>in</strong> (1) illustrate <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>in</strong> Tashlhiyt Berber:<br />

(1)<br />

gru ‘pick up’ agraw ‘assembly’<br />

bri ‘crush, pound’ abraj ‘crushed seeds’<br />

The problem arises with <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g dative for<strong>ms</strong> grujas ‘pick to him’ and brijas<br />

‘crush seeds to him’. Followed by a vowel-<strong>in</strong>itial morpheme –as, U and I should normally<br />

surface as glides, lead<strong>in</strong>g to *grwas and *brjas. Faced with similar for<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> Tamazight Berber<br />

Guerssel (1986: 3) posits “a phonemic dist<strong>in</strong>ction between glides and high vowels”.<br />

The key to understand<strong>in</strong>g this paradox lies, we argue, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> morpho-syntactic<br />

structure of dative formations. In l<strong>in</strong>e with recent works at <strong>the</strong> syntax – phonology <strong>in</strong>terface<br />

(Marv<strong>in</strong> 2002, Marantz 2007, Pigott and Newell 2006, Samuels 2010), we argue that <strong>the</strong><br />

behaviour of I and U <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> for<strong>ms</strong> just discussed is <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> application of spell-out<br />

and phase impenetrability condition (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2001) at different levels <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

structure. In particular, we show that vP corresponds to a phase where U and I are spelled-out<br />

as high vowels before <strong>the</strong> enclitic –as is added. The result<strong>in</strong>g hiatus is <strong>the</strong>n resolved by means<br />

of j epen<strong>the</strong>sis, lead<strong>in</strong>g to grujas and brijas. In agraw and abraj, U and I surface as glides s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

<strong>the</strong>y belong to <strong>the</strong> same phase (nP) as <strong>the</strong> neighbour<strong>in</strong>g a. The for<strong>ms</strong> represented <strong>in</strong> (2)<br />

illustrate <strong>the</strong> proposal:<br />

(2) a. grujas "pick to him" b. agraw ‘assembly’<br />

Spell-out-as-you-merge and Phase Impenetrability thus allow expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

paradoxical behaviour of I and U <strong>in</strong> Tashlhiyt Berber (see also Pigott and Newell 2006 about<br />

Ojibwa). The question that arises <strong>the</strong>n is <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g: under <strong>the</strong> assumption that phonology<br />

is sensitive to external morph-syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation, what k<strong>in</strong>d of devices allows direct <strong>in</strong>termodular<br />

communication? Do morpho-syntactic phases leave any phonological traces?<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Scheer (2011), we will assume that empty CV units, purely phonological objects


(Lowenstamm 1996, 1999), carry morpho-syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>to phonology. They mark<br />

phase boundaries. How does phonology use <strong>the</strong>se empty CVs is an issue we will discuss.<br />

References<br />

Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A Life <strong>in</strong> Language, edited by<br />

Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.<br />

Dell, François & Mohamed Elmedlaoui. 2002. Syllables <strong>in</strong> Tashlhiyt Berber and <strong>in</strong> Moroccan<br />

Arabic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.<br />

Guerssel, Mohand. 1986. Glides <strong>in</strong> Berber and Syllabicity. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 17-1: 1-12.<br />

Lowenstamm, Jean. 1996. CV as <strong>the</strong> only syllable type. In Current trends <strong>in</strong> Phonology.<br />

Models and Methods, edited by Jacques Durand & Bernard Laks, 419-441.<br />

Salford, Manchester: ESRI.<br />

Lowenstamm, Jean. 1999. The beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> word. In Phonologica 1996, edited by John<br />

Rennison & Klaus Kühnhammer, 153-166. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics.<br />

Marantz, Alec. 2007. Phases and Words. In Phases <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Theory of Gramma, edited by Sook-<br />

Hee Choe, 191-222. Seoul: Dong In.<br />

Marv<strong>in</strong>, Tatjana. 2002. Topics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Stress and Syntax of Words. Ph.D dissertation, MIT.<br />

Piggott, Glyne & Hea<strong>the</strong>r Newell. 2006. Syllabification and <strong>the</strong> Spell-Out of Phases <strong>in</strong><br />

Ojibwa Words. McGill Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 20.2: 39-64.<br />

Samuels, Bridget. 2010. Phonological Derivation by Phase: Evidence from Basque.<br />

University of Pennsylvania Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 16: 166-175.<br />

Scheer, Tobias. 2011. A Guide to Morphosyntax – Phonology Interface Theories. Berl<strong>in</strong>:<br />

Mouton de Gruyter.<br />

Uriagereka, Juan 1999. Multiple spell-out. In Work<strong>in</strong>g M<strong>in</strong>imalism, edited by Samuel Epste<strong>in</strong><br />

& Norbert Hornste<strong>in</strong>, 251-282. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.


Chris Laterza (Maryland)<br />

Gaps with<strong>in</strong> Silence<br />

This talk provides a novel account of <strong>the</strong> role of traces <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g conditions for VP ellipsis<br />

(VPE). As I will show, this approach unifies <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g conditions for canonical VPE with<br />

related phenomena such as pseudogapp<strong>in</strong>g and ACD, a task that has been attempted <strong>in</strong> several<br />

different ways s<strong>in</strong>ce at least as early as Lapp<strong>in</strong> (1992). Assum<strong>in</strong>g that VPE is PF deletion<br />

licensed by LF identity (an approach pursued, for example, by Sag (1976) and Kennedy (2003)),<br />

my ma<strong>in</strong> claim (<strong>in</strong>formally put) is that traces <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ellipsis clause (EC) act as “wildcard” element<br />

for <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ation of identity; just so long as <strong>the</strong>re is a DP/PP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent clause (AC)<br />

VP occupy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same type of argument/adjunct position as <strong>the</strong> trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC VP, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> that<br />

AC DP/PP and <strong>the</strong> EC trace count as identical for <strong>the</strong> purposes of licens<strong>in</strong>g VPE, even if <strong>the</strong> LF<br />

content of <strong>the</strong> AC DP/PP is not identical to that of <strong>the</strong> DP/PP which moved from <strong>the</strong> position of<br />

<strong>the</strong> trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC. To illustrate, take <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stance of VPE:<br />

(1) John [VP met Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky at WCCFL]. Guess who1 Bill did [VP meet t1 at WCCFL].<br />

A more str<strong>in</strong>gent approach to ellipsis licens<strong>in</strong>g would have a hard time expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g (without ad<br />

hoc str<strong>in</strong>g vacuous movement) how VPE is licensed <strong>in</strong> (1), s<strong>in</strong>ce [Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky] is not identical to<br />

[t1] nor [who1] <strong>in</strong> any approach to VPE (previous versions of PF deletion, LF copy<strong>in</strong>g, pro-form<br />

VPs, etc.). However, <strong>the</strong> relaxed approach to identity offered here treats (1) as a licit case of<br />

VPE: almost everyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> AC and EC VPs are LF-identical, <strong>the</strong> sole exception be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

direct objects, and s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> object <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC is a trace, it counts as identical with [Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky] <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> AC under this approach and thus ellipsis is licensed. The rema<strong>in</strong>der of <strong>the</strong> abstract provides<br />

some o<strong>the</strong>r examples of this approach at work.<br />

PSEUDOGAPPING: The present approach fits well with a popular treatment of pseudogapp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(as argued for by Jayaseelan (1990) and Lasnik (1999)) which states that pseudogapp<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

extraction of <strong>the</strong> "survivor" from <strong>the</strong> VP followed by VPE, as shown <strong>in</strong> (2). This creates a<br />

configuration that is short of full LF-identity between <strong>the</strong> AC and EC VPs, though it is one that<br />

falls with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> purview of <strong>the</strong> current approach and counts as a licit case of VPE, s<strong>in</strong>ce t1 will<br />

match [on <strong>the</strong> porch] under <strong>the</strong> current approach, even though t1 is a trace of [<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gazebo].<br />

(2) John [VP read a book on <strong>the</strong> porch this morn<strong>in</strong>g], while Bill did (so) [VP read a<br />

book t1 this morn<strong>in</strong>g] [PP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gazebo]1<br />

ACD: Virtually all analyses of relative clause formation <strong>in</strong>volve some sort of movement from<br />

<strong>the</strong> relativization site to some A'-position. Therefore, it is typical to treat cases of ACD as<br />

<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC VP (whenever <strong>the</strong> relativization site is with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> VP). Under <strong>the</strong><br />

present approach, (3) is licensed s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> AC VP = [read [DP few books that Bill did]] and <strong>the</strong><br />

EC VP = [read t1], and t1 will match any direct object DP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> AC clause, even if it is complex<br />

and conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> trace itself.<br />

(3) John [VP read few (of <strong>the</strong>) books Op1 that Bill did [VP read t1 ] ]<br />

While some argue that <strong>the</strong>re is QR <strong>in</strong> (3), <strong>the</strong>reby mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> current approach unnecessary for<br />

cases of ACD, <strong>the</strong>re are some cases where <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>er matters for VPE<br />

licens<strong>in</strong>g, and thus it must somehow be represented with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> VP. We can see this <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> non-<br />

ACD (4), as <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> EC is clearly that Bill read few books.<br />

(4) John read few (of <strong>the</strong>) books, and Bill did [VP read few (of <strong>the</strong>) books] too<br />

If QR is present <strong>in</strong> (4), leav<strong>in</strong>g a trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> VP that is devoid of any content (an assumption<br />

made by May (1985) for QR to deal with <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite regress), <strong>the</strong>n it is surpris<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong><br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er’s mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> aspect of “fewness”, is relevant for VPE. (3) differs from (4) <strong>in</strong> that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no DP movement out of <strong>the</strong> VP <strong>in</strong> (4), for if <strong>the</strong>re were, we are left without an<br />

explanation for why <strong>the</strong> DP’s mean<strong>in</strong>g is recovered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC VP <strong>in</strong> (4). Thus, (4) has stricter


identity conditions than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of (3) which <strong>in</strong>volves a trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> relativization site, which<br />

lightens <strong>the</strong> identity conditions under <strong>the</strong> present approach; i.e., <strong>the</strong> semantic content of <strong>the</strong> direct<br />

object’s determ<strong>in</strong>er matters for VPE licens<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (4) but not <strong>in</strong> (3). From what I can tell, <strong>the</strong><br />

observation of <strong>the</strong> asymmetry above between (3) and (4) (whe<strong>the</strong>r or not determ<strong>in</strong>er mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

matter for VPE) brought about by non-universal determ<strong>in</strong>ers is novel, and is expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong><br />

present account of traces <strong>in</strong> VPE identity conditions. It is also noteworthy that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite regress<br />

problem is no problem at all for <strong>the</strong> current approach, s<strong>in</strong>ce VPE licens<strong>in</strong>g does not require <strong>the</strong><br />

content of <strong>the</strong> AC direct object <strong>in</strong> (3) to be represented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> trace <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r support for <strong>the</strong> AC direct object <strong>in</strong> (3) not be<strong>in</strong>g represented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC aga<strong>in</strong> comes from<br />

<strong>the</strong> paradigm above <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a proportional determ<strong>in</strong>er; if <strong>the</strong> AC direct object were represented<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC <strong>in</strong> (3) (mak<strong>in</strong>g it relevant for VPE licens<strong>in</strong>g), <strong>the</strong>n why is <strong>the</strong> aspect of "fewness"<br />

miss<strong>in</strong>g from this clause, <strong>in</strong> a way that it is clearly present <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> non-ACD (4)? This account is<br />

conceptually similar to Wyngaerd and Zwart (1991) <strong>in</strong> that both try to account for ellipsis<br />

licens<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> ACD constructions without be<strong>in</strong>g dependent on QR.<br />

SPROUTING: Sprout<strong>in</strong>g (Chung et al. (1995)) is when, <strong>in</strong> a case of sluic<strong>in</strong>g, a DP/PP that was<br />

not present <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> AC appears overtly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ellipsis clause (typically as a wh-expression).<br />

(5) John saw The Lion K<strong>in</strong>g, but I don't know where<br />

(6) There navy seals were fir<strong>in</strong>g, but at what is unclear<br />

(7) Mary f<strong>in</strong>ished <strong>the</strong> exam on time, but with whose help is unclear<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> possibility of sprout<strong>in</strong>g see<strong>ms</strong> to be limited to cases of sluic<strong>in</strong>g. (8-10) below<br />

show that <strong>the</strong> acceptability of sprout<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> cases of VPE is severely degraded. Unacceptability of<br />

sprout<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> cases of VPE is, to <strong>the</strong> best of my knowledge, a novel empirical observation.<br />

(8) *John saw The Lion K<strong>in</strong>g. I wonder where Bill did<br />

(9) *The navy seals were fir<strong>in</strong>g, but at what <strong>the</strong> green berets were is unclear<br />

(10) *Mary f<strong>in</strong>ished <strong>the</strong> exam on time, but with whose help did Susan<br />

(Notice that <strong>the</strong> subject DPs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ECs are different from those <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir respective ACs <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to rule out MaxElide as be<strong>in</strong>g responsible for <strong>the</strong> unacceptability; see Hartman (2011).) The<br />

present approach can easily account for unacceptability of (8-10). Consider a case like (8): <strong>the</strong><br />

AC VP = [saw The Lion K<strong>in</strong>g], and <strong>the</strong> EC VP = [saw The Lion K<strong>in</strong>g t]; <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g locative PP <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> AC for <strong>the</strong> t <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> EC to match, hence (8) is not a licit case of<br />

VPE under <strong>the</strong> present approach s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> LF-identity conditions are not met. It is unclear to me<br />

why sprout<strong>in</strong>g would be acceptable <strong>in</strong> cases of sluic<strong>in</strong>g and not VPE, and it is worth po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out<br />

that <strong>the</strong> fact that sprout<strong>in</strong>g is allowed <strong>in</strong> cases of sluic<strong>in</strong>g is precisely why this account is limited<br />

to VPE and cannot be extended to IP ellipsis. Perhaps sprout<strong>in</strong>g is just ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>in</strong> which<br />

sluic<strong>in</strong>g and VPE differ, on par with as Chung et al.’s (1995) observation that while sluic<strong>in</strong>g can<br />

repair island violations, VPE cannot.<br />

References: Chung, S. et al. 1995. Sluic<strong>in</strong>g and logical form. Natural Language Semantics 3:<br />

239-282. Jayaseelan. K.A. 1990. Incomplete VP deletion and gapp<strong>in</strong>g. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Analysis 20:<br />

64-81. Kennedy, C. 2003 Ellipsis and syntactic representation. In The Interfaces: deriv<strong>in</strong>g and<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g omitted structures. Hartman, J. 2011. The semantic uniformity of traces: evidence<br />

from ellipsis parallelism. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry 42.3: 367-388. Lapp<strong>in</strong>, S. 1992. The syntactic basis<br />

of ellipsis resolution. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> Stuttgart Workshop on Ellipsis. Lasnik, H. 1999.<br />

Pseudogapp<strong>in</strong>g puzzles. In Fragments: Studies <strong>in</strong> ellipsis and gapp<strong>in</strong>g, 141-174. May, R. 1985.<br />

Logical Form. Cambridge: MIT Press. Sag, I. 1976. Deletion and Logical Form. PhD diss., MIT.<br />

Wyngaerd, G. V., and J.-W. Zwart. 1991. Reconstruction and Vehicle Change. In <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands, 151-160.


Timothy Leffel (NYU)<br />

Nonrestrictive adjectives and <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of scalar implicature<br />

Summary Nonrestrictive adjectives (NAs) attribute a general property to <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

denotation of <strong>the</strong> adjacent noun (Larson & Maruˇsič 2004; Morzycki 2008; etc.).<br />

(1) a. Cigarettes conta<strong>in</strong> harmful tox<strong>in</strong>s. b. ∴ Tox<strong>in</strong>s are (generally) harmful.<br />

Nom<strong>in</strong>al modifiers typically give rise to implicatures <strong>in</strong> downward entail<strong>in</strong>g contexts ((2)). Correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

implicatures are not triggered by NAs ((3)).<br />

(2) a. Every harmful chemical will be elim<strong>in</strong>ated by this product.<br />

b. � Not every chemical will be elim<strong>in</strong>ated by this product.<br />

(3) a. Every harmful tox<strong>in</strong> will be elim<strong>in</strong>ated by this product.<br />

b. �� Not every tox<strong>in</strong> will be elim<strong>in</strong>ated by this product.<br />

Here I argue that <strong>the</strong> contrast between (2) and (3) is not due to <strong>the</strong> contextual knowledge that<br />

tox<strong>in</strong>s are generally harmful. First I argue that scalar alternatives should be computed structurally<br />

(Katzir 2007) and excludability should be computed without access to contextual <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

(Magri 2009). I <strong>the</strong>n suggest that NAs <strong>in</strong> non-def<strong>in</strong>ite DPs comb<strong>in</strong>e with nouns via<br />

a presupposition-<strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g functional head <strong>in</strong> C<strong>in</strong>que’s (2010) “direct modification” doma<strong>in</strong><br />

(build<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>sights of Larson 1998;2000). This correctly predicts <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ference <strong>in</strong> (3) to be<br />

<strong>in</strong>valid because (3a) has a presupposition that <strong>the</strong> negation of (3b) lacks (details below).<br />

Background on SI The computation of a sentence’s scalar implicatures (SIs) depends on what<br />

<strong>the</strong> alternatives to that sentence are. In “Horn scale”-based approaches (e.g. Gazdar 1979;<br />

Sauerland 2004), alternatives are obta<strong>in</strong>ed by replac<strong>in</strong>g scalar ter<strong>ms</strong> with “scalemates,” so that<br />

(4a) and (4b) are alternatives to one ano<strong>the</strong>r (s<strong>in</strong>ce 〈some,all〉 is a Horn scale).<br />

(4) a. John ate some of <strong>the</strong> beans. b. John ate all of <strong>the</strong> beans.<br />

SIs are <strong>the</strong>n computed on <strong>the</strong> basis of whe<strong>the</strong>r an alternative is excludable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that<br />

its negation asymmetrically entails what is asserted. If an alternative is excludable, <strong>the</strong>n its<br />

negation is a predicted SI (details differ from <strong>the</strong>ory to <strong>the</strong>ory). Scale-based approaches do not<br />

predict implicatures to arise from <strong>in</strong>tersective modifiers as <strong>in</strong> (2), s<strong>in</strong>ce nouns like chemical are<br />

not on a lexical scale with harmful chemical.<br />

Katzir’s (2007) structural <strong>the</strong>ory of alternatives provides a natural explanation for (2) while<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sights of scale-based approaches. Alternatives are determ<strong>in</strong>ed syntactically: given<br />

a sentence ϕ, ψ ∈ Alt(ϕ) iff ψ can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed from ϕ by a f<strong>in</strong>ite series of (i) deletions of constituents,<br />

(ii) contractions (remove tree edge and identify end nodes), and (iii) substitutions of<br />

term<strong>in</strong>al elements for o<strong>the</strong>r elements (which are ei<strong>the</strong>r lexical or are subtrees of ϕ) of <strong>the</strong> same<br />

(syntactic) category. In this framework excludability is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of a better-than relation<br />

≺. ϕ is at least as good (�) as ψ iff ϕ is an alternative to ψ and ϕ entails ψ. If ϕ � ψ but<br />

ψ �� ϕ, <strong>the</strong>n ϕ is strictly better (≺) than ψ. Equivalently, ϕ ≺ ψ iff<br />

(5) a. ϕ is an alternative to ψ and entails ψ; and ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

b. ψ is not an alternative to ϕ, or ψ does not entail ϕ.<br />

Determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g excludability The better-than relation <strong>in</strong> (5) makes crucial reference to “entailment.”<br />

Two candidate def<strong>in</strong>itions of “entailment” are: (from Magri 2009)<br />

(6) a. ϕ logically entails ψ iff �ϕ� ⊆ �ψ�<br />

b. ϕ contextually entails ψ iff (�ϕ� ∩C) ⊆ �ψ�, where C is <strong>the</strong> Context Set.


Magri (2009;2011) argues that (6a) is <strong>the</strong> notion of entailment relevant for comput<strong>in</strong>g SIs—this<br />

is called <strong>the</strong> “bl<strong>in</strong>dness hypo<strong>the</strong>sis” (BH) because it says that SIs are computed without access<br />

to world knowledge. BH is crucial <strong>in</strong>, e.g. captur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> oddness of #Some Italians come from a<br />

warm country: it triggers <strong>the</strong> bl<strong>in</strong>d implicature that not all Italians come from a warm country.<br />

I propose that BH is required for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of structural alternatives to work. The argument<br />

is based on <strong>the</strong> existence of lexical ite<strong>ms</strong> whose sole function is to <strong>in</strong>troduce a presupposition:<br />

(7) Context: It is mutually known that several people o<strong>the</strong>r than Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party.<br />

a. Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party too. b. Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party.<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> contextual <strong>in</strong>formation, (7a) and (7b) are equivalent. Therefore if entailment is def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

as <strong>in</strong> (6b), it follows that (7b)≺(7a), because (7b) is an alternative to (7a), but (7a) is not<br />

an alternative to (7b) (see (5)). Hence an utterance of (7a) is <strong>in</strong>correctly predicted to give rise to<br />

<strong>the</strong> implicature that (7b) is not assertable. This argument can be replicated for also, even, etc.<br />

If <strong>in</strong>stead logical entailment (=(6a)) is used <strong>in</strong> (5), <strong>the</strong>n (7b) is not predicted to be strictly<br />

better than (7a), because:<br />

(8) a. (7b) is an alternative to (7a) (delete too and contract its branch), but<br />

b. (7b) does not logically entail (7a), s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re are logically consistent worlds <strong>in</strong><br />

which Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party and no one else did.<br />

and hence an utterance of (7a) is correctly predicted to not give rise to <strong>the</strong> implicature that (7b)<br />

is not assertable. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, logical entailment must be computed relative to local contexts (see<br />

Schlenker 2009), s<strong>in</strong>ce if entailment were computed globally, <strong>the</strong>n (9a) should be dispreferred<br />

to (9b), s<strong>in</strong>ce (9a) has no global presupposition.<br />

(9) a. John came to <strong>the</strong> party, and Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party too.<br />

b. John came to <strong>the</strong> party, and Mary came to <strong>the</strong> party.<br />

Nonrestrictive read<strong>in</strong>gs NR read<strong>in</strong>gs of attributive adjectives are licensed only <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> syntactic<br />

positions, which may vary depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> language (Bol<strong>in</strong>ger 1967; C<strong>in</strong>que 2010).<br />

(10) a. Every unsuitable word was deleted. ✓Rest. ✓NR<br />

b. Every word unsuitable was deleted. ✓Rest. ✗NR<br />

C<strong>in</strong>que (2010) has argued that NAs are <strong>in</strong>troduced as <strong>the</strong> specifiers of a DP-<strong>in</strong>ternal functional<br />

head <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “direct modification” doma<strong>in</strong>, which <strong>in</strong> English is immediately above NP but below<br />

a doma<strong>in</strong> of reduced relative clause adjectives with <strong>in</strong>tersective semantics. Larson (1998;2000)<br />

notes that many adjectives <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> direct modification doma<strong>in</strong> are associated with generic <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

I propose that NAs are also associated with genericity. The functional head that<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduces NAs (GENNR) is assigned <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g semantics, which encodes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ference <strong>in</strong><br />

(1b) as a presupposition (“:” <strong>in</strong>dicates def<strong>in</strong>edness condition, Γ is a generic quantifier).<br />

(11) GENNR : λPλQλy : Γx[P(x)][Q(x)].P(y)<br />

If harmful and tox<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> (3a) comb<strong>in</strong>e via (11), <strong>the</strong>n (3a) presupposes that tox<strong>in</strong>s are generically<br />

harmful. The structural alternative Every tox<strong>in</strong> will be... to (3a) does not have this presupposition,<br />

and so does not logically entail (3a) (by reason<strong>in</strong>g along <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es of (8)). Therefore <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ference from (3a) to (3b) is correctly predicted to be <strong>in</strong>valid. This explanation is not available<br />

to any pragmatic <strong>the</strong>ory of NR read<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

Selected references C<strong>in</strong>que, G. 2010. The syntax of adjectives • Katzir, R. 2007. Structurallydef<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

alternatives. L&P. • Larson, R. 1998. Events and modification <strong>in</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>als. SALT<br />

8. • Magri, G. 2009. A <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>in</strong>dividual-level predicates based on bl<strong>in</strong>d mandatory scalar<br />

implicatures. NaLS. • Sauerland, U. 2004. Scalar implicatures <strong>in</strong> complex sentences. L&P.


Shevaun Lewis (Maryland) & W<strong>in</strong>g Yee Chow (Maryland)<br />

!<br />

" # $<br />

' $ " $<br />

% &<br />

" ( )<br />

"! * ! ! !<br />

" " $ !<br />

!<br />

! $ "<br />

" % )<br />

$ $ !<br />

+ $<br />

! !<br />

" (<br />

, ! " "<br />

! " $<br />

" !<br />

) !<br />

$ - .! !<br />

$ ! -<br />

$<br />

"! . . /0 $ $ $<br />

1 " 2 3<br />

$ ! $ # #<br />

! $ " " " $<br />

$ $<br />

" + $<br />

/ !3 $ " "<br />

+ " " $ $<br />

+ $ " $ $<br />

4 5 $ "<br />

" ! "<br />

$ ! , ! "<br />

"! ! 5 $ $<br />

" $<br />

6<br />

" ( ! " "!<br />

' $ !<br />

+ ! "<br />

! $<br />

$<br />

$ " - $ -<br />

$ " + "


! " 1 2<br />

" $ !<br />

+ / 3 $<br />

" $ /7 83 , " - / "9 3 + " -<br />

/ "9 3 $ ! " "9 / 3<br />

/ 3 5 :; < = :* = "<br />

$<br />

/ "3 :; < = : < = "<br />

$<br />

/ 3 5 :; < = : < = $<br />

$ $ "<br />

$<br />

) " "9 ! $ "<br />

, " > ! $ + ; $<br />

" "9 $ $ + " "9<br />

- > ! !<br />

" $ ! $<br />

* # ! ! $<br />

? ! $ " ! + "<br />

, " /<br />

3<br />

+ $ /<br />

; " 3 )<br />

" , " > $ "<br />

+ " > $<br />

0 # ! " !<br />

$ "!<br />

+ ! $<br />

$ " $ )<br />

! + " ! @<br />

) "!<br />

" " ( " ; ! !<br />

!<br />

" " ! ! /<br />

3 " " ! !<br />

" " /<br />

; 3 " $ !<br />

/; " 3 6 $ !<br />

"<br />

. # A " / BB 3 C &4C &%D<br />

E / BB 3 4D<br />

- A $ ! / DCD3 C D<br />

4 ? E A , " / DD43 % &% D<br />

F A ) / BB43 G "<br />

% / BB 3 4C 4 %<br />

& H I A / BBD3 BC 4B


Charles L<strong>in</strong> (Indiana)<br />

Typological Perspectives on Relative Clause Process<strong>in</strong>g: Thematic Mapp<strong>in</strong>g, Case<br />

Markedness, Filler-Gap Integrations, and Their Relative Tim<strong>in</strong>g<br />

It is well-known that <strong>in</strong> head-<strong>in</strong>itial languages, relative clauses <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g subject<br />

extractions are processed with greater ease than those <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g object extractions (Brazilian<br />

Portuguese: Gouvea, 2003; Dutch: Frazier, 1987b; English: Ford, 1983, Gibson, Desmet,<br />

Grodner, Watson, & Ko, 2005, K<strong>in</strong>g & Just, 1991, K<strong>in</strong>g & Kutas, 1995, Traxler, Morris, &<br />

Seely, 2002; French: Cohen & Mehler, 1996, Frauenfelder, Segui, & Mehler, 1980, Holmes<br />

& O’Regan, 1981; German: Meckl<strong>in</strong>ger, Schriefers, Ste<strong>in</strong>hauer, & Friederici, 1995,<br />

Schriefers, Friederici, & Kuhn, 1995). In <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of relative clauses that are headf<strong>in</strong>al,<br />

however, <strong>the</strong> effect has been <strong>in</strong>consistent. Easier comprehension of subject relative<br />

clauses has been reported <strong>in</strong> Japanese (Miyamoto & Nakamura, 2003; Ueno & Garnsey,<br />

2008), Korean (Kwon, Lee, Gordon, Kluender, & Pol<strong>in</strong>sky, 2010), Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese (L<strong>in</strong> &<br />

Bever, 2006) and Turkish (Kahraman, Sato, Ono & Sakai, 2010), while easier process<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

object relative clauses has been reported <strong>in</strong> Basque (Carreiras, Duñabeitia, Vergara, de la<br />

Cruz-Pavía, & Laka, 2010), Japanese (Ishizuka, Nakatani, & Gibson, 2006) and Mandar<strong>in</strong><br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese (Hsiao & Gibson, 2003; Gibson & Wu, 2011; Packard, Ye, & Zhou, 2011).<br />

Research so far mostly assumed that <strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relativized gap and <strong>the</strong> head noun<br />

(i.e., <strong>the</strong> filler) is critical to relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g. A distance-based account has been<br />

adopted to account for <strong>the</strong> subject-object asymmetries <strong>in</strong> relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g across<br />

languages. The distance between <strong>the</strong> filler and <strong>the</strong> gap has been counted l<strong>in</strong>early based on <strong>the</strong><br />

number of <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g discourse entities (Gibson, 1998) and hierarchically based on <strong>the</strong><br />

number of <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g structural nodes (O’Grady, 1997). No <strong>the</strong>ory, however, has been able<br />

to account for <strong>the</strong> variations of <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>in</strong> both head-<strong>in</strong>itial and head-f<strong>in</strong>al relativization.<br />

In this talk, we review previous research (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g ours) and propose a typological<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g, pay<strong>in</strong>g special attention to head positions, case mark<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

and <strong>the</strong>matic orders (Figure 1). Languages are first classified based on <strong>the</strong> head positions<br />

<strong>in</strong>side NPs. Filler-gap dependencies (<strong>in</strong> head-<strong>in</strong>itial relatives) and gap-filler dependencies (<strong>in</strong><br />

head-f<strong>in</strong>al relatives) are taken to <strong>in</strong>volve dist<strong>in</strong>ctive process<strong>in</strong>g effects. The word-order<br />

variations with<strong>in</strong> languages with head-<strong>in</strong>itial relatives suggest that when <strong>the</strong> filler precedes<br />

<strong>the</strong> gap, <strong>the</strong> processor adopts an Active Filler Strategy (Frazier, 1987): upon encounter<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

filler, <strong>the</strong> parser <strong>in</strong>itiates <strong>the</strong> search for a gap to m<strong>in</strong>imize <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g memory load.<br />

If <strong>the</strong> gap precedes <strong>the</strong> filler as <strong>in</strong> a head-f<strong>in</strong>al type of dependency, <strong>the</strong> construction of<br />

a gap-filler dependency would be complicated by issues of structural garden path regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

where <strong>the</strong> relative clauses starts and where <strong>the</strong> gap is located (Hirose, 2006; L<strong>in</strong> & Bever,<br />

2011). Strategies that do not focus on construct<strong>in</strong>g a filler-gap relation would be used <strong>in</strong>stead.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> literature, it has been suggested that <strong>in</strong> case-prom<strong>in</strong>ent languages like Basque,<br />

Japanese, Korean, and Turkish, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> grammatical case is marked determ<strong>in</strong>es<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g difficulty (Carreiras et al., 2010). In a nom<strong>in</strong>ative-accusative language like<br />

Japanese, Korean, and Turkish, an object relative is more difficult than a subject relative<br />

because <strong>the</strong> object of a transitive verb receives an accusative case, which is more marked<br />

than <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>ative case of a subject NP. In an ergative language like Basque, <strong>the</strong> subject of<br />

a transitive verb receives <strong>the</strong> ergative case and is more marked than an object NP. Therefore,<br />

a subject relative is more difficult than an object relative.<br />

In a word order prom<strong>in</strong>ent language like Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese, <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>the</strong>matic<br />

order functions as a template to be mapped with <strong>in</strong>com<strong>in</strong>g nom<strong>in</strong>al arguments and verbs for<br />

“quick and dirty” <strong>the</strong>matic <strong>in</strong>terpretations (similar to <strong>the</strong> pseudosyntax of Townsend and


Bever, 2001 and <strong>the</strong> good-enough process<strong>in</strong>g of Ferreira, 2003). Sequences of nom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

arguments and verbs that follow <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>the</strong>matic orders <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language (e.g., Agentaction-Patient<br />

<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese object relatives) are easier to process than those that do not.<br />

Therefore, a subject relative is easier to process than an object relative (as was found by<br />

Gibson and Wu, 2011).<br />

The proposed typology demonstrates effects and strategies of structural <strong>in</strong>tegration,<br />

<strong>the</strong>matic mapp<strong>in</strong>gs as well as sensitivity to case markedness that h<strong>in</strong>ge on <strong>the</strong> typological<br />

properties of specific languages. We will fur<strong>the</strong>r exam<strong>in</strong>e previous experimental results of L2<br />

relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g and discuss <strong>the</strong> implications that such a typology has for second<br />

language studies of relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> particular, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

relative clauses <strong>in</strong> L1s and L2s of different types would be affected by <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctive<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g mechanis<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r language (cf., Juffs, 2005; Clahsen & Felser, 2006, 2008).<br />

Head-<strong>in</strong>itial<br />

Filler-gap <strong>in</strong>tegration<br />

Relative Clauses<br />

+ case-mark<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Morphological<br />

unmarkedness<br />

Figure 1. Typology of relative clause process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Head-f<strong>in</strong>al<br />

- case-mark<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Thematic template<br />

match<strong>in</strong>g


Bethany Lochbihler (McGill)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>al and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phase status<br />

This paper discusses <strong>in</strong>equality between syntactic phases as f<strong>in</strong>al that show stronger<br />

boundaries versus non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases that <strong>in</strong>stitute a more permeable boundary. F<strong>in</strong>al phases<br />

correspond to top level functional projections <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> spirit of Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw (2000), <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g CP,<br />

DP, PP and AP, and act as absolute boundaries on head movement (Li 1990, 2005) and<br />

restrict scrambl<strong>in</strong>g (Fowlie 2010). Non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases, like category def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g heads v and n<br />

(Marantz 2001) and <strong>the</strong>ta-complete heads v* (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2004), allow head movement and<br />

scrambl<strong>in</strong>g past <strong>the</strong> phase boundary. I propose that non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases occur with<strong>in</strong> extended<br />

projections, while f<strong>in</strong>al phases mark <strong>the</strong> edge of an extended projection. I <strong>in</strong>vestigate <strong>the</strong><br />

phonological predictions made implicit by <strong>the</strong> syntactic literature, namely that <strong>the</strong> difference<br />

<strong>in</strong> type of phase boundary (as more or less permeable) should affect <strong>the</strong> phonological form<br />

that takes syntactic phase spell-out as <strong>in</strong>put. I test <strong>the</strong> phonological effect of f<strong>in</strong>al phases <strong>in</strong><br />

Ojibwe, a Central Algonquian language spoken <strong>in</strong> Canada and parts of <strong>the</strong> USA, which has<br />

syntactically complex prosodic words exhibit<strong>in</strong>g word-<strong>in</strong>ternal phases. I show that <strong>the</strong> status<br />

of a phase as f<strong>in</strong>al or non-f<strong>in</strong>al bears on prosodic word boundaries, stress assignment and <strong>the</strong><br />

order of application of phonological processes.<br />

At <strong>the</strong> heart of <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between f<strong>in</strong>al and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases is <strong>the</strong><br />

lexical/functional specification of categories. First, Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw (2000) puts forth <strong>the</strong> notion of<br />

extended projection where a lexical head resides with<strong>in</strong> a functional shell (e.g. V with<strong>in</strong> InflP<br />

and CP) but shares its categorical properties with <strong>the</strong>se functional projections. Edges of<br />

extended projections are marked by <strong>the</strong> maximal projection of a top level functional head<br />

(e.g. C for a V head). I want to claim that <strong>the</strong>se top level functional projections <strong>in</strong> fact def<strong>in</strong>e<br />

f<strong>in</strong>al phases because <strong>the</strong>y create a firm boundary between <strong>the</strong> extended doma<strong>in</strong>s of lexical<br />

heads (e.g. between verbs and <strong>the</strong>ir nom<strong>in</strong>al arguments) and show unique properties with<br />

respect to syntactic movement, discussed below.<br />

Second, f<strong>in</strong>al phases <strong>in</strong>teract with head movement. Li (1990, 2005) looks at verb<br />

<strong>in</strong>corporation where a lexical verb comb<strong>in</strong>es with a causative morpheme via head movement,<br />

form<strong>in</strong>g one prosodic word. Li argues that <strong>in</strong>corporation of a lower verb <strong>in</strong>to a higher<br />

causative Vº cannot pass through Inflº and Cº (as was proposed by Baker 1988) s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

embedded <strong>in</strong>flection is never realized and verbs tak<strong>in</strong>g full clausal complements cannot<br />

undergo verb <strong>in</strong>corporation. Li proposes that movement of a lexical head cannot go through a<br />

functional head back to a lexical one, parallel to improper movement of XPs from A-bar to<br />

A-positions (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 1986). Although <strong>the</strong> specifier of a f<strong>in</strong>al phase can act as an escape<br />

hatch for A-bar movement (e.g. long distance wh-front<strong>in</strong>g), Li’s analysis implies that f<strong>in</strong>al<br />

phase heads, such as Cº, are an absolute boundary for head movement (Nºs also cannot move<br />

past Dº) while o<strong>the</strong>r phase heads, such as v*º, do not restrict head movement.<br />

A third set of data show<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> syntactic uniqueness of f<strong>in</strong>al phases comes from <strong>the</strong><br />

k<strong>in</strong>ds of scrambl<strong>in</strong>g possible cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically. Fowlie (2010) discusses data from different<br />

languages (e.g. Tagalog, Walpiri and Tohono O’odham), <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that scrambl<strong>in</strong>g can occur<br />

with<strong>in</strong> DPs (also APs, PPs) and with<strong>in</strong> CPs, but cannot occur past <strong>the</strong> edge of a DP or CP.<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong> we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> same set of f<strong>in</strong>al phases creat<strong>in</strong>g a stronger boundary, now with respect to<br />

scrambl<strong>in</strong>g, while non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases (xPs, v*P) do not show such strong restrictions.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>al phases (CP, DP, AP, PP) have syntactic status as <strong>the</strong> top level functional<br />

projection <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extended projection of a lexical head, and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases (xPs, v*P) are<br />

found <strong>in</strong>ternally to extended projections of lexical heads. However, phases conceptually exist<br />

so that <strong>the</strong> derivation is divided <strong>in</strong>to packets to be sent to <strong>the</strong> phonological and semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terfaces of <strong>the</strong> grammar (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2001). On <strong>the</strong> semantic side, f<strong>in</strong>al phases as whole<br />

extended projections are semantically saturated and <strong>the</strong>ta-marked. Next I will discuss some<br />

effects of <strong>the</strong> different phase types beyond <strong>the</strong> syntax at <strong>the</strong> phonological <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

Ojibwe phonology shows <strong>the</strong> effects of f<strong>in</strong>al phases (versus non-f<strong>in</strong>al) <strong>in</strong> several ways.<br />

First, this polysyn<strong>the</strong>tic language tends to def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> edges of prosodic words by f<strong>in</strong>al phases<br />

1


F<strong>in</strong>al and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phase status<br />

(potentially conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>termediate phases), such that <strong>in</strong>dependent words correspond to CP,<br />

DP, AP, PP or are elements outside of <strong>the</strong>se doma<strong>in</strong>s, such as quantifiers or discourse<br />

particles <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> specifiers of DP and CP respectively. The spell-out of a f<strong>in</strong>al phase places a<br />

f<strong>in</strong>al prosodic word boundary as well as a syntactic boundary.<br />

Second, stress assignment <strong>in</strong> Ojibwe is dependent on phase doma<strong>in</strong>, where secondary<br />

stress is computed at <strong>the</strong> spell-out of each phase, but primary stress is only computed at f<strong>in</strong>al<br />

phases. Newell (2008) shows <strong>the</strong> sensitivity of secondary stress to word-<strong>in</strong>ternal (non-f<strong>in</strong>al)<br />

phases where degenerate feet are only allowed at <strong>the</strong> right edge of a phase doma<strong>in</strong> (1).<br />

Conversely, primary stress marks <strong>the</strong> antepenultimate foot of <strong>the</strong> entire prosodic word, which<br />

is <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al phase CP <strong>in</strong> (1) (bolded).<br />

(1) (bòo)(ní)|(m<strong>in</strong>ì)(kwèe) (*(bóo)(nimì)(nikwèe))<br />

[CP[InflP[aP booni]-[vP m<strong>in</strong>ik-iwee]]]<br />

quit-dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g-VAI ‘he quit dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g’ (Newell 2008:214)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, f<strong>in</strong>al phases affect <strong>the</strong> distribution of T-Pal(atalization) (i.e. /t, /→[č,]/__/i/), which<br />

can only occur between segments spelled-out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same phase and is blocked across phase<br />

edges (see Slav<strong>in</strong> 2007; Mathieu 2009). T-Pal <strong>in</strong>teracts with vowel Apocope <strong>in</strong> Ojibwe,<br />

which can delete <strong>the</strong> environment for T-Pal, namely /i/ (Piggott & Kaye 1973). (2a) <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

a T-Pal>Apocope order (or a rank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> OT) s<strong>in</strong>ce /t/ becomes [č] despite <strong>the</strong> deletion of /i/,<br />

and (2b) is <strong>the</strong> opposite Apocope>T-Pal order where vowel deletion bleeds palatalization. I<br />

account for this order<strong>in</strong>g paradox by appeal<strong>in</strong>g to f<strong>in</strong>al phases and <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that certa<strong>in</strong><br />

phonological processes can only occur at <strong>the</strong> spell-out of a specific type of phase. I propose<br />

that <strong>the</strong> process of T-Pal applies at <strong>the</strong> spell-out of every phase but Apocope only applies at a<br />

f<strong>in</strong>al phase spell-out (account<strong>in</strong>g for Apocope exclusively delet<strong>in</strong>g actual word f<strong>in</strong>al<br />

segments, and not <strong>in</strong>termediate f<strong>in</strong>al segments cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically, e.g. Hale 1973).<br />

Therefore, <strong>in</strong> (2b) both T-Pal and Apocope are triggered at a f<strong>in</strong>al phase, and so Apocope can<br />

bleed T-Pal, but <strong>in</strong> (2a) T-Pal is triggered <strong>in</strong> an earlier v*P phase and Apocope must wait<br />

until <strong>the</strong> spell-out of <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al CP phase, giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> apparent T-Pal>Apocope order<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(2) a. nimiškawač b. peemaatisit<br />

[CP ni-[v*P miškaw-a-t-i]] [[peem-aat-isi]-t-i]<br />

1-freeze/hard-VII-<strong>in</strong>trans-VAI along-live-VAI -3conj-PART<br />

‘I am frozen.’ ‘he who lives’ (Kaye & Piggott 1973:356)<br />

The idea that CP and DP (as well as AP and PP) constitute special doma<strong>in</strong>s is implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

syntactic literature, a property I aim to make explicit with <strong>the</strong> notion of f<strong>in</strong>al phases def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by extended projection of a lexical category. The effects of phases are seen <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntax as<br />

well as <strong>the</strong> phonology, and <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between f<strong>in</strong>al and non-f<strong>in</strong>al phases likewise affects<br />

both parts of <strong>the</strong> grammar.<br />

References: Baker, M. 1988. Incorporation. UChicago Press. | Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. 1986. Barriers.<br />

MIT Press. | Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. 2004. Beyond explanatory adequacy. In Belletti et al (eds), The<br />

cartography of syntactic structures. OUP. | Fowlie, M. 2010. More Multiple Multiple Spellout.<br />

Ms. UCLA. | Gri<strong>ms</strong>haw, J. 2000. Locality and Extended Projection. In Coopmans et al (eds),<br />

Lexical Specification and Insertion. Benjam<strong>in</strong>s. | Hale, K. 1973. Deep and surface canonical<br />

disparities <strong>in</strong> relation to analysis and change. Current Trends <strong>in</strong> <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> 11: 408-458. | Kaye,<br />

J. D., and Piggott, G. L. 1973. On <strong>the</strong> Cyclical Nature of Ojibwa T-Palatalization. LI 4:345-362. |<br />

Li, Y. 1990. X 0 -b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g and Verb Incorporation. LI 21:399-426. | Li, Y. 2005. Xº: A Theory of <strong>the</strong><br />

Morphology-Syntax Interface. MIT Press. | Marantz, Alec. 2001. Words. Ms. MIT. | Mathieu, E.<br />

2009. Noun Incorporation and Word Formation via Phrasal Movement. Ms. UOttawa. | Newell,<br />

H. 2008. Aspects of <strong>the</strong> morphology and phonology of phases. PhD Dissertation, McGill. |<br />

Slav<strong>in</strong>, T. 2007. T-Palatalization <strong>in</strong> Oji-Cree as a w<strong>in</strong>dow <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> morphosyntactic structure of<br />

<strong>the</strong> verbal complex. Generals Paper, UToronto.<br />

2


Terje Lohndal (Maryland) & Bridget Samuels (CalTech)<br />

On how null elements and unpronounced copies are different<br />

Syntax creates sound-mean<strong>in</strong>g pairs. With<strong>in</strong> Cho<strong>ms</strong>kyan generative grammar, this is<br />

typically described <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of transferr<strong>in</strong>g (portions of) syntactic structures to <strong>the</strong><br />

phonological/phonetic and semantic/conceptual <strong>in</strong>terfaces through PF and LF, respectively.<br />

However, to paraphrase Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky & Halle (1968), whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> output of <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

component and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put of <strong>the</strong> phonological component are <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g is an empirical<br />

issue. Indeed, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> 1970’s, much work on <strong>the</strong> syntax-phonology <strong>in</strong>terface has focused on<br />

how to derive phonological doma<strong>in</strong>s from syntactic structures under <strong>the</strong> assumption that<br />

<strong>the</strong>se two representations are related but non-isomorphic. This issue of doma<strong>in</strong>s is, however,<br />

but one piece of <strong>the</strong> much larger puzzle of how to characterize <strong>the</strong> transformations at PF<br />

which turn hierarchical, phonology-free morphosyntactic structures <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>ear phonological<br />

representations. The purpose of this talk is to shed light on <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g of operations at PF,<br />

and crucially argue that empty categories <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntax can sometimes create a configuration<br />

that is not l<strong>in</strong>earizable. Our goal <strong>in</strong> this paper is to scrut<strong>in</strong>ize <strong>the</strong> conditions under which such<br />

configurations arise, and <strong>in</strong>tegrate <strong>the</strong>se with more general observations about <strong>the</strong> effects of<br />

and differences between unpronounced copies and null elements <strong>in</strong> morphophonology.<br />

The specific case study that we will focus on relates to ‘empty edges’: phonologically<br />

contentless edges of certa<strong>in</strong> doma<strong>in</strong>s. Whe<strong>the</strong>r to characterize <strong>the</strong>se doma<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> syntactic or<br />

phonological ter<strong>ms</strong> will be one of our primary concerns. Towards this goal, we provide a new<br />

analysis of facts traditionally attributed to <strong>the</strong> ECP (e.g., Stowell 1981; cf. Pesetsky &<br />

Torrego 2001, Bošković & Lasnik 2003). An (2007a) suggests that <strong>the</strong>se data are captured by<br />

<strong>the</strong> Intonational Phrase Edge Generalization (IPEG), which states that “<strong>the</strong> edge of an<br />

Intonational phrase cannot be empty (where <strong>the</strong> edge encompasses <strong>the</strong> specifier and <strong>the</strong> head<br />

of <strong>the</strong> relevant syntactic constituent).” This expla<strong>in</strong>s why sentences which are unacceptable<br />

with an empty CP edge can be ameliorated by overt content, be it <strong>in</strong> SpecCP or <strong>in</strong> C (1).<br />

(1) a. *I saw <strong>the</strong> child yesterday [Øspec ØC Mary was wait<strong>in</strong>g for]<br />

b. I saw <strong>the</strong> child yesterday [who ØC Mary was wait<strong>in</strong>g for]<br />

c. I saw <strong>the</strong> child yesterday [Øspec that Mary was wait<strong>in</strong>g for]<br />

In order to allow for <strong>the</strong> omission of C <strong>in</strong> (2b), An (2007a) needs to assume that <strong>the</strong><br />

formation of a separate I-phrase for clausal complements of verbs (and restrictive relative<br />

clauses) is optional. The IPEG also extends to o<strong>the</strong>r categories: vP (3a,b), DP (3c,d), and AP<br />

(3e,f).<br />

(2) a. I believe [CP that [IP John liked l<strong>in</strong>guistics]].<br />

b. I believe [CP ØC [IP John liked l<strong>in</strong>guistics.]]<br />

(3) a. Eat <strong>the</strong> cake John did and eat <strong>the</strong> cookie Mary did<br />

b. *[vP Eat <strong>the</strong> cake] John did and [Øspec Øv <strong>the</strong> cookie] Mary did<br />

c. John likes this book of l<strong>in</strong>guistics and Mary, that book of physics.<br />

d. *John likes this book of l<strong>in</strong>guistics and Mary likes [Øspec ØD book of physics.<br />

e. Eager to w<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pulitzer Prize, John is, and eager to w<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nobel Prize, Mary is.<br />

f. *[AP Eager to w<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pulitzer Prize], John is, and [Øspec ØA to w<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nobel Prize,<br />

Mary is].<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> justification for <strong>the</strong> IPEG is unclear and does not follow from <strong>in</strong>dependent facts<br />

about <strong>the</strong> architecture of grammar. Moreover, it requires syntactic analyses which violate<br />

Bare Phrase Structure because An is forced to stipulate empty specifiers, which Bare Phrase<br />

structure rejects (cf. Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 1995, Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 1998). We suggest a<br />

new analysis which accounts for <strong>the</strong> above data by referr<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>dependently needed<br />

constructs, which we argue should be <strong>the</strong> null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis given M<strong>in</strong>imalist concerns about<br />

modular architecture (cf. Idsardi and Raimy <strong>in</strong> press).<br />

We argue for a syntactic—or at least, ‘pre-phonological’—account of empty-edge<br />

phenomena which h<strong>in</strong>ges on exactly how we understand <strong>the</strong> PF <strong>in</strong>terface. We will make a


specific proposal concern<strong>in</strong>g this architecture, show how this new account can capture all <strong>the</strong><br />

data that have been discussed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature, and extend it to cover additional data which<br />

have not previously been addressed <strong>in</strong> treatments of <strong>the</strong> ECP. We argue that (1a) and (3b,d,f)<br />

are unacceptable because <strong>the</strong>y cannot be l<strong>in</strong>earized. Specifically, two consecutive syntactic<br />

objects cannot be null at <strong>the</strong> stage when l<strong>in</strong>earization applies, or else <strong>the</strong> algorithm will be<br />

unable to return a l<strong>in</strong>earization statement, cf. (4).<br />

(4) L<strong>in</strong>earization algorithm: When encounter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> merged {α, β}, α and β ccommand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

each o<strong>the</strong>r, upon Spell-Out, return an ordered set or .<br />

We follow Epste<strong>in</strong> et al. (1998) and Richards (2004) <strong>in</strong> assum<strong>in</strong>g that mutual ccommand<br />

‘overdeterm<strong>in</strong>es’ l<strong>in</strong>earization; <strong>the</strong> Precedence Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple demands that<br />

<strong>in</strong> such a configuration, one object’s c-command relations over <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r must be ignored<br />

(which object be<strong>in</strong>g subject to parametric variation). The key component to our analysis of<br />

(1)-(3) is that <strong>the</strong> algorithm (4) only succeeds <strong>in</strong> return<strong>in</strong>g an ordered pair when <strong>the</strong> elements<br />

to be l<strong>in</strong>earized are featurally dist<strong>in</strong>ct. They have to be dist<strong>in</strong>ct because of <strong>the</strong> irreflexivity<br />

condition on l<strong>in</strong>earization, as Nunes (1995, 2004) po<strong>in</strong>ts out. If <strong>the</strong> two elements are not<br />

featurally dist<strong>in</strong>ct, this results <strong>in</strong> a crash when a merged pair of elements has only Edge<br />

Features (EF; Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2008), as a result of non-<strong>in</strong>sertion of phonological content (which is<br />

crucially dist<strong>in</strong>ct from copy deletion, contra An 2007b.) Two elements with only EF are nondist<strong>in</strong>ct,<br />

which will result <strong>in</strong> a crash at l<strong>in</strong>earization. EFs are visible to <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>earization<br />

algorithm s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>se features are never deleted, as Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2008) argues, but <strong>the</strong>y are also<br />

never phonologically realized. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, we provide evidence that copies are marked for<br />

deletion prior to l<strong>in</strong>earization but actually deleted after l<strong>in</strong>earization, which exempts<br />

unpronounced copies from caus<strong>in</strong>g empty-edge crashes and resolves a tension between <strong>the</strong><br />

empty-edge bans <strong>in</strong> An (2007a) and (2007b), one of which is asymmetrical (left edge only)<br />

but <strong>in</strong>cludes copies, and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r which is symmetrical but excludes copies.<br />

Assum<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> accordance with Bare Phrase Structure that C does not project a specifier<br />

<strong>in</strong> declarative sentences such as (5a) [or <strong>in</strong> (2b)] (cf. Starke 2004), our account<br />

straightforwardly predicts <strong>the</strong> sentences <strong>in</strong> (5) to be grammatical, while such cases constitute<br />

prima facie exceptions to <strong>the</strong> IPEG.<br />

(5) a. [CP ØC [TP Mary was wait<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> child]]<br />

b. [CP Who did Mary [vP see [VP tv tobj ]]]<br />

The same holds for adjuncts to matrix clauses, where <strong>the</strong>re is no null element <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(6) a. [CP [AP True to herself], [TP she planned to rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>re ]]. (Selkirk 2005)<br />

b. [CP [PP On <strong>the</strong> fourth of July], [TP we’ll have a parade and fireworks]].<br />

We fur<strong>the</strong>r show that <strong>the</strong> above analysis extends to account for <strong>the</strong> unacceptable<br />

sentences <strong>in</strong> (3) as well as those <strong>in</strong> (7), <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a sentential subject (7b) and a topicalized<br />

CP (7d). In both <strong>the</strong> unacceptable cases, <strong>the</strong>re will be two objects that only have EFs that are<br />

adjacent, thus <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>earization algorithm crashes.<br />

(7) a. [CP ØC [CP That John is a genius] was believed by many people.<br />

b. *[CP ØC [CP ØC John is a genius] was believed by many people.<br />

c. [CP ØC [CP That John is a genius], Mary believed.<br />

d. *[CP ØC [CP ØC John is a genius], Mary believed.<br />

We will address fur<strong>the</strong>r cases as well, and <strong>the</strong>n turn to o<strong>the</strong>r data concern<strong>in</strong>g how<br />

morphophonology deals with null elements. We argue that morphophonology ‘knows about’<br />

null elements s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y trigger phonological cycles and produce cyclic block<strong>in</strong>g effects, but<br />

that unpronounced copies are phonologically <strong>in</strong>ert (Samuels 2011). This streng<strong>the</strong>ns our<br />

claim that unpronounced copies and null elements must be dist<strong>in</strong>guished, and we argue that<br />

<strong>the</strong> former are elim<strong>in</strong>ated earlier than <strong>the</strong> latter – null elements actually persist until <strong>the</strong><br />

handoff to phonology proper.


Sophia Manika, Sergey Avrut<strong>in</strong> & Eric Reuland (Utrecht)<br />

The bits of dependencies<br />

Background<br />

Consider a m<strong>in</strong>imally different pair:<br />

1. Maria blames, <strong>in</strong> most of <strong>the</strong> cases, herself for <strong>the</strong> bad grades<br />

2. Maria blames, <strong>in</strong> most of <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong> teacher for <strong>the</strong> bad grades<br />

Interpretation of <strong>the</strong> first sentence requires establish<strong>in</strong>g a syntactic dependency between an<br />

anaphoric element and its antecedent. Interpretation of <strong>the</strong> second sentence requires<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegration of def<strong>in</strong>ite NP <strong>the</strong> teacher <strong>in</strong>to discourse as part of <strong>the</strong> blam<strong>in</strong>g event.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Reuland's model of <strong>the</strong> language - relevant architecture of work<strong>in</strong>g memory<br />

(Reuland 2009, 2010), <strong>the</strong>se two operations nicely reflect two dist<strong>in</strong>ct memory networks<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> language process<strong>in</strong>g. In Reuland's term<strong>in</strong>ology one computes form/syntax (socalled<br />

Declarative / Procedural Interface, or DPI) and one is responsible for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tegration of<br />

<strong>the</strong> content/discourse <strong>in</strong>formation.<br />

The current study provides experimental evidence for <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong>se two dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

syste<strong>ms</strong> and proposes a novel measure of process<strong>in</strong>g complexity. Specifically, we<br />

demonstrate that it is <strong>the</strong> entropy of <strong>the</strong> verbal paradigm (an <strong>in</strong>formation - <strong>the</strong>oretic<br />

notion <strong>in</strong>troduced by Shannon 1948) that <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>the</strong> operation of <strong>the</strong> relevant<br />

memory syste<strong>ms</strong>. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, we demonstrate that changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> entropy value of<br />

<strong>the</strong> verb family <strong>in</strong>fluence (crucially, <strong>in</strong> a different way!) <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g cost of <strong>the</strong><br />

reflexive object NP and a def<strong>in</strong>ite object NP.<br />

Entropy calculation<br />

Inflectional entropy of a verb’s paradigm <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> level of similarity 1 among its ite<strong>ms</strong>. It<br />

is a function of <strong>the</strong> number of <strong>in</strong>flected for<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>the</strong> verb, <strong>the</strong> frequency of each verb form<br />

and <strong>the</strong> number of possible l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>the</strong> form can be found <strong>in</strong> (i.e. <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

form “work” <strong>in</strong> English can be used as 1 st sg, 2 nd sg, <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itive etc). In this sense, higher<br />

entropy reflects a more “uniform” distribution of memory traces between for<strong>ms</strong> (hence,<br />

higher uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong> lexical retrieval), while a more “diverse” distribution is represented by a<br />

lower entropy (and thus by a lower uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong> retrieval). Van Ewijk & Avrut<strong>in</strong> (2011,<br />

among o<strong>the</strong>rs) showed that <strong>in</strong>flectional entropy of a verb modulated retrieval of a target form<br />

and suggest that entropy is an <strong>in</strong>dex of complexity.<br />

Method<br />

Thirty-four Dutch native students, aged 21-29 years old, were tested <strong>in</strong> a self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

task. <strong>Read<strong>in</strong>g</strong> times <strong>in</strong> each word were measured.<br />

Twenty-four Dutch verbs were chosen based on <strong>the</strong>ir entropy values (taken from van Ewijk &<br />

Avrut<strong>in</strong>, 2011) and were classified <strong>in</strong> two groups: low and high entropy. Each verb was used<br />

<strong>in</strong> two conditions; with a syntactic dependency (a reflexive pronoun) and without (proper<br />

name), result<strong>in</strong>g to forty-eight experimental ite<strong>ms</strong>. Although <strong>the</strong> critical regions are <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

after <strong>the</strong> verb (rg 2) and <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of object <strong>in</strong>tegration (rg 7), we <strong>in</strong>cluded subsequent regions<br />

(rg 8- 11) to account for spillover effects. All words <strong>in</strong> regions 3-11, (except for <strong>the</strong> proper<br />

name), were identical ensur<strong>in</strong>g weighed <strong>in</strong>formation load across ite<strong>ms</strong> (see Table below).<br />

1 Shannon’s notion of Entropy was proposed to apply to a random variable X to describe <strong>the</strong> degree of<br />

uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty related to <strong>the</strong> distribution of probabilities of <strong>the</strong> variable. For simplicity reasons we refer to Entropy<br />

as degree of similarity because we are study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>flectional families and when entropy is applied it mirrors how<br />

different <strong>the</strong> verb-for<strong>ms</strong> with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> paradig<strong>ms</strong> are.


He/She Verb, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> most cases, HIM(HER)SELF/ Loes and not <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r (noun)<br />

Reflexive<br />

NP<br />

HIJ/ZIJ verb <strong>in</strong> de meeste gevallen<br />

ZICHZELF<br />

Loes<br />

en niet de andere<br />

vary<strong>in</strong>g entropy constant entropy object spill over<br />

region 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11<br />

Results<br />

At <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of verb retrieval (rg 3), high entropy verbs were read significantly faster than low<br />

entropy ones (p< .05, r=.35).<br />

At <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>the</strong> object (rg7), <strong>the</strong>re was a significant <strong>in</strong>teraction between type of object and<br />

verb entropy (p< 0.5, r=.43). Importantly, contrasts revealed that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction was due to<br />

<strong>the</strong> reflexives; higher entropy verbs delayed establish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dependency between <strong>the</strong><br />

reflexive and its referent.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong>re was a ma<strong>in</strong> effect of object type <strong>in</strong> rg8. Reflexives were read significantly<br />

faster across conditions than referential NPs (p< .001, r=.56).<br />

Discussion<br />

These data show how entropy can <strong>in</strong>fluence memory processes. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>y show that<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of a dependency between a reflexive and its antecedent is not only<br />

grammatically constra<strong>in</strong>ed, but it is <strong>in</strong>fluenced by non-grammatical constra<strong>in</strong>ts such as verbal<br />

entropy as well.<br />

Activation of a verb form automatically activates its paradigm network. The more “uniform”<br />

<strong>the</strong> probability distribution of <strong>the</strong> verb for<strong>ms</strong> with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> paradigm is, <strong>the</strong> higher is <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>flectional entropy. Verbs with high entropy lose less energy than low entropy verbs dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> spread of activation, and retrieval is faster (as <strong>in</strong> van Ewijk & Avrut<strong>in</strong>, replicated here <strong>in</strong><br />

rg3). The reflexive cases signal <strong>the</strong> need for an <strong>in</strong>tra-sentential referent and <strong>the</strong> verb is readdressed.<br />

High <strong>in</strong>flectional entropy <strong>in</strong>duces competition between <strong>the</strong> target verb form and<br />

<strong>the</strong> “yet-not-decayed” for<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>the</strong> paradigm that have similar probability. This<br />

“<strong>in</strong>terference”, present only <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>flectional paradig<strong>ms</strong> with high entropy, delays <strong>the</strong><br />

establish<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> dependency between <strong>the</strong> reflexive and its antecedent (<strong>in</strong>teraction <strong>in</strong> rg 7).<br />

Additionally, <strong>the</strong> effect at region 8 <strong>in</strong>dicates that grammatically-constra<strong>in</strong>ed dependencies<br />

(reflexives) are established faster than non-grammatically constra<strong>in</strong>ed dependencies (noun).<br />

That implies <strong>the</strong> existence of a dist<strong>in</strong>ct network that computes, very fast, syntactic<br />

requirements, such as assignment of an <strong>in</strong>tra-sentential referent. Delay of <strong>the</strong> nouns results<br />

from <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>in</strong>formation from discourse is needed for a referent to be found.<br />

References:<br />

Reuland, E. (2009). Language, Symbolization and beyond. In R. B. Knight. (Ed.), The<br />

Prehistory of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Reuland, E. (2010). Imag<strong>in</strong>ation, plann<strong>in</strong>g and work<strong>in</strong>g memory: <strong>the</strong> emergence of language.<br />

Current Anthropology, 51, 99-110.<br />

Shannon, C. E. (1948). A ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>the</strong>ory of communication. Bell System Technical<br />

Journal , 27, 379–423.<br />

van Ewijk, L., & Avrut<strong>in</strong>, S. (2011). Auditory lexical decision <strong>in</strong> healthy elderly and young<br />

subjects.The effect of <strong>in</strong>formation load and <strong>in</strong>flectional entropy. Procedia- Social and<br />

Behavioural Sciences, 23, 104-105.


Rita Manz<strong>in</strong>i (Firenze) & Anna Roussou (Patras)<br />

Empty categories: empty operators and variables at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface<br />

We argue for a restricted <strong>in</strong>ventory of <strong>in</strong>terpretable non-pronounced elements of grammar,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g only empty operators and variables. Our model observes m<strong>in</strong>imalist postulates<br />

(Inclusiveness, one level of syntactic representation, etc.), but is representational, s<strong>in</strong>ce we ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><br />

that operators and variables are <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>in</strong>terpretive pr<strong>in</strong>ciples at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

1. Phrasal ‘trace’ and ‘PRO’ are (just) variables at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface. In standard m<strong>in</strong>imalism,<br />

movement is Internal Merge (IM): a Probe α with an EPP feature targets a Goal β already merged <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> derivation, as <strong>in</strong> (1). IM is construed as a mechanism that <strong>in</strong>troduces a second copy of β. If all<br />

<strong>in</strong>stances of ‘movement’ are overt (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky 2000), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> EPP can be viewed as an <strong>in</strong>struction<br />

for lexicalization.<br />

(1) [αP β αEPP [… [ γP γ.. β]]]<br />

Alternatively, <strong>in</strong> multi-dom<strong>in</strong>ance (MD) approaches (Starke 2001; Frampton 2004; Johnson 2009;<br />

de Vries 2009; a.o.) β merges once (externally, EM), and ‘re-merge’ amounts to immediate<br />

dom<strong>in</strong>ance by a higher node, so that β has more than one mo<strong>the</strong>r node, as <strong>in</strong> (2). (2) allows for<br />

spell-out of β <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> higher or <strong>the</strong> lower position, subject to some PF-algorithm.<br />

(2) [αP α(EPP) [… [γP γ.. β]]]<br />

(1) and (2) share <strong>the</strong> requirement that β merge <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower position for argument structure<br />

satisfaction, at least if β is an argument, i.e. EM expresses <strong>the</strong> core properties of D-structure.<br />

A different logical possibility is that Merge is always external, with β directly merg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

EPP position; <strong>the</strong>re is a s<strong>in</strong>gle copy/occurrence and no re-merge, as <strong>in</strong> (3). S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> position of<br />

Merge <strong>in</strong> (3) is also that of spell-out, <strong>the</strong>re is no need for a PF-deletion operation, as <strong>in</strong> (1), or<br />

l<strong>in</strong>earization algorithm as <strong>in</strong> (2). In ter<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>in</strong>terpretation, though, β associates with some lower<br />

part of <strong>the</strong> configuration, here <strong>in</strong>dicated as e. Therefore we need to consider what e amounts to –<br />

and what ensures cha<strong>in</strong> formation between β and e.<br />

(3) [αP β αEPP [… [ γP γ .. (e) ]]]<br />

In standard generative <strong>the</strong>ory, if β is an argument, <strong>the</strong>n e corresponds to its <strong>the</strong>ta-position – whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

e is a copy or its GB counterpart, i.e. <strong>the</strong> identity element e of <strong>the</strong> str<strong>in</strong>g. But suppose <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ta-role<br />

has no structural correlate. This means that <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> should be computed at <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terface by some<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretive algorithm.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> sake of concreteness consider <strong>the</strong> wh-construction <strong>in</strong> (4). In <strong>the</strong> copy-<strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

movement, <strong>the</strong> second gap e2 <strong>in</strong> (4) is a copy of what which deletes at PF, while LF converts it to a<br />

variable (cf. Fox 2002). The first gap e1 is a copy of you, which aga<strong>in</strong> deletes, while <strong>the</strong> PFrealization<br />

co<strong>in</strong>cides with that of <strong>the</strong> EPP argument (syntactic subject). If e, now understood as a<br />

variable, is not structurally represented (as a copy or some o<strong>the</strong>r empty category), as we propose<br />

here, it must be <strong>in</strong>troduced directly at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

(4) [C What did [I you [V (e1) see (e2) ]]]<br />

Indeed see, be<strong>in</strong>g a two-place predicate, <strong>in</strong>troduces two variables (x, y) which are bound by <strong>the</strong><br />

external and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal arguments respectively (by <strong>the</strong> λ-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g mechanism of Heim & Kratzer<br />

1997, cf. Adger & Ramchand’s (2005) Λ feature, etc.). This (operator, variable) relation is fully<br />

equivalent to <strong>the</strong> movement operation – and it is redundant when added to it (Brody’s (2003)<br />

argument for representationalism). In an A’-dependency, <strong>the</strong> wh-operator is <strong>in</strong> turn construed as a<br />

λ-abstractor, and so can be construed <strong>the</strong> EPP <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong> subject, follow<strong>in</strong>g Butler (2004).<br />

In short, a ‘movement’ relation is def<strong>in</strong>ed by a s<strong>in</strong>gle argument satisfy<strong>in</strong>g two <strong>in</strong>stances of<br />

λs. Though control will not be considered here <strong>in</strong> any detail, we notice that <strong>the</strong> same also holds of<br />

(obligatory) control, which m<strong>in</strong>imally <strong>in</strong>volves two <strong>the</strong>ta-roles (λ-abstractors) bound by <strong>the</strong> same<br />

argument. In ‘arbitrary’ control, one variable is simply bound by a generic closure operator. Hence<br />

PRO, like trace, <strong>in</strong> present ter<strong>ms</strong> translates to a variable at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface.<br />

2. There are no head ‘trace’ and pro. The empirical relevance of our discussion becomes more<br />

evident when we move from <strong>the</strong> dislocation of phrases (specifically DP’s) to that of heads<br />

(specifically verbal heads). Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2001) excludes that IM applies to heads. If on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand,


head movement is a PF operation, as Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky proposes, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>in</strong> syntax heads always sit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

EM position, conceived of as <strong>the</strong>ir D-structure position. At <strong>the</strong> same time it is not clear what PF<br />

movement amounts to. A possible construal for it is Morphological Merger (Marantz 1988, Embick<br />

and Noyer 2001). However, to <strong>the</strong> extent that similar Merge operations occur <strong>in</strong> different<br />

components, obvious notions of economy (e.g. non redundancy) appear to be violated.<br />

The discussion <strong>in</strong> part 1 suggests ano<strong>the</strong>r logical possibility, namely that <strong>in</strong> syntax heads<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed occupy <strong>the</strong>ir EM position which is now identified with <strong>the</strong>ir surface position. Consider for<br />

example V-to-C ‘movement’ (or V-<strong>in</strong>-C position<strong>in</strong>g) as <strong>in</strong> German (5). The Merge position of <strong>the</strong><br />

verb <strong>in</strong> (5) will be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d of considerations as <strong>the</strong> Merge of <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase <strong>in</strong><br />

(4), i.e. <strong>the</strong> (‘EPP’) <strong>in</strong>struction to lexicalize certa<strong>in</strong> properties (<strong>the</strong> wh-property or <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

subject EPP <strong>in</strong> (4), <strong>the</strong> ‘f<strong>in</strong>iteness’ property <strong>in</strong> (5)).<br />

(5) [CP Gestern sahst [IP du den Peter ]] (lit: ‘yesterday saw you Peter’)<br />

At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence that <strong>the</strong>re are head variables <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> putative Dstructure<br />

position. The <strong>in</strong>terpretive question <strong>the</strong>n is: how can predicate-argument relations be<br />

established? When <strong>the</strong> argument is <strong>in</strong> a position to b<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> variable <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>the</strong> predicate, <strong>the</strong><br />

discussion goes through as <strong>in</strong> (4). So <strong>the</strong> question is what happens when <strong>the</strong> reverse configuration<br />

holds, as <strong>in</strong> (5) (or <strong>in</strong> any declarative sentence <strong>in</strong> languages with V <strong>in</strong> I, etc.). Given <strong>the</strong> availability<br />

of overt agreement between predicates and <strong>the</strong>ir arguments, we have evidence that functional heads<br />

must have ‘probes’ reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to argument positions <strong>the</strong>ir ‘goals’), yield<strong>in</strong>g standard m<strong>in</strong>imalist<br />

Agree – which we could use to this end. Yet Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky (2000) argues that <strong>the</strong>ta-roles are not<br />

features and <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong>ta-relations cannot be established by feature-check<strong>in</strong>g under Agree (contra<br />

Hornste<strong>in</strong> 1999, Manz<strong>in</strong>i & Roussou 2000).<br />

We take Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky’s (2000) conclusion to be correct, but we also argue that agreement is not<br />

a feature check<strong>in</strong>g relation. Consider <strong>the</strong> classical example of subject-f<strong>in</strong>ite verb agreement, say<br />

between du and –st <strong>in</strong> (5). It is a traditional idea (see <strong>the</strong> null subject parameter) that <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ite verb<br />

<strong>in</strong>flection is pronom<strong>in</strong>al(-like), hav<strong>in</strong>g all of <strong>the</strong> crucial properties of a pronoun, for <strong>in</strong>stance<br />

reference to ‘hearer’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of –st ‘2 nd sg’. If so, agreement need not <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong> deletion of<br />

un<strong>in</strong>terpretable features. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> ‘hearer’ specifications of du and –st must be attributed to <strong>the</strong><br />

same argument slot. The non-dist<strong>in</strong>ctness (i.e. agreement) of <strong>the</strong>ir referentially relevant properties<br />

(features) will simply be a consequence of this. Therefore, feature check<strong>in</strong>g is not what probe-goal<br />

relations are about. Instead, what <strong>the</strong>y are about is precisely <strong>the</strong> predicate-argument calculus, of<br />

which agreement is but a reflex.<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, saturation of <strong>the</strong>ta-roles corresponds to <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of variables (<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>taroles<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>in</strong> section 1, i.e. <strong>the</strong> ‘probes’) by arguments (i.e. <strong>the</strong> ‘goals’). Phifeature<br />

bundles, notably f<strong>in</strong>ite verb <strong>in</strong>flections, are <strong>in</strong>terpretable as <strong>the</strong> most elementary possible<br />

satisfaction of <strong>the</strong>ta-roles. In turn, <strong>the</strong> agreement relation (for <strong>in</strong>stance between a verb <strong>in</strong>flection and<br />

a DP) is part of <strong>the</strong> predicate-argument calculus, and is essentially <strong>the</strong> reverse of <strong>the</strong> movement<br />

relation. ‘Movement’ has a s<strong>in</strong>gle argument and two λ abstractions, while ‘agreement’ has a s<strong>in</strong>gle λ<br />

abstraction (i.e. <strong>the</strong>ta-role or argument slot) and two arguments (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g now <strong>in</strong>flections).<br />

A consequence of <strong>the</strong> construal of phi-feature bundles as pronom<strong>in</strong>al elements is of course<br />

<strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation of pro (both expletive and referential). Null subject languages (or person for<strong>ms</strong><br />

with<strong>in</strong> a language) are those where <strong>the</strong> word-level lexicalization provided by <strong>the</strong> verb <strong>in</strong>flection<br />

suffices for <strong>the</strong> EPP; non-null subject languages (or for<strong>ms</strong>) are those where it does not.<br />

3. Empty operators. Our proposal so far admits only of variables at <strong>the</strong> LF <strong>in</strong>terface, elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g<br />

purely syntactic (or ‘PF’) elements such as head trace and pro. In such a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>the</strong>re will of course<br />

be empty operators as well. As time allows, we will argue that some ‘functional’ categories are<br />

better understood as operators (e.g. ‘number’, cf. <strong>the</strong> discussion with<strong>in</strong> Distributed Morphology<br />

from Noyer (1992) to Harbour (2011)). Therefore ‘silent’ categories, i.e. phonologically empty<br />

lexical item <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of Kayne (2010) may prove unnecessary (<strong>the</strong> converse of <strong>the</strong> conclusion <strong>in</strong><br />

section 2 that <strong>the</strong>re are no ‘un<strong>in</strong>terpretable’ lexical entries ei<strong>the</strong>r), once <strong>the</strong> more restrictive category<br />

of empty operator is adequately def<strong>in</strong>ed.


Tania Leal Méndez & Christ<strong>in</strong>e Shea (Iowa)<br />

L1 and L2 Mexican Spanish and <strong>in</strong>formation structure: P-movement or <strong>in</strong>-situ<br />

prosody?<br />

The present experiments focus on P-movement, a Spanish structure that lies at <strong>the</strong> syntaxdiscourse<br />

<strong>in</strong>terface. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Zubizarreta (1998), <strong>the</strong> syntactic reflex of P-movement<br />

results <strong>in</strong> two word orders: VOS and [S]VPPO: (underl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g represents new <strong>in</strong>formation)<br />

Context: Who ate <strong>the</strong> apple? P-movement type 1<br />

Comió la manzana Juan. (VOS)<br />

Ate <strong>the</strong> apple Juan<br />

#Juan comió la manzana. (#SVO)<br />

Context: What did Juan put on top of <strong>the</strong> table? P-movement type 2<br />

Juan puso sobre la mesa un libro. (SVPPO)<br />

Juan put on top of <strong>the</strong> table a book.<br />

#Juan puso un libro sobre la mesa (#SVOPP)<br />

Juan put a book on top of <strong>the</strong> table<br />

Given that p-movement is a result of phonological alignment requirements, it has been<br />

argued to be prosodically motivated (Zubizarreta, 1998; but see López, 2009 for a<br />

syntactically-motivated explanation).<br />

Experiment 1 (Judgments)<br />

To test whe<strong>the</strong>r native Spanish speakers and L2 learners would <strong>the</strong> pert<strong>in</strong>ent word orders to<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formational structure (context), we used a used a bi-modal (text-audio) contextualized<br />

acceptability task, conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se context-test sentence comb<strong>in</strong>ations (all <strong>in</strong> Spanish): 12<br />

P-movement (VOS and [S]VPPO), 6—Rheme (VSO), plus 18 fillers. SVO was excluded as<br />

an option because it is a „default‟ (biased) order <strong>in</strong> Spanish. Us<strong>in</strong>g a scale (1-4 or “I don‟t<br />

know”), participants judged (<strong>in</strong>)felicity <strong>in</strong> context. Participants also completed a proficiency<br />

test (two multiple-choice sections of a standardized test). Participants (N=137) <strong>in</strong>cluded 49<br />

native speakers, 25 advanced learners, 29 <strong>in</strong>termediate, and 46 low-<strong>in</strong>termediate. All learners<br />

had English as <strong>the</strong>ir L1. Group and <strong>in</strong>dividual results <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong>se properties can be<br />

successfully acquired, although not all to <strong>the</strong> same extent (see Figures for results).<br />

Additionally, <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>the</strong> native speakers <strong>in</strong>dicate that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of P-movement 1, <strong>the</strong><br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> two word orders <strong>in</strong> context is clear, while this was not <strong>the</strong> case for Pmovement<br />

2.<br />

Experiment 2 (Production)<br />

To test whe<strong>the</strong>r native Mexican Spanish speakers (from central Mexico, Puebla State)<br />

produced this orders <strong>in</strong> context and to analyze <strong>the</strong>ir prosodic encod<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

structure, we used a contextualized forced choice production task. In a video, participants<br />

were presented with a context (a question) (8 seconds). After each question, participants<br />

viewed a short segment of a silent film (10-15 seconds). Then, participants were presented<br />

with three options to answer <strong>the</strong> question. These options differed only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> word order.<br />

Responses were audio-recorded (10 seconds). Participants <strong>in</strong>cluded a monol<strong>in</strong>gual Spanish<br />

group (n=53) all born and resid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Mexico and a bil<strong>in</strong>gual group (n=11) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual NS of<br />

Spanish who had completed a Master‟s degree <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> States and had lived <strong>in</strong> an Englishspeak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

country at least 7 years (TOEFL m<strong>in</strong>: 500). Group and <strong>in</strong>dividual results show that<br />

<strong>the</strong> preferential manner for encod<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation structure (focus) is not through syntactic<br />

means (word order) but through prosody. Spanish ToBI analyses reveal that native Mexican<br />

Spanish speakers do mark <strong>in</strong>formation focus, but not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> expected fashion. Instead, <strong>the</strong>se


speakers prefer to mark narrow focus by means of pitch accents on <strong>the</strong> narrow-focus words<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> expected syntactic movement. While Zubizarreta (1998) does not necessarily<br />

rule out this option, it is not hypo<strong>the</strong>sized to be <strong>the</strong> overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gly preferred one. While<br />

dialect-specific differences <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of how prosody and <strong>in</strong>formation structure <strong>in</strong>teract have<br />

been well-documented, <strong>the</strong> evidence presented here suggests that not only can prosody be<br />

dialect specific (Prieto & Roseano, 2010), but <strong>the</strong> syntax-prosody <strong>in</strong>terface may also manifest<br />

dialect-specific effects <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of production.<br />

Experiment 3 (Perception)<br />

To fur<strong>the</strong>r test <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that Mexican Spanish speakers prefer <strong>the</strong> prosodic option <strong>in</strong><br />

ter<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>in</strong>formation structure realization (as perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to P-movement), we used a forced<br />

choice listen<strong>in</strong>g identification task. Participants heard a sentence with ei<strong>the</strong>r narrow focus<br />

on <strong>the</strong> subject (p-movement 1, VOS, 6 sentences) or narrow focus on <strong>the</strong> object (p-movement<br />

2, [S]VPPO, 6 sentences), plus 10 fillers and had to select which question best corresponded<br />

to <strong>the</strong> sentence heard, whe<strong>the</strong>r a question focused on <strong>the</strong> subject (e.g., ¿Quién comió? Who<br />

ate?, or ¿Qué pasó? What happened?). Based upon <strong>the</strong> data from <strong>the</strong> production study cited<br />

above, we hypo<strong>the</strong>size that Mexican Spanish speakers will prefer sentences with SVO order,<br />

accompanied by prosodically-realized narrow focus on <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> response to „Who ate?‟<br />

type questions over VOS word-order. The same preference is predicted for p-movement 2.<br />

We are currently analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> data for this experiment.<br />

Discussion<br />

We present prelim<strong>in</strong>ary perception and production data suggest<strong>in</strong>g that p-movement may be a<br />

dialect-dependent manifestation of <strong>the</strong> syntax-prosody <strong>in</strong>terface, given that Mexican Spanish<br />

speakers do not seem to use it to express <strong>in</strong>formation-structure shifts. This implies that <strong>the</strong><br />

realization of <strong>the</strong> prosody-syntax <strong>in</strong>terface <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>in</strong>formation structure may need to be<br />

re-conceptualized to <strong>in</strong>corporate optional, less categorical preferences <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> grammar of<br />

native speakers.<br />

Figures<br />

Experiment 1: Acceptability Judgment averages for P-movement 1, P-movement 2<br />

Experiment 2:<br />

P-movement 1, Bil<strong>in</strong>guals P-movement 1, Monol<strong>in</strong>guals<br />

References<br />

Zubizarreta, M. L. (1998). Prosody, focus, and word order. Cambridge: MIT Press.<br />

Prieto, P., Roseano, P. (coords.) (2010). Transcription of Intonation of <strong>the</strong> Spanish Language.<br />

L<strong>in</strong>com Europa: München.


Luisa Meroni & Andrea Gualm<strong>in</strong>i (Utrecht)<br />

Do you know all SI? I know some<br />

Context –dependence of children’s computation of SIs<br />

Many experimental studies have shown that children don't compute scalar implicatures (SIs)<br />

as much as adults, despite master<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> prerequisites to <strong>the</strong>ir computation (Chierchia et al.,<br />

2000). In addition, different tasks (truth value judgment, picture‐selection or act‐out) have<br />

been shown to affect children's SIs computation, lead<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> complexity of<br />

judgment‐tasks is beyond children's limited cognitive resources (Pouscoulous et al. 2007;<br />

Katsos et el., <strong>in</strong> press). This paper presents experimental data show<strong>in</strong>g that 1) children can <strong>in</strong><br />

fact compute SIs to <strong>the</strong> same extent as adults when this is <strong>the</strong> only contextually available<br />

option (Gualm<strong>in</strong>i et al., 2008) and 2) <strong>the</strong>y do so <strong>in</strong> a typical Truth Value Judgment task (Cra<strong>in</strong><br />

& Thornton, 1998).<br />

The role of contextual <strong>in</strong>formation for SIs computation was discussed by Welker<br />

(1994) and Carston (1998), through examples (1) and (2).<br />

(1) A: I'm hav<strong>in</strong>g a d<strong>in</strong>ner party and I need six more chairs.<br />

B: John has four chairs.<br />

(2) A: I'm hav<strong>in</strong>g a d<strong>in</strong>ner party and I need four more chairs.<br />

B: John has four chairs.<br />

The contrast lies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> SI associated with <strong>the</strong> numeral four (exactly 4) is<br />

computed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first dialogue, but not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second one (see Zondervan et al., 2009). In light<br />

of <strong>the</strong>oretical and experimental evidence suggest<strong>in</strong>g that implicatures are costly (Re<strong>in</strong>hart<br />

1998, Chierchia et al. 2000, Noveck 2001 among o<strong>the</strong>rs) a plausible view is that <strong>the</strong>ir cost<br />

needs to be justified. Our proposal is that contextual relevance provides children with a reason<br />

to comply with this cost. In particular, we draw upon <strong>the</strong> question that is raised <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context,<br />

and that is usually referred to as <strong>the</strong> Question Under Discussion (QUD, Roberts 1996) that has<br />

been already shown to exert an effect on resolv<strong>in</strong>g scope ambiguities for both children and<br />

adults (see Gualm<strong>in</strong>i et al. 2008).<br />

To <strong>in</strong>vestigate whe<strong>the</strong>r children compute <strong>the</strong> SI associated with some (some but not<br />

all), when presented with <strong>the</strong> appropriate QUD, we tested children with a Truth Value<br />

Judgment task. In a typical Truth Value Judgment task experiment, children listen to stories<br />

with a puppet and have to evaluate what <strong>the</strong> puppet says relatively to <strong>the</strong> story <strong>the</strong>y just heard.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce we wanted to study <strong>the</strong> effect of an explicit QUD on children's computation of SIs,<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> design by Zondervan et al. (2009), we elicited <strong>the</strong> target question from <strong>the</strong><br />

puppet by overtly ask<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relevant QUD. The target question <strong>the</strong>n had to be evaluated by<br />

<strong>the</strong> subjects relatively to <strong>the</strong> story <strong>the</strong>y had just heard.<br />

To illustrate, children heard sentences like 3) I th<strong>in</strong>k some hotdogs were delivered as a<br />

description of a story <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> relevant character delivered all <strong>the</strong> hot‐dogs. As <strong>in</strong><br />

Zondervan et al. (2009), <strong>the</strong> target sentence (3) was presented as an answer to two different<br />

questions (4a or 4b), depend<strong>in</strong>g on which condition children had been assigned to:<br />

4) a. Were some hot‐dogs delivered? Condition1<br />

b. Were all <strong>the</strong> hot‐dogs delivered? Condition2<br />

Thirty English-speak<strong>in</strong>g children participated <strong>in</strong> this experiment, rang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> age from 3;8 to<br />

6;5 (Mean = 4;10). We used a between-subject design where 15 children were presented with<br />

<strong>the</strong> question under discussion <strong>in</strong> 4a (Mean = 5;1) and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r 15 children with <strong>the</strong> question<br />

<strong>in</strong> 4b (Mean = 4;8). Each child saw four target trials <strong>in</strong>terspersed with fillers to balance <strong>the</strong><br />

expected number of yes and no answers.


We predicted that <strong>the</strong> implicature calculation would be affected by <strong>the</strong> contextually<br />

available question. Thus, subjects should calculate <strong>the</strong> SI ‐ and reject (3) ‐ when asked to<br />

evaluate (3) as an answer to <strong>the</strong> QUD <strong>in</strong> (4b), but not when (3) was presented as an answer to<br />

(4a). The reason is that both read<strong>in</strong>gs of (3), with or without SI, answer <strong>the</strong> QUD; thus a<br />

different criterion needs to be <strong>in</strong>voked to select one read<strong>in</strong>g (for <strong>in</strong>stance, computational<br />

complexity or <strong>the</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Charity, both lead<strong>in</strong>g to an affirmative answer). Differently,<br />

without <strong>the</strong> relevant implicature, (3) is not a good answer to (4b) (Gualm<strong>in</strong>i et al., 2008).<br />

Subjects should thus be led to consider whe<strong>the</strong>r an alternative <strong>in</strong>terpretation can be found that<br />

answers <strong>the</strong> QUD, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relevant SI fits <strong>the</strong> bill. The results<br />

confirmed our prediction. Children accepted <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>in</strong> (3) 85 % of <strong>the</strong> time, when this<br />

was preceded by question (4a), but <strong>the</strong>ir acceptance dropped to 13% when (3) followed (4b),<br />

exactly like <strong>the</strong> English speak<strong>in</strong>g adults tested by Zondervan et al. (2009). Children were also<br />

asked to motivate <strong>the</strong>ir negative answers to ensure <strong>the</strong>y were <strong>in</strong>deed comput<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> SI when<br />

reject<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> puppets' statement.<br />

To evaluate if children's computation of SI <strong>in</strong> Condition 2 was due to <strong>the</strong> mere<br />

presence of <strong>the</strong> quantifier all <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> QUD, a control experiment was conducted. To this end,<br />

we slightly changed <strong>the</strong> QUD, as exemplified <strong>in</strong> Error! Reference source not found.:<br />

(5) Control Condition<br />

a. QUD: Were all <strong>the</strong> hot-dogs delivered?<br />

b. Target Sentence: I th<strong>in</strong>k some pizza were delivered<br />

As one can see, <strong>the</strong> QUD still conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> quantifier all but this time it revolves around hotdogs<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> pizzas. To make <strong>the</strong> question contextually felicitous, <strong>the</strong> story also<br />

<strong>in</strong>cluded some hot-dogs. A third group of 15 English-speak<strong>in</strong>g children participated <strong>in</strong> this<br />

experiment. Age was from 4;3 to 6;0 (Mean = 5;1). Each child was presented with 4 target<br />

trials <strong>in</strong>terspersed with fillers. Turn<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> results, <strong>the</strong> fifteen children <strong>in</strong>terviewed<br />

computed <strong>the</strong> SI associated with (5b) only 10% of <strong>the</strong> time. Children did not compute <strong>the</strong> SI<br />

associated with <strong>the</strong> quantifier some despite <strong>the</strong> occurrence of <strong>the</strong> stronger term all <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> QUD<br />

allow<strong>in</strong>g us to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> computation of <strong>the</strong> SI <strong>in</strong> Experiment 1 can be<br />

attributed to <strong>the</strong> QUD ra<strong>the</strong>r than to some prim<strong>in</strong>g effect. In particular, children were not<br />

concerned with <strong>the</strong> change of focus implied by <strong>the</strong> target sentence and accepted <strong>the</strong> target<br />

sentence.<br />

Our f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs show that once <strong>the</strong> question under discussion is explicitly given nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

developmental nor methodological differences emerge. Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g<br />

literature, our results show that one contextual property, that of <strong>the</strong> QUD, can account for<br />

participants’ preferences on two apparently dist<strong>in</strong>ct phenomena: scope ambiguities and scalar<br />

implicatures. This result is an important step <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process of understand<strong>in</strong>g how context<br />

drives <strong>in</strong>terpretation


The L<strong>in</strong>guistic Expression of Causation<br />

Ad Neeleman & Hans van de Koot (UCL)<br />

1. The mental representation of causal relations The most common def<strong>in</strong>ition of causation<br />

has three components (Lewis 1973): (i) it is a relation between a caus<strong>in</strong>g and a caused event,<br />

such that (ii) <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event may not follow <strong>the</strong> caused event and (iii) if <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event<br />

had not occurred <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event would not have occurred ei<strong>the</strong>r. There is ample evidence<br />

that causation is primarily a tool humans use for structur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir mental model of <strong>the</strong> world<br />

(Johnson-Laird 1983, 2006). Causation cannot be l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong> nature, as it can be present <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> absence of language (Call 2004, Varley & Siegel 2002, Leslie 1984). The central question<br />

for l<strong>in</strong>guists, <strong>the</strong>n, is how <strong>the</strong> psychological notion of causation is expressed l<strong>in</strong>guistically.<br />

We propose that causative verbs do not encode a caus<strong>in</strong>g event. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y encode a<br />

macro-event, a resultant state, and <strong>the</strong> Crucial Contribut<strong>in</strong>g Factor (CCF) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g about<br />

of <strong>the</strong> matrix event. The CCF is realized as <strong>the</strong> external argument (Re<strong>in</strong>hart 2002) and<br />

identifies which factor, out of a range of potential factors contribut<strong>in</strong>g to an outcome, is<br />

deemed by <strong>the</strong> speaker not to fall <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ceteris paribus category. As causal cha<strong>in</strong>s can be<br />

quite complex, <strong>the</strong>re are few <strong>in</strong>herent restrictions on what can function as a CCF, expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> variation of x <strong>in</strong> x eventually killed Leo (e.g. whisky, Bill, or <strong>the</strong> distance to <strong>the</strong> nearest<br />

oasis). Our proposal does not imply that language cannot express caus<strong>in</strong>g events. But when<br />

<strong>the</strong>se are expressed, this is not done through <strong>the</strong> verb, but ra<strong>the</strong>r through an adjunct, as <strong>in</strong><br />

Little Orson grew <strong>in</strong>to a big man [by eat<strong>in</strong>g Irish Oatmeal], where grow is an anticausative.<br />

2. The paradox of direct causation The standard view is that <strong>the</strong> lexical semantics of a<br />

causative verb conta<strong>in</strong>s a caus<strong>in</strong>g event. Whisky eventually killed Leo is <strong>the</strong>n taken to mean<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re is an event <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g whisky, such that it caused Leo’s death. The well-known<br />

Restriction to Direct Causation <strong>in</strong> simplex causatives (RDC) can be construed as evidence for<br />

this view, as formulat<strong>in</strong>g it requires reference to caus<strong>in</strong>g events. It follows that our proposal is<br />

falsified if <strong>the</strong> RDC is correct. However, evidence for <strong>the</strong> RDC is surpris<strong>in</strong>gly weak.<br />

The ma<strong>in</strong> source of evidence for <strong>the</strong> RDC consists of what we will call Katz effects (Katz<br />

1970): <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of (1), (2a) is accepted by all speakers, but (2b) is not.<br />

(1) A sheriff’s six-shooter is faultily repaired by <strong>the</strong> local gunsmith. As a result, his<br />

weapon ja<strong>ms</strong> at a critical moment and <strong>the</strong> sheriff is gunned down.<br />

(2) a. The gunsmith caused <strong>the</strong> sheriff to die.<br />

b. The gunsmith killed <strong>the</strong> sheriff.<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>in</strong> (1) is undoubtedly real, <strong>the</strong>re are many examples <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> RDC is<br />

violated. For <strong>in</strong>stance, a 1943 Duke Ell<strong>in</strong>gton song entitled A slip of <strong>the</strong> lip can s<strong>in</strong>k a ship<br />

describes a situation <strong>in</strong> which loose talk by sailors may allow a spy to obta<strong>in</strong> and transmit<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation that may <strong>in</strong> turn allow a foreign navy to <strong>in</strong>struct its submar<strong>in</strong>es to torpedo and<br />

s<strong>in</strong>k ships <strong>in</strong> a convoy. We conclude from examples of this type that <strong>the</strong> RDC is <strong>in</strong>correct and<br />

must <strong>the</strong>refore be attributed to <strong>in</strong>dependent factors. We discuss <strong>the</strong>se factors below.<br />

Adverbial modification is sometimes claimed to provide fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence for <strong>the</strong> RDC (see<br />

Fodor 1970 for related discussion). We will show that this claim is <strong>in</strong>correct.<br />

3. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Katz effects The basis for our analysis of Katz effects is <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that<br />

language encodes accountability for outcome through <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>in</strong> (3), where [+m] is a feature<br />

borrowed from Re<strong>in</strong>hart 2002 that expresses that <strong>the</strong> referent of an argument has a m<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

(3) Accountability: The referent of a DP specified as [+m] is held accountable for <strong>the</strong><br />

action expressed by <strong>the</strong> verb if and only if it is <strong>the</strong> CCF argument of that verb.<br />

Accountability only plays a role when a causative verb takes a [+m] subject and is <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

<strong>in</strong>applicable to <strong>the</strong> slip of <strong>the</strong> lip example, expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> absence of a Katz effect. The<br />

awkwardness of (2b) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of (1) also follows, because (1) does not <strong>in</strong>vite <strong>the</strong> reader<br />

to hold <strong>the</strong> gunsmith responsible for <strong>the</strong> sheriff’s death. But tweaks of <strong>the</strong> scenario improve<br />

examples like (2b). Suppose that follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> demise of <strong>the</strong> sheriff, <strong>the</strong> gunsmith visits a


psychoanalyst because he is struggl<strong>in</strong>g with feel<strong>in</strong>gs of guilt. He might <strong>the</strong>n say I killed <strong>the</strong><br />

sheriff, mean<strong>in</strong>g that he holds hi<strong>ms</strong>elf responsible. Notice that <strong>the</strong> RDC makes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>correct<br />

prediction that <strong>the</strong> gunsmith would under such circu<strong>ms</strong>tances know<strong>in</strong>gly utter a falsity.<br />

Katz effects also disappear if <strong>the</strong> gunsmith sabotages <strong>the</strong> sheriff’s gun because he has a<br />

long-stand<strong>in</strong>g grudge aga<strong>in</strong>st him. In such a scenario, (2b) is unobjectionable (Wolff 2003).<br />

In fact it can be shown that accountability assignment is subject to a locality condition<br />

stated over causal relations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mental model. In particular, ascription of accountability<br />

across participants of an <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g event <strong>in</strong> a causal cha<strong>in</strong> is forbidden, unless <strong>the</strong>ir actions<br />

fall <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ceteris paribus category. Thus, (2b) becomes unacceptable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extended sabotage<br />

scenario if we <strong>in</strong>troduce an <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g agent whose decisions are presented as crucial to <strong>the</strong><br />

outcome. This locality effect confir<strong>ms</strong> that accountability assignment is real.<br />

Why is cause to die different from kill? In <strong>the</strong> case of kill, a [+m] CCF is accountable for<br />

<strong>the</strong> entire macro-event encoded by <strong>the</strong> verb, which <strong>in</strong>cludes <strong>the</strong> resultant state. In <strong>the</strong> case of<br />

cause to die, <strong>the</strong> accountability of a [+m] CCF is limited to <strong>the</strong> causation event (<strong>the</strong><br />

circu<strong>ms</strong>tances lead<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> sheriff’s death) – it excludes <strong>the</strong> resultant state (<strong>the</strong> death itself)<br />

because that state is <strong>in</strong>troduced by a separate predicate.<br />

The above is sufficient to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects that <strong>in</strong>itially motivated <strong>the</strong> RDC. However, we<br />

discuss additional factors <strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g Katz effects, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> lexical encod<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>struments<br />

(The gunsmith shot <strong>the</strong> sheriff is <strong>in</strong>felicitous <strong>in</strong> all contexts mentioned above).<br />

4. Test<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> presence of a caus<strong>in</strong>g event We close our presentation with a discussion<br />

of proposals that assume that <strong>the</strong> lexical semantics of causative verbs conta<strong>in</strong>s a caus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

event. Strik<strong>in</strong>gly, even <strong>in</strong> generative semantics <strong>the</strong>re was no syntactic position for such an<br />

event. Instead, <strong>the</strong> standard assumption was (and is) that <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event is encoded as part<br />

of <strong>the</strong> semantics of <strong>the</strong> CAUSE predicate (compare Dowty 1979). Similar ideas can be found <strong>in</strong><br />

Hale & Keyser 1993, Ramchand 2008, and Pylkkänen 2008. What is <strong>the</strong> evidence for this<br />

representation of <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event?<br />

Consider first <strong>the</strong> claim that eventive subjects of causative verbs denote <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event.<br />

This claim must be <strong>in</strong>correct, <strong>in</strong> view of examples like (4), where <strong>the</strong> relevant event follows<br />

<strong>the</strong> caused event. This is unproblematic if <strong>the</strong> eventive subject is a CCF, because <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

event <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mental model can <strong>the</strong>n be people act<strong>in</strong>g on knowledge of a future event.<br />

(4) Tomorrow’s strike by London Underground staff caused mayhem on <strong>the</strong> North<br />

Circular Road dur<strong>in</strong>g this even<strong>in</strong>g’s rush hour.<br />

A second potential argument could be based on semantic restrictions on <strong>the</strong> subject. These<br />

could result from lexical specification of <strong>the</strong> putative caus<strong>in</strong>g event. However, although all<br />

lexical causatives express restrictions on <strong>the</strong> caused event (kill means ‘cause to die’), it is<br />

certa<strong>in</strong>ly not true <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> general case that <strong>the</strong>y impose restrictions on <strong>the</strong> caus<strong>in</strong>g event. At<br />

least, <strong>the</strong>re is no necessary restriction on <strong>the</strong> choice of subject. As already mentioned, a very<br />

wide variety of elements that can replace x <strong>in</strong> x eventually killed Leo.<br />

Two fur<strong>the</strong>r arguments for caus<strong>in</strong>g events <strong>in</strong> lexical semantics are presented by Pylkkänen<br />

(2008), who argues, on <strong>the</strong> basis Japanese and F<strong>in</strong>nish, that a caus<strong>in</strong>g event can be present,<br />

even if no associated external argument is <strong>in</strong>troduced. In <strong>the</strong> Japanese case, <strong>the</strong> claim is that<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> adjuncts are excluded <strong>in</strong> anticausative contexts but permitted <strong>in</strong> adversity<br />

constructions, where <strong>the</strong>y are licensed by a hidden caus<strong>in</strong>g event. We show that this argument<br />

is based on an <strong>in</strong>correct premise, as <strong>the</strong> relevant type of modifier does <strong>in</strong> fact show up with<br />

anticausatives. In <strong>the</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish case, sluic<strong>in</strong>g is claimed to identify a hidden caus<strong>in</strong>g event <strong>in</strong><br />

desiderative constructions. This analysis makes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>correct prediction that <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

sluic<strong>in</strong>g should also be possible <strong>in</strong> uncontroversially causative constructions, contrary to fact.<br />

5. Conclusions Causative verbs do not encode a caus<strong>in</strong>g event. This is because subjects of<br />

causative verbs express a CCF (which is associated with accountability when [+m]). If<br />

expressed at all, caus<strong>in</strong>g events surface as adjuncts.


��������� ���������� ������� �� ������� �� ������<br />

����� ������ ������ ���� �� ������ ����������� ����� ���� ������� ��� ������ ���<br />

��������� �� ������ ��������� �� ������ ����� �� ��������� ����������� �� ��������<br />

�������� �� ��� ���� ������� ���� ��� ��������������� �� ������� ������ ���������� ���<br />

�� ��������� �� ���������������� �������� ���� �� ���������� ���������� ����������� ���<br />

���� ����� ��� �������� ��� ��������� �� ���� �������� �� ���� ��� ��������������� ��<br />

��������� �� ������� ���� ����� ������������� �� ��� ������ ����������<br />

��� ��� �� ���� ���� �� �� ����������� ������� ���������� ������� ����� �� ����� ������<br />

��� ������������ ��� ������������ ��� ������� ��� ��� ��������������� �� ������� ��<br />

������ ���������� �� ������� ��������� ���� ����������� ���� ���������� ������� �� ���<br />

������� ��� ��� �������� ������� �� ��� ������� ����<br />

��� ����� �� ���������� � ������������ ���� ��� ���������� ���� �� �������������<br />

���������� ���� ��� ���������� �� ��������� ������������� �� �������� �� � ������ �� ������<br />

������� �������� �������� ������� ��� ����������� �� ��������� �� � ������� ��� �� ���������<br />

���� ��� ������� ���� ����������� ���������� ����� ��� ���� ���� ����� �� �������� ���<br />

����������� ��� ������ ������� ���� �� ��� ��������� ���� �� ����� ��� ������������ ���������<br />

����� ��� �� ���� ����� ��� �������� ��� �������������������� ����������� ������� ��� ���<br />

���� �� ��������� �� ����� ��� ����� ����������� ��� � ���������� ������� ����������<br />

����������� ��� ������� �� ��� ������������� ����� �� ������<br />

���������� � ����� ���� ��������� �������� ��� ������������� ��������� �� ���������<br />

���� ����� ����������� �������� ���� ������������ ���� ��� ���� ��� ��������� �����<br />

����������� � ������� ���� ��������� ���� ����� ���������� ��� �������� ����������<br />

������� ������ ��������� ������� ��� �������� ���������� ��� ���� ������ ���������� ����<br />

��� �������� ��������������� �������� ����� ������� ������ ���� ��� ���� ���� ��� �����<br />

����������� �� ����� ���������� �� ���� ��� �� ����� ��� ���������� ������������<br />

��� ��� � �� ����� ���� �� ������� ����� ���� � ���������<br />

���� ����� �������� ��� ��� ���� ���� �� ��� � �� ����<br />

��������<br />

���� �����<br />

���� ��� ����� ������ ��� ���� ���� �� ��� � ���� ����� ������ �<br />

������������ ����������<br />

��� �� ���� ����� ����� ���� �� ������� ����� ���� �<br />

����� ����� ����� �������� ��� ��� ���� ���� �� ��� �<br />

��������� ��������<br />

�� ���� ���� �����<br />

����� ����� ��� ����� ������ ��� ���� ���� �� ��� � ���� ����� ������ �<br />

�������� ����������<br />

���������� � ����� �� ���������� ����� ��� ��������� �� ����� �������� ���������� ����<br />

����� ���������� ��� ��� ����������� �� ���������� ��������<br />

��� ��� � ��<br />

����<br />

������<br />

������<br />

�����<br />

���<br />

��<br />

���<br />

�����<br />

��� ���<br />

��������<br />

���� ����<br />

�<br />

�<br />

������<br />

������<br />

���� ��� ������ ���� ��� ��� ���� ���� � ���� ����� ������ �<br />

������������ ����������<br />

��� � ����<br />

�����<br />

�������<br />

���<br />

Bruno Nicemboim (Potsdam)<br />

������<br />

������<br />

�����<br />

���<br />

�<br />

��<br />

���<br />

�����<br />

��� ���<br />

��������<br />

���� ����<br />

�������<br />

�����<br />

�<br />

�<br />

������<br />

������


�������<br />

�����<br />

����� ��� ��� ������ ���� ��� ��� ���� ���� � ���� ����� ������ �<br />

�������� ����������<br />

���������� � ������� ���� ��������� ����������� ��� ���������� �� ��������� ������������ ��<br />

��������� ���� ����� ����������� �������� �� ����������� ������� ������������� �����<br />

����� ��� ������� ����� ��� ������ ���� ������ ������� �� ���������� � ���� ����<br />

��������� ���� ��� ������� ��� ������������� �� �������� ��������� ���� ����� ������<br />

����� �� ��� ����� �� ��� ����������� ��������� ��� ��� ������� �� ��� �������� ��������<br />

��� ��������� ���� ������ ��� ��� �������� ��������� ���� ����� ���������� ���� ��� ���<br />

��������� ���� �������� ���� ��� ���������� �� ��������� ������������ �� ����������� ��<br />

����� ������� ����� �� ��� ���������� ���� ��� ���� ���� ����������� �� ��� ���������<br />

��������� ���������� �� ��� ��������� ������������ ������� ��� ����������� ��� �����<br />

��������� �������<br />

��������� ��� ������� ���� ����������� � ��� � �������� ����� ���� ����� ���<br />

����� ��� ��� ���� �������� ��������� ��� � ����� ���� ��� ��������������� �� �����<br />

���������� �� ��� �� ����� �����������������<br />

��������� ����� ����������� ����� �� � ����� �������� �� ���������� �� ��� ���� ��<br />

��� ������ ���������� ���� ����� ���������� ��� ������� �� ���������� ������� �������� ����<br />

������ ��������� ������������ ������ � ������ �� ��� ������ ��� ����� ��� �������������<br />

�� ��������� ���� ����� ����������� ���� ���� ���� ��� ����������� ��������� ����������<br />

������ ��������� ��� ������ ���������� �� ��������� ������������ �� ����� ���������� ���<br />

�� ���� ������ ���� �� ����������� ��������� ����� ������� ����������� ���� �������� ����<br />

��� ���������� �� ��������� ������������ �� ��������� �� ��� ��������������� �� �����<br />

�����������<br />

����������<br />

����������� �� ��� ���� �� �� ������� ��������� ����������� ��� ������ ������� ���������<br />

���<br />

��������� �� ������� �� ��� ����������� ������� ������ ��� ���� �������� � ����������<br />

������������ ������ ��� ���������� ����� ��������<br />

��������� �� ������� ����������� �������� ��� ����������� �������� ��� ��������������<br />

�� ���� ������������ ����� �������<br />

����� �� ������� ����������� �� ��������� �� ������� ��� ������� ����<br />

���� �� ��� ����������� ��� ��� ������� �� ������� ���������� ���������� �� ����������<br />

����������� ��� ������� ���� ������ ����������� �� ����������� ���� ��� ������ �������<br />

�� ��� ������� ���������� �������� ������ ��� ����� �������� ���� ���� ��������<br />

�������� �� ������� � ������� ��� ������������ ������� ������� ����� ��� ���������� ��<br />

�������� �������������<br />


Leticia Pablos, Bobby Ruijgrok, Jenny Doetjes & Lisa Cheng (Leiden)<br />

Process<strong>in</strong>g cataphoric pronouns <strong>in</strong> Dutch: an ERP study<br />

The process<strong>in</strong>g of cataphoric pronouns has been shown to follow <strong>the</strong> same mechanis<strong>ms</strong> as<br />

<strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of wh-dependencies <strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong> parser actively searches [1] for an antecedent to<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> pronoun with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence, except <strong>in</strong> those cases where <strong>the</strong> pronoun must obey<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory and cannot be c-commanded by <strong>the</strong> antecedent [2]. This is <strong>the</strong><br />

case for <strong>the</strong> Gender Mismatch (GMM) effect, named after a slowdown effect that shows that <strong>the</strong><br />

parser tries to l<strong>in</strong>k an antecedent to a preced<strong>in</strong>g pronoun only when a pronoun can be bound by it<br />

[3,4]. Most of <strong>the</strong> studies that tested whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is an active search triggered for an antecedent<br />

after encounter<strong>in</strong>g cataphoric pronouns used behavioral techniques such as self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

eye-track<strong>in</strong>g [5,6] and only a few used <strong>the</strong> electroencephalography (EEG) technique [7].<br />

The current study on Dutch uses Event Related Potentials (ERP) to exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

process<strong>in</strong>g of sentences with cataphoric pronouns as <strong>the</strong> parser looks for an antecedent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

upcom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>put. If <strong>the</strong> parser attempts to b<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> pronouns zijn and haar <strong>in</strong> (1a) and (1b) to <strong>the</strong><br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e antecedent Lodewijk, we expect a GMM effect at <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> potential<br />

antecedent <strong>in</strong> (1b). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, if <strong>the</strong> parser respects Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong><br />

(1c) and (1d), we do not expect to f<strong>in</strong>d any ERP difference at <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> potential<br />

antecedent Lodewijk show<strong>in</strong>g that no l<strong>in</strong>k has tried to be made between <strong>the</strong> pronouns hij and zij<br />

and <strong>the</strong> antecedent. Additional proper nouns such as Mirjam and Thomas <strong>in</strong> (1) were <strong>in</strong>cluded to<br />

guarantee that all pronouns had an antecedent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

(1) No constra<strong>in</strong>t match<br />

a. Zijnj assistenten kwamen erachter dat Lodewijkj Boer geen prijsw<strong>in</strong>naar<br />

His assistants realized that Lodewijkmasc Boer no prizew<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

Geselecteerd had, maar Mirjami had geen <strong>in</strong>teresse <strong>in</strong> de roddel.<br />

Selected had but Mirjamfem had no <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gossip.<br />

No constra<strong>in</strong>t mismatch<br />

b. Haari assistenten kwamen erachter dat Lodewijkj Boer geen prijsw<strong>in</strong>naar<br />

Her assistants realized that Lodewijkmasc Boer no prizew<strong>in</strong>ner,<br />

geselecteerd had, maar Mirjami had geen <strong>in</strong>teresse <strong>in</strong> de roddel.<br />

selected had, but Mirjamfem had no <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gossip.<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C match<br />

c. Hiji kwam erachter dat Lodewijkj Boer geen prijsw<strong>in</strong>naar<br />

He realized that Lodewijkmasc Boer no prize w<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

geselecteerd had, maar Thomasi had geen <strong>in</strong>teresse <strong>in</strong> de roddel.<br />

selected had, but Thomasmasc had no <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gossip.<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C mismatch<br />

d. Ziji kwam erachter dat Lodewijkj Boer geen prijsw<strong>in</strong>naar<br />

She realized that Lodewijkmasc Boer no prize w<strong>in</strong>ner,<br />

geselecteerd had, maar Mirjami had geen <strong>in</strong>teresse <strong>in</strong> de roddel.<br />

selected had, but Mirjamfem had no <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gossip.


We conducted an ERP experiment where EEG was cont<strong>in</strong>uously recorded while native<br />

speakers (n=24) of Dutch read silently 36 sentences such as (1a-d) <strong>in</strong>terspersed with 35 fillers<br />

and subsequently answered a comprehension question for every sentence. As illustrated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

accompany<strong>in</strong>g leftmost figure, results show that <strong>the</strong>re is a central anterior negativity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 200-<br />

600<strong>ms</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dow <strong>in</strong> (1b) condition with respect to (1a) at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>the</strong> potential antecedent<br />

Lodewijk (significant 3-way <strong>in</strong>teraction between factors Condition, Hemisphere (left, Right,<br />

Central) and electrode position (Anterior, Middle, Posterior); F(12,276)=2,05, p=0.045)). On <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r hand, comparison between conditions (1c) and (1d) yielded no significant difference <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

ERP wavefor<strong>ms</strong> as shown <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rightmost figure.<br />

Amplitude (μV)<br />

-10<br />

-5<br />

0<br />

GMM Exp - Condition A vs. B at "Lodewijk" - Electrode Fz<br />

5<br />

10<br />

A<br />

B<br />

-100 0 100 200 300 400 500 600 700 800<br />

Time (<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

Amplitude (μV)<br />

-10<br />

-5<br />

0<br />

Time (<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

GMM Exp - Condition C vs. D at "Lodewijk" - Electrode Fz<br />

5<br />

10<br />

C<br />

D<br />

-100 0 100 200 300 400 500 600 700 800<br />

Time (<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

The long susta<strong>in</strong>ed negativity generated at <strong>the</strong> antecedent Lodewijk for (1b) condition<br />

suggests that <strong>the</strong> parser attempts to l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> antecedent to <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g pronoun haar and fails to<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret it at <strong>the</strong> antecedent due to <strong>the</strong> gender mismatch between <strong>the</strong> pronoun -marked for<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender - and <strong>the</strong> antecedent Lodewijk – a name <strong>in</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender. The same effect is<br />

absent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r conditions, which shows that <strong>the</strong> parser does not try to l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

with <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g pronoun <strong>in</strong> (1c) and (1d) so that pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C is respected. Overall results<br />

confirm <strong>the</strong> active search mechanism for an antecedent started whenever <strong>the</strong>re is a pronoun that<br />

must be bound <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> local context as <strong>in</strong> (1b). We discuss implications of <strong>the</strong>se results <strong>in</strong> light of<br />

<strong>the</strong> accumulated knowledge on long-distance dependency process<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

References:<br />

[1] Clifton, C, & Frazier, L. (1989). Comprehend<strong>in</strong>g sentences with long distance dependencies.<br />

In Carlson, G.N. & Tanenhaus, M. eds., L<strong>in</strong>guistic Structure <strong>in</strong> Language Process<strong>in</strong>g, 273-317.<br />

[2] Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. 1981. Lectures on Government and B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, Dordrecht: Foris Publications.<br />

[3]Van Gompel, R.P.G., & Liversedge, S.P. (2003). The <strong>in</strong>fluence of morphological <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

on cataphoric pronoun assignment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learn<strong>in</strong>g, Memory,<br />

and Cognition, 29, 128-139.<br />

[4] Kazan<strong>in</strong>a, N., Lau, E., Lieberman, M., Yoshida, M., & Phillips, C. (2007). The Effect of<br />

Syntactic Constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> Process<strong>in</strong>g of Backwards Anaphora. Journal of Memory and<br />

Language, 56, 384–409.<br />

[5] Sturt, P. (2003). The time-course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> reference<br />

resolution. Journal of Memory and Language, 48, 542-562.<br />

[6] Aoshima, S. , Yoshida, M. & C.Phillips (2009). Incremental Process<strong>in</strong>g of Coreference and<br />

B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Japanese. Syntax, 12, 93-134.<br />

[7] Kre<strong>in</strong>er, H. Mohr, S. Kessler, K. and S. Garrod. (2008) Can context affect gender process<strong>in</strong>g?<br />

ERP Evidence about differences between lexical and stereotypical gender. Poster presented at<br />

Bra<strong>in</strong> Talk, Lund.


Daniel Parker & Sol Lago (Maryland)<br />

Retrieval Interference <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Resolution of Anaphoric PRO<br />

Recent research on <strong>the</strong> memory operations used <strong>in</strong> real-time language comprehension<br />

has revealed a selective profile for retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference effects. Dependencies such as<br />

subject-verb agreement show strong facilitatory <strong>in</strong>terference effects, as predicted by misretrieval<br />

due to partial cue-match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a content-addressable memory architecture [1,2]. On<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, previous studies of reflexive anaphors have not found facilitation effects.<br />

They have ei<strong>the</strong>r found no effects of structurally <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents [3,4,5,6], or <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have found <strong>in</strong>hibition effects [3,7,8], which are not directly predicted by <strong>the</strong> cue-based<br />

retrieval model. This profile has been taken to suggest <strong>the</strong> use of different retrieval<br />

mechanis<strong>ms</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two cases, despite superficially similar structural and morphological<br />

requirements [5]. The reasons for this contrast rema<strong>in</strong> unresolved. The contrast may reflect<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that anaphoric dependencies are <strong>in</strong>terpreted whereas agreement is not. Or it may<br />

reflect differential use of non-structural features as retrieval cues. The licens<strong>in</strong>g of anaphoric<br />

PRO provides a good test of <strong>the</strong> candidate retrieval mechanis<strong>ms</strong> because it shares properties<br />

with both agreement and reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. Results from three studies us<strong>in</strong>g off-l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

judgments, computational model<strong>in</strong>g and self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g confirm <strong>the</strong> structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

on licens<strong>in</strong>g PRO, but show an on-l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>terference profile similar to agreement, suggest<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> use of non-structural cues for retriev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> antecedent of PRO. These results provide <strong>the</strong><br />

first case of facilitatory <strong>in</strong>terference effects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> resolution of anaphoric dependencies.<br />

The licens<strong>in</strong>g of PRO <strong>in</strong> adjunct clauses is subject to structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts. The<br />

controller must be <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> next higher clause (1).<br />

1a. Johni read <strong>the</strong> report after PROi dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g his coffee.<br />

1b. *The report confused Johni after PROi dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g his coffee.<br />

This constra<strong>in</strong>t and <strong>the</strong> anaphoric nature of <strong>the</strong> dependency both suggest that retrieval might<br />

proceed <strong>in</strong> a structure-sensitive fashion, similar to reflexive licens<strong>in</strong>g. Conversely, <strong>the</strong> search<br />

for a controller shares at least two properties with subject-verb agreement. First, onl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

detection of PRO and subsequent retrieval of <strong>the</strong> controller is triggered by a verb ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

by an <strong>in</strong>dependent anaphoric element. Second, selectional restrictions from <strong>the</strong> gerundive<br />

verb <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> control clause (e.g. it may show a bias for a [+animate] subject) may provide<br />

additional retrieval cues. Previous studies of agreement have shown strong facilitatory<br />

<strong>in</strong>terference effects, attributed to fallible cue-based retrieval mechanis<strong>ms</strong> (e.g. [2]). If PRO<br />

behaves similarly to agreement, <strong>the</strong>n we should f<strong>in</strong>d evidence of facilitatory <strong>in</strong>terference<br />

from structurally <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents, due to partial cue-match<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

We compared <strong>the</strong> profiles of subject-verb agreement and adjunct control <strong>in</strong> a design<br />

with 8 conditions, us<strong>in</strong>g 48 sets of sentences like those <strong>in</strong> (2). Conditions (2a-d) provided a<br />

basic profile for agreement <strong>in</strong>terference. The ma<strong>in</strong> clause subject NP ei<strong>the</strong>r agreed (2a/b) or<br />

disagreed (2c/d) with <strong>the</strong> highlighted verb, and we manipulated <strong>the</strong> number of an <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g<br />

relative clause subject (‘attractor’) to ei<strong>the</strong>r match or mismatch <strong>the</strong> critical verb. This allowed<br />

us to test for <strong>the</strong> ‘illusions of grammaticality’ observed <strong>in</strong> previous studies. Conditions (2e-h)<br />

were designed to test <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of anaphoric PRO us<strong>in</strong>g maximally similar<br />

configurations to (2a-d). We <strong>in</strong>dependently manipulated <strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> clause<br />

subject (correct controller) and <strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> relative clause subject (<strong>in</strong>correct<br />

controller). The <strong>in</strong>animate NPs were chosen such that <strong>the</strong>y could be <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

verb <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> control clause, although <strong>the</strong>y might be dispreferred due to an animacy bias. An<br />

emphatic reflexive requir<strong>in</strong>g an animate, gender match<strong>in</strong>g NP antecedent as <strong>the</strong> local subject<br />

(PRO) served as a probe to determ<strong>in</strong>e whe<strong>the</strong>r an animate NP was retrieved as <strong>the</strong> subject of<br />

<strong>the</strong> adjunct clause.<br />

1


2a/b: The doctor that <strong>the</strong> {researcher/reports} evaluated extensively was commended [after<br />

PRO disprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> controversial <strong>the</strong>ory at <strong>the</strong> research <strong>in</strong>stitute <strong>in</strong> Europe].<br />

2c/d: The experiment that <strong>the</strong> {researchers/report} evaluated extensively were commended<br />

[after PRO disprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> controversial <strong>the</strong>ory at <strong>the</strong> research <strong>in</strong>stitute <strong>in</strong> Europe].<br />

2e/f: The doctor that <strong>the</strong> {researcher/report} evaluated extensively was commended [after<br />

PRO disprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> controversial <strong>the</strong>ory hi<strong>ms</strong>elf at <strong>the</strong> research <strong>in</strong>stitute <strong>in</strong> Europe].<br />

2g/h: The experiment that <strong>the</strong> {researcher/report} evaluated extensively was commended<br />

[after PRO disprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> controversial <strong>the</strong>ory hi<strong>ms</strong>elf at <strong>the</strong> research <strong>in</strong>stitute <strong>in</strong><br />

Europe].<br />

Experiment 1 (off-l<strong>in</strong>e acceptability judgment, n=24) confirmed that PRO <strong>in</strong> an<br />

adjunct clause must be controlled by <strong>the</strong> next higher subject. Experiment 2 (computational<br />

model<strong>in</strong>g) used <strong>the</strong> ACT-R parser to establish predictions from a cue-based retrieval <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

The simulations predict facilitatory <strong>in</strong>terference effects for both <strong>the</strong> agreement conditions<br />

(2a-d) and <strong>the</strong> adjunct control conditions (2e-h). Interference <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> agreement conditions is<br />

predicted <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of process<strong>in</strong>g time at <strong>the</strong> verbal region and error rate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> retrieval of<br />

attractors. In <strong>the</strong> adjunct control conditions, simulations predict access to both <strong>the</strong> licit and<br />

illicit subject NPs at <strong>the</strong> adjunct verb. Facilitatory <strong>in</strong>terference effects similar to those shown<br />

for agreement are predicted <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of process<strong>in</strong>g time at <strong>the</strong> reflexive, and error rate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

retrieval of a structurally <strong>in</strong>accessible animate NP subject.<br />

Experiment 3 (self-paced read<strong>in</strong>g, n=32) tested <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> model. In <strong>the</strong><br />

agreement conditions (2a-d), l<strong>in</strong>ear mixed-effects model<strong>in</strong>g revealed effects of both<br />

grammaticality and attractor number (grammaticality: t=-2.043; attractor number: t=2.434;<br />

ps


Umesh Patil (Potsdam), Shravan Vasishth (Potsdam) & Richard Lewis (Michigan)<br />

Early effect of retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference on reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

The onl<strong>in</strong>e application of Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple A of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory is claimed to be <strong>in</strong>fallible<br />

to memory phenomena like retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference from antecedents that are <strong>in</strong>accessible <strong>in</strong><br />

ter<strong>ms</strong> of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory (Phillips, Wagers, & Lau, 2009; Dillon, 2011). Sturt (2003)<br />

and Xiang, Dillon, and Phillips (2009) report a set of studies with English reflexives and<br />

conclude that if <strong>the</strong>re is any effect of retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference from grammatically <strong>in</strong>accessible<br />

antecedents, it appears only dur<strong>in</strong>g later stages of process<strong>in</strong>g. Based on <strong>the</strong>se results,<br />

Phillips et al. (2009) and Dillon (2011) propose that reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g is immune to<br />

<strong>in</strong>terference dur<strong>in</strong>g early stages of process<strong>in</strong>g, because <strong>the</strong> antecedent of a reflexive is<br />

retrieved from memory us<strong>in</strong>g strictly syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation, and that agreement features<br />

like gender and number are completely ignored <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent search process.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, a large body of work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of dependency resolution <strong>in</strong><br />

sentence process<strong>in</strong>g has shown that <strong>the</strong> memory retrieval process utilizes non-syntactic<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation as well. Van Dyke and colleagues (Van Dyke & Lewis, 2003; Van Dyke<br />

& McElree, 2006) have shown that semantic properties of nouns (e.g. animacy feature)<br />

and selectional requirements of verbs are utilized <strong>in</strong> retrievals. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g English reflexives <strong>in</strong>side picture noun phrases (Runner, Sussman, & Tanenhaus,<br />

2006) and Ch<strong>in</strong>ese reflexives (Chen, Jäger, & Vasishth, 2011) is shown to be <strong>in</strong>fluenced<br />

by <strong>the</strong> agreement features of <strong>the</strong> grammatically <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent. In fact, recently<br />

Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs and Felser (2011) have shown that high memory span readers occasionally<br />

consider <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents dur<strong>in</strong>g b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g argument reflexives. In <strong>the</strong> light of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

results, <strong>the</strong> strictly syntactic retrieval account see<strong>ms</strong> to be an exception, which calls for<br />

a specialized retrieval mechanism to expla<strong>in</strong> only a limited set of results.<br />

We formulated <strong>the</strong> question—what type of retrieval cues are used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

process—<strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> <strong>the</strong> cue-based retrieval (CBR) <strong>the</strong>ory (Lewis & Vasishth, 2005). The<br />

CBR <strong>the</strong>ory provides a computational architecture for model<strong>in</strong>g sentence process<strong>in</strong>g phenomena.<br />

The <strong>the</strong>ory is based on <strong>the</strong> memory and process<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of ACT-R, a cognitive<br />

architecture developed for model<strong>in</strong>g general cognitive processes. We implemented<br />

two CBR models of reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> English—model-1 that uses strictly syntactic cues<br />

and, model-2 that uses syntactic cues as well as gender mark<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> reflexive to identify<br />

its antecedent. We also ran an eye track<strong>in</strong>g study to evaluate <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> two<br />

models.<br />

The models’ predictions were generated for <strong>the</strong> four conditions (2x2 design; factors:<br />

accessible NP match/mismatch for gender x <strong>in</strong>accessible NP match/mismatch for gender)<br />

listed <strong>in</strong> (1). The predictions of <strong>the</strong> models are <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of: (i) antecedent retrieval<br />

time and (ii) accuracy <strong>in</strong> retriev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> grammatical antecedent. Model-1 predicts no<br />

<strong>in</strong>terference effect, whereas, model-2 predicts an <strong>in</strong>terference effect <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of retrieval<br />

times and retrieval accuracies.<br />

(1) a. Accessible-match/<strong>in</strong>accessible-match: The tough soldier that Fred treated <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> military hospital <strong>in</strong>troduced hi<strong>ms</strong>elf to all <strong>the</strong> nurses.<br />

b. Accessible-match/<strong>in</strong>accessible-mismatch: The tough soldier that Katie treated<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> military hospital <strong>in</strong>troduced hi<strong>ms</strong>elf to all <strong>the</strong> nurses.<br />

c. Accessible-mismatch/<strong>in</strong>accessible-match: The tough soldier that Katie treated<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> military hospital <strong>in</strong>troduced herself to all <strong>the</strong> nurses.<br />

d. Accessible-mismatch/<strong>in</strong>accessible-mismatch: The tough soldier that Fred<br />

treated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> military hospital <strong>in</strong>troduced herself to all <strong>the</strong> nurses.


We ran an eye track<strong>in</strong>g study (n=40) with <strong>the</strong> four conditions listed above, to evaluate<br />

<strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> two models, assum<strong>in</strong>g that early and late effects are dist<strong>in</strong>guishable<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> eye track<strong>in</strong>g measures. As predicted by model-2, <strong>the</strong> study showed an early effect of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terference from <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedent <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong> of first-pass regression probability;<br />

i.e. a gender match between <strong>the</strong> reflexive and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accessible NP (1a and 1c) <strong>in</strong>duced<br />

a significantly higher (p=0.038) proportion of first-pass regressions from <strong>the</strong> reflexive <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> sentence. Although o<strong>the</strong>r early eye movements measures did not show any significant<br />

effect, a regression cont<strong>in</strong>gent analysis of first-fixation durations showed a pattern of<br />

fixations that was consistent with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terference predictions of model-2.<br />

In sum, <strong>the</strong> eye track<strong>in</strong>g results are consistent with <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> model that<br />

utilizes both syntactic and gender <strong>in</strong>formation to identify <strong>the</strong> antecedent of a reflexive.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> early <strong>in</strong>terference effect found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> current study is not consistent with <strong>the</strong><br />

claim that <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents are not considered dur<strong>in</strong>g earlier stages of process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(Sturt, 2003; Phillips et al., 2009; Dillon, 2011). We conclude that a strictly syntactic<br />

search mechanism is overly selective and, hence, unable to account for <strong>the</strong> data reported<br />

here and <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r studies like Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs and Felser (2011) and Badecker and Straub (2002).<br />

References<br />

Badecker, W., & Straub, K.(2002). The process<strong>in</strong>g role of structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of pronouns and anaphors. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learn<strong>in</strong>g, Memory,<br />

and Cognition, 28 (4), 748–769.<br />

Chen, Z., Jäger, L., & Vasishth, S. (2011). How structure sensitive is <strong>the</strong> parser? Evidence<br />

from Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese. In B. Stolterfoht & S. Fea<strong>the</strong>rston (Eds.), Empirical approaches<br />

to l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>the</strong>ory: Studies of mean<strong>in</strong>g and structure. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton de Gruyter. (<strong>in</strong><br />

press)<br />

Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs, I., & Felser, C. (2011). The role of work<strong>in</strong>g memory <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of reflexives.<br />

Language and Cognitive Processes. (<strong>in</strong> press)<br />

Dillon, B. (2011). Structured access <strong>in</strong> sentence comprehension. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,<br />

Maryland.<br />

Lewis, R. L., & Vasishth, S.(2005). An activation-based model of sentence process<strong>in</strong>g as skilled<br />

memory retrieval. Cognitive Science: A Multidiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary Journal, 29 (3), 375–419.<br />

Phillips, C., Wagers, M. W., & Lau, E. F.(2009). Grammatical illusions and selective fallibility<br />

<strong>in</strong> real time language comprehension. Language and <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> Compass.<br />

Runner, J. T., Sussman, R. S., & Tanenhaus, M. K.(2006). Process<strong>in</strong>g reflexives and pronouns<br />

<strong>in</strong> picture noun phrase. Cognitive Science, 30 (2), 193–241.<br />

Sturt, P.(2003). The time-course of <strong>the</strong> application of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> reference resolution.<br />

Journal of Memory and Language, 48 (3), 542–562.<br />

Van Dyke, J. A., & Lewis, R. L.(2003). Dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g effects of structure and decay on attachment<br />

and repair: A cue-based pars<strong>in</strong>g account of recovery from misanalyzed ambiguities.<br />

Journal of Memory and Language, 49, 285–316.<br />

Van Dyke, J. A., & McElree, B.(2006). Retrieval <strong>in</strong>terference <strong>in</strong> sentence comprehension. Journal<br />

of Memory and Language, 55, 157–166.<br />

Xiang, M., Dillon, B., & Phillips, C. (2009). Illusory licens<strong>in</strong>g effects across dependency types:<br />

Erp evidence. Bra<strong>in</strong> and Language, 108 (1), 40–55.


Syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of pronouns<br />

Syntactic constra<strong>in</strong>ts affect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of pronouns <strong>in</strong>clude, among o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ear<br />

distance between a pronoun and a potential antecedent (e.g. Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs et al., 2011) and<br />

condition B of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory (Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, 1981). Little is known, however, about how<br />

<strong>the</strong>se potentially compet<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong>teract dur<strong>in</strong>g real-time sentence comprehension. We<br />

will report <strong>the</strong> results from an eye-movement monitor<strong>in</strong>g study <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g when dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g local and/or non-local antecedents for pronouns are considered <strong>in</strong> different types<br />

of syntactic environment.<br />

B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g condition B demands that (non-reflexive) pronouns must not be bound with<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g doma<strong>in</strong>, which should exclude David from <strong>the</strong> set of candidate antecedents<br />

for him <strong>in</strong> sentences like (1) below.<br />

(1) Nicki th<strong>in</strong>ks that Davidk likes himi/*k.<br />

Clare Patterson & Claudia Felser (Potsdam)<br />

Pronouns <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> syntactic environments appear to be exempt from condition B, however.<br />

These <strong>in</strong>clude so-called ‘short distance pronouns’ (henceforth, SDPs) <strong>in</strong> sentences such as (2)<br />

below, where ei<strong>the</strong>r Nick or David can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as coreferential with <strong>the</strong> pronoun him.<br />

(2) Nicki saw Davidk put <strong>the</strong> cat beside himi/k.<br />

Possible reasons as to why SDPs might be exempt from condition B <strong>in</strong>clude proposals to <strong>the</strong><br />

effect that prepositional phrases such as beside him <strong>in</strong> (2), or certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds of (VP-<strong>in</strong>ternal)<br />

aspectual phrases, can be b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g doma<strong>in</strong>s (Hestvik, 1991; Tenny, 2004). Experimental<br />

evidence for <strong>the</strong> referential ambiguity of SDPs has been reported by Seker<strong>in</strong>a et al. (2004).<br />

Previous research on <strong>the</strong> role of condition B <strong>in</strong> onl<strong>in</strong>e pronoun resolution has yielded a<br />

number of different hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Based on results from cross-modal prim<strong>in</strong>g, Nicol and<br />

Sw<strong>in</strong>ney (1989) argued that b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples act as an <strong>in</strong>itial filter on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

pronouns, such that only antecedents that are licensed by condition B are considered dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g. An alternative view was put forward by Badecker and Straub (2002), who<br />

suggested that syntactically ‘<strong>in</strong>accessible’ antecedents for pronouns are also <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>itial candidate set. F<strong>in</strong>ally, if Sturt’s (2003) f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g of reflexives (which<br />

are subject to b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g condition A) carry over to pronouns, <strong>the</strong>n condition B should act as an<br />

early but defeasible filter, with <strong>in</strong>accessible antecedents potentially be<strong>in</strong>g considered at later<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g stages only.<br />

34 native speakers of English were presented with sentences which conta<strong>in</strong>ed an<br />

object pronoun (him or her) and two potential sentence-<strong>in</strong>ternal antecedents. Gender<br />

congruence between <strong>the</strong> pronoun and <strong>the</strong> proper names was manipulated (match vs.<br />

mismatch) to serve as a diagnostic for referential dependency formation. In Experiment 1,<br />

‘condition B’ type sentences were used (see examples 3a-c):<br />

(3) a. DOUBLE MATCH<br />

John remembered that Mark had taught him a new song on <strong>the</strong> guitar.<br />

b. LOCAL MISMATCH<br />

John remembered that Jane had taught him a new song on <strong>the</strong> guitar.<br />

c. NON-LOCAL MISMATCH<br />

Jane remembered that John had taught him a new song on <strong>the</strong> guitar.<br />

In Experiment 2, sentences conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g SDPs were used (examples 4a-c):


(4) a. DOUBLE MATCH<br />

Barry saw Gav<strong>in</strong> place a gun near him on <strong>the</strong> ground with great care.<br />

b. LOCAL MISMATCH<br />

Barry saw Megan place a gun near him on <strong>the</strong> ground with great care.<br />

c. NON-LOCAL MISMATCH<br />

Megan saw Barry place a gun near him on <strong>the</strong> ground with great care.<br />

While a general preference for l<strong>in</strong>early closer antecedents favours <strong>the</strong> local antecedent <strong>in</strong> both<br />

(3) and (4), b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g condition B rules <strong>the</strong> local antecedent out <strong>in</strong> sentences of type (3). All<br />

experimental and filler sentences were embedded with<strong>in</strong> short neutral discourse contexts, and<br />

comprehension questions followed two thirds of <strong>the</strong> trials. Participants’ eye movements were<br />

recorded while <strong>the</strong>y were read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> stimulus materials on a computer screen.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> condition B type sentences (Experiment 1), <strong>the</strong> ‘non-local mismatch’ condition<br />

(3c) yielded significantly longer reread<strong>in</strong>g and total view<strong>in</strong>g times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronoun and<br />

spillover region compared to <strong>the</strong> ‘local mismatch’ condition (3b). The ‘non-local mismatch’<br />

condition (3c) also yielded significantly <strong>in</strong>creased regression-path times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al region<br />

compared to <strong>the</strong> ‘local mismatch’ condition (3b). This <strong>in</strong>dicates that participants experienced<br />

late but significant difficulty when <strong>the</strong> non-local antecedent mismatched <strong>the</strong> pronoun <strong>in</strong><br />

gender. Additionally, <strong>the</strong>re was a trend for <strong>the</strong> ‘double match’ condition (3a) to have<br />

<strong>in</strong>creased reread<strong>in</strong>g and total view<strong>in</strong>g times compared to <strong>the</strong> ‘local mismatch’ condition (3b),<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g potential <strong>in</strong>terference from a gender-match<strong>in</strong>g local antecedent. For SDP sentences<br />

(Experiment 2) a different pattern was observed. Here <strong>the</strong> ‘local mismatch’ condition (4b)<br />

elicited <strong>the</strong> longest reread<strong>in</strong>g times <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pref<strong>in</strong>al and f<strong>in</strong>al regions, <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

participants experienced process<strong>in</strong>g difficulty later dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sentence when <strong>the</strong> local<br />

antecedent mismatched <strong>in</strong> gender.<br />

Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>se results suggest that when a pronoun is first encountered <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

not an immediate default to ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> local (Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs et al., 2011) or <strong>the</strong> first-mentioned<br />

(Arnold et al., 2000) antecedent. Nor is <strong>the</strong>re an automatic application of condition B at an<br />

early ‘bond<strong>in</strong>g’ stage. Instead, candidate antecedents are evaluated fully at a later ‘resolution’<br />

stage, which <strong>in</strong>cludes consideration of <strong>the</strong> syntactic configuration and <strong>the</strong> application of<br />

condition B. For pronouns which are exempt from condition B (Experiment 2), a preference<br />

for <strong>the</strong> local antecedent is observed.<br />

References<br />

Arnold, J. E., Eisenband, J. G., Brown-Schmidt, S, and Trueswell, J. C. (2000). The<br />

immediate use of gender <strong>in</strong>formation: Eyetrack<strong>in</strong>g evidence of <strong>the</strong> time-course of pronoun<br />

resolution. Cognition 76, B13-B26.<br />

Badecker, W., & Straub, K. (2002). The process<strong>in</strong>g role of structural constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of pronouns and anaphors. J Exp Psychol Learn 28, 748-769.<br />

Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky, N. (1981). Lectures <strong>in</strong> Government and B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. Dordrecht: Foris.<br />

Cunn<strong>in</strong>gs, I., Patterson, C., & Felser, C. (2011). “Variable b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g and coreference <strong>in</strong><br />

sentence comprehension: Evidence from eye movements”. AMLaP 17, Paris.<br />

Hestvik, A. (1991). Subjectless b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g doma<strong>in</strong>s. Nat Lang L<strong>in</strong>guist Th 9, 455-496.<br />

Nicol, J., & Sw<strong>in</strong>ney, D. (1989). The role of structure <strong>in</strong> coreference assignment dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sentence comprehension. J Psychol<strong>in</strong>guist Res 18, 5-20.<br />

Seker<strong>in</strong>a, I., Stro<strong>ms</strong>wold, K., & Hestvik, A. (2004). How do adults and children process<br />

referentially ambiguous pronouns? J Child Lang 31, 123-152.<br />

Tenny, C. (2004). “Pronoun b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> grammar of sentience”. Workshop on Semantic<br />

Approaches to B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g Theory, ESSLLI 16, Université Henri Po<strong>in</strong>caré, Nancy.


Uli Sauerland (ZAS) & Jonathan Bobaljik (UConn)<br />

Syncretism Distribution Model<strong>in</strong>g and Person Paradig<strong>ms</strong><br />

<strong>Generative</strong> analyses of paradigm morphology relate two layers: <strong>the</strong> morpheme layer and <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

feature layer. <strong>Generative</strong> rules relate <strong>the</strong> two layers – for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong>sertion rules <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case<br />

of distributed morphology, which we adopt for concreteness <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g. Such a generative<br />

analysis is restricted by two factors: a) <strong>the</strong> set of features, and b) <strong>the</strong> type of rule-order<strong>in</strong>g it allows.<br />

We dist<strong>in</strong>guish between extr<strong>in</strong>sic, weak <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic and strong <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic rule order<strong>in</strong>g. Consider <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g illustration: If <strong>the</strong>re are two <strong>in</strong>dependent features F1 and F2, <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

three possible rules:<br />

A: [F1 & F2] ↦→ /a/, B: [F1] ↦→ /b/, C: [F2] ↦→ /c/<br />

Rules can be ordered <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically by <strong>the</strong>ir specificity: e.g. rule A must be ordered first <strong>in</strong> any<br />

language that uses it because if it was ordered after any of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r rules, it wouldn’t have any<br />

effect. Rule B and C, however, don’t stand <strong>in</strong> any <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic order. The three order pr<strong>in</strong>ciples are<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guished <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir treatment of <strong>the</strong>se two. Extr<strong>in</strong>sic order allows languages to specify <strong>the</strong> order<br />

of B and C, a weak <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic order allows languages to use rule B and C, but only if <strong>the</strong> language<br />

also uses rule A – <strong>in</strong> that context, <strong>the</strong> order of rules B and C is actually irrelevant. A strong <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

order never allows languages to make use of more than one of B and C.<br />

The feature set and constra<strong>in</strong>ts on rule order predict which paradig<strong>ms</strong> can be generated. However,<br />

paradigm morphology differs from o<strong>the</strong>r doma<strong>in</strong>s of generative l<strong>in</strong>guistics <strong>in</strong> that paradig<strong>ms</strong> that<br />

cannot be generated <strong>in</strong> a systematic fashion, can still be generated via accidental homophony. For<br />

example, consider <strong>the</strong> paradigm [+F1, +F2] ↔ /b/, [+F1, -F2] ↔ /b/, [-F1, +F2] ↔ /c/. If extr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

rule order is possible, <strong>the</strong> rules B followed by C generate <strong>the</strong> paradigm. But, if only weak <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

orders are possible, <strong>the</strong> paradigm can still be generated: Namely, it requires all three rules A, B,<br />

and C and <strong>the</strong> assumption that morphemes /a/ and /b/ are accidentally homophonous.<br />

How do we f<strong>in</strong>d out which feature set and which rule order<strong>in</strong>g type are correct? Traditionally<br />

morphologist follow are rule of thumb, that Halle & Marantz (2008) state as follows: avoid accidental<br />

homophony and maximize generalizations. Despite its usefulness, <strong>the</strong> rule of thumb has<br />

no pr<strong>in</strong>cipled justification. In this talk, we <strong>in</strong>stead focus on <strong>the</strong> accidental, i.e. random, nature of<br />

accidental homophony: We view accidental homophony like random noise and it must <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

be randomly distributed. For a concrete generative analysis, we compute for a large amount of<br />

morphological data from several languages which syncretis<strong>ms</strong> can be systematic and which must<br />

be accidental. We <strong>the</strong>n test how ‘random’ <strong>the</strong> distribution of <strong>the</strong> accidental syncretism is us<strong>in</strong>g an<br />

exact, non-parametric statistical test. The method is an <strong>in</strong>stance of maximum likelihood model<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

The best morphological analysis is one where <strong>the</strong> actual distribution of accidental is highly likely<br />

to have arisen from random noise.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> talk, we present two results: 1) A general statistical framework for <strong>the</strong> analysis of typological<br />

paradigm frequencies. 2) An application of <strong>the</strong> framework to Cysouw’s (2003, OUP) data on<br />

person mark<strong>in</strong>g to argue that extr<strong>in</strong>sic rule order is necessary. In this abstract, we focus on a<br />

exemplary subcase – <strong>the</strong> case of first person morphology. For this case, we tested all possible<br />

generative analyses, and f<strong>in</strong>d that surpris<strong>in</strong>gly two can account for <strong>the</strong> data.<br />

The First Person Case: Now consider real data: <strong>the</strong> four cells of first person (first exclusive<br />

m<strong>in</strong>imal = 1, first <strong>in</strong>clusive m<strong>in</strong>imal = 1+2, first exclusive augmented = 1+3, and first <strong>in</strong>clusive


0 5 10 15<br />

augmented = 1+2+3). In this case, <strong>the</strong>re are 15 possible paradig<strong>ms</strong> and also 15 possible features.<br />

The m<strong>in</strong>imal number of universal features sufficient to allow an analysis of all 15 paradigm is 3.<br />

Our computational analysis shows that <strong>the</strong>re are 47 dist<strong>in</strong>ct generative analyses with 3 universal<br />

features (out of over 16000 total possible analyses).<br />

We <strong>the</strong>n tested whe<strong>the</strong>r any of <strong>the</strong> generative analyses predicts <strong>the</strong> actual distribution of languages<br />

across <strong>the</strong> 15 possible paradig<strong>ms</strong>. To limit <strong>the</strong> effect of large language families, we counted maximally<br />

15 languages per paradigm follow<strong>in</strong>g Cysouw (Post hoc, we confirmed our results to be<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependent of this assumption.) Contra Cysouw’s claim, we found that <strong>the</strong>re are generative analyses<br />

that predict <strong>the</strong> actual distribution to be highly likely. Contra generative expectations, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are actually two generative models yield likelihood greater 80% for <strong>the</strong> actual distribution (all o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

models yield <strong>in</strong> likelihood smaller 0.1%): Model A and Model B illustrated below. On <strong>the</strong> x-axis,<br />

<strong>the</strong> two graphs show <strong>the</strong> 15 possible paradig<strong>ms</strong>, and on <strong>the</strong> y-axis <strong>the</strong> number of language (grey =<br />

actual, white = most likely expected). The top right corner shows <strong>the</strong> 3 basic features (bold frame)<br />

and possible derived features, <strong>the</strong> rate of accidental homophony, and <strong>the</strong> likelihood predicted for<br />

<strong>the</strong> actual distribution. Model A uses three semantically def<strong>in</strong>able, features 1, -2 and m<strong>in</strong>imal, and<br />

assumes a rate of accidental homophony of 5.8%. Model B uses also uses <strong>the</strong> features 1 and -2,<br />

but <strong>in</strong> addition <strong>the</strong> semantically unexpected feature [[1,-2,m<strong>in</strong>imal] or [1,2,augmented]], while <strong>the</strong><br />

accidental homophony rate is 10.3%. For <strong>the</strong> paradig<strong>ms</strong>, a bold frame <strong>in</strong>dicates that <strong>the</strong> paradigm<br />

can be generated without accidental homophony and <strong>the</strong> t<strong>in</strong>y numbers below <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong> optimal<br />

underly<strong>in</strong>g distribution of languages.<br />

21.6 16.4 14.5 14.4 13 2.2 0.8<br />

aHomph rate: 5.8 %<br />

p > 9.9 * 10^ -1<br />

actual # of languages<br />

predicted # of languages<br />

0 5 10 15<br />

aHomph rate: 10.3 %<br />

p > 8.5 * 10^ -1<br />

actual # of languages<br />

predicted # of languages<br />

27.6 16.3 13.8 13.7 11.6 0 0<br />

Model A Model B<br />

Conclusion: In sum, we argue that generative morphology must use statistical models to get<br />

around <strong>the</strong> problem of accidental homophony and propose such a model, syncretism distribution<br />

model<strong>in</strong>g. Us<strong>in</strong>g this approach, we show that <strong>the</strong> morphological data from person paradig<strong>ms</strong><br />

support generative models, but require extr<strong>in</strong>sic rule order.<br />

References: Cysouw, M., 2003. The Paradigmatic Structure of Person Mark<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford University<br />

Press.


Patrick Sturt (University of Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh)<br />

The tim<strong>in</strong>g of dependency formation: State of <strong>the</strong> art and future challenges<br />

In <strong>the</strong> last two decades, on-l<strong>in</strong>e experimental techniques have yielded a wealth of evidence about<br />

<strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g of dependency formation. But what does this evidence tell us about <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

strategies and overall architecture of <strong>the</strong> language comprehension system? In this talk, I will attempt<br />

to build up a picture of <strong>the</strong> sentence comprehension system from <strong>the</strong> available evidence, focus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on recent work conducted at Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh and elsewhere, cover<strong>in</strong>g a range of dependency types<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g control dependencies, reflexive b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> picture noun and co-argument contexts),<br />

subject-verb agreement. I will review <strong>the</strong> evidence with <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g questions <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d: Is <strong>the</strong>re a<br />

systematic explanation for <strong>the</strong> variability <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g and violability of grammatical constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

under different conditions? What is <strong>the</strong> relation between on-l<strong>in</strong>e structure-build<strong>in</strong>g and f<strong>in</strong>al<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation? What k<strong>in</strong>d of memory access might be <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> dependency formation? What is<br />

<strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong> use of top-down and bottom-up structural <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> pars<strong>in</strong>g? The talk<br />

will end with an outl<strong>in</strong>e of challenges for future research, and some suggestions on how we might<br />

tackle <strong>the</strong>m.


Yanyan Sui (NYU)<br />

Metrical Structural Prom<strong>in</strong>ence Versus Perceived Prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> Standard Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

Proposal: This study dist<strong>in</strong>guishes stress as metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence from perceived<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> metrical stress analysis of Standard Ch<strong>in</strong>ese, a tone language whose<br />

syllables have fixed underly<strong>in</strong>g tones. It clai<strong>ms</strong> that perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence may diverge from<br />

metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence under <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of duration and tones. The <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ence of particular tones <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable of a disyllabic word, as well as longer<br />

duration as a boundary leng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g effect may lead to iambic prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgment, whereas<br />

consistent F0 and durational patterns <strong>in</strong> addition to <strong>the</strong> distribution of neutral tones and<br />

segmental reduction suggest <strong>the</strong> basic foot structure is trochaic.<br />

Background: The stress pattern of disyllabic words whose second syllables are toneless,<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r underly<strong>in</strong>gly or as a result of tone deletion, is agreed to be Strong-Weak. What rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

controversial, both <strong>in</strong> native speakers‟ judgment and <strong>in</strong> previous phonological analyses, is <strong>the</strong><br />

stress pattern of words that do not conta<strong>in</strong> toneless syllables, which is claimed to be (1)<br />

iambic (Chao 1968, Xu 1982), (2) ei<strong>the</strong>r iambic or trochaic depend<strong>in</strong>g on lexical specification<br />

(Hoa 1983), or (3) trochaic (Duanmu 2000), but (4) becomes iambic <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> surface by stress<br />

shift (Chang 1992) or by employment of a special type of foot (Duanmu 2007), or ra<strong>the</strong>r, (5)<br />

<strong>the</strong> stress pattern is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by tonal prom<strong>in</strong>ence (Meredith 1990). This paper argues that<br />

it is <strong>in</strong>correct to treat perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence directly as metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence.<br />

Prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgment is subject to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of duration and tones, among many o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

factors <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ence perception.<br />

Perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence ≠ metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence: Perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence may not<br />

be <strong>the</strong> faithful reflection of metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence due to durational and tonal effects<br />

<strong>in</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgment. First, durational difference between syllables <strong>in</strong> a word <strong>in</strong>duces<br />

judgment of syllables with longer duration as more salient. In a corpus study of 2239<br />

disyllabic words <strong>in</strong> connected speech by Deng (2010), it is found that before no pause, <strong>the</strong><br />

first syllable is longer than <strong>the</strong> second syllable, but before little pause, <strong>the</strong> second syllable is<br />

longer, and <strong>the</strong> durational difference grows substantially before an obvious pause and <strong>in</strong><br />

utterance f<strong>in</strong>al position. Patterns <strong>in</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgment closely correlate with <strong>the</strong> durational<br />

differences. Before no pause and little pause, 64% and 52% of words respectively are judged<br />

stronger <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first syllable, but before an obvious pause, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g utterance f<strong>in</strong>ally, only<br />

about 26% of words are judged stronger <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first syllable. And when grouped by tones,<br />

words that are judged stronger <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable <strong>in</strong>variably have longer second syllables.<br />

Second, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic prom<strong>in</strong>ence of tones <strong>in</strong>terferes with prom<strong>in</strong>ence judgment. Previous<br />

studies have noted that syllables with High Fall<strong>in</strong>g tone tend to be judged as <strong>the</strong> most<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ent, whereas syllables with Low tone are <strong>the</strong> least likely to be perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ent<br />

(Hoa 1983). This observation is confirmed by <strong>the</strong> perception experiment by Deng (2010) and<br />

by <strong>the</strong> present study on embedded made-up disyllabic words, which vary <strong>in</strong> tonal<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ations, but are devoid of morphosyntactic and semantic <strong>in</strong>formation. The results show<br />

that <strong>in</strong> a disyllabic word if <strong>the</strong> second syllable bears High Fall<strong>in</strong>g tone, or if <strong>the</strong> first syllable<br />

bears Low tone, <strong>the</strong> word tends to be judged more salient <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable (at about 65%<br />

and 59% chances respectively), and <strong>the</strong> likelihood reaches 89% if <strong>the</strong> first syllable bears Low<br />

tone and <strong>the</strong> second syllable bears High Fall<strong>in</strong>g tone. In contrast, a second syllable with Low<br />

tone is judged prom<strong>in</strong>ent only 21% of <strong>the</strong> time. The correlation of tones and prom<strong>in</strong>ence<br />

judgment is salient and consistent across various speech registers <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g read isolated


words, broadcast news, and conversational speech. Therefore, perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence cannot<br />

be simply equated with metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence. Representations of metrical structure<br />

may only be built on evidence <strong>in</strong>dependent of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic tonal prom<strong>in</strong>ence and durational<br />

effects due to boundary leng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Phonetic evidence for disyllabic trochee: (1) Strong-Weak F0 alternation: <strong>in</strong> a corpus study<br />

of prosody <strong>in</strong> broadcast news by Lai et al. (2010) which <strong>in</strong>cludes 56378 disyllabic tokens,<br />

4540 trisyllabic tokens and 727 quadrisyllabic tokens, a robust strong-weak F0 pattern is<br />

found <strong>in</strong> disyllabic words, and <strong>the</strong> strong-weak pattern repeats <strong>in</strong> quadrisyllabic words<br />

between <strong>the</strong> third and fourth syllables; Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, when grouped by tones, a tone is realized<br />

more closely to its tonal template <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first syllable than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable <strong>in</strong> disyllabic<br />

words; Strong-Weak alternation <strong>in</strong> metrical strength is also found <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dependent study of<br />

<strong>in</strong>tonation model<strong>in</strong>g by Kochanski et al. (2003); (2) Durational patterns: duration is not an<br />

immediate acoustic cue to metrical strength, it also <strong>in</strong>dicates prosodic constituent boundaries.<br />

However, consistent durational patterns emerge <strong>in</strong> sentential medial position before no pause,<br />

<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> first syllable is longer than <strong>the</strong> second syllable, and <strong>the</strong> third syllable longer than<br />

<strong>the</strong> second syllable <strong>in</strong> polysyllabic words (Wang & Wang 1993, Lai et al. 2010, Deng 2010).<br />

Phonological evidence for disyllabic trochee: (1) Distribution of neutral tone: underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

toneless syllables may only occur <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable of a disyllabic word, never <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first<br />

syllable, e.g., zhǔn tou „accuracy‟, jì de „remember‟; (2) Position of tone deletion: only <strong>the</strong><br />

tone of <strong>the</strong> second syllable may be deleted <strong>in</strong> disyllabic words, e.g., gōng jiā/ jia „<strong>the</strong> state‟, yì<br />

wù/ wu „obligation‟; (3) Position of segmental reduction: i) vowel reduction only occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

second syllable, e.g., mián huā, /x w ɑ/ → [x w ə] „cotton‟, chuāng hù, /xu/ → [x w ə] „w<strong>in</strong>dow‟; ii)<br />

vowel devoic<strong>in</strong>g only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second syllable, e.g., kuò qì /tɕ h i/ → [tɕ h i ] „lavish‟, sòng qǜ /tɕ h y/<br />

→ [tɕ h y ] „send‟. These phenomena are manifestations of weaker metrical strength <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

second syllable of disyllabic words, which support <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis of disyllabic trochee.<br />

Foot construction: Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Generalized Trochee Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (Hayes 1991) this study<br />

proposes that <strong>the</strong> metrical foot <strong>in</strong>ventory of Standard Ch<strong>in</strong>ese is Construct (σ σ), else (σµµ).<br />

When a disyllabic trochee cannot be formed, a bimoraic trochee is constructed, e.g., Ft(yǐ zi)<br />

„chair‟, Ft(xīn zàng) „heart‟, [Ft(qì chē) Ft(kù)] „garage‟. Stress <strong>in</strong>teracts with tone <strong>in</strong> ter<strong>ms</strong><br />

that stressed positions must bear tone, while unstressed position is subject to tone deletion.<br />

Conclusion: This study has shown that perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence may diverge from metrical<br />

structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence under <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of tone and duration. It is <strong>in</strong>correct to identify<br />

metrical structural prom<strong>in</strong>ence with perceived prom<strong>in</strong>ence. Close exam<strong>in</strong>ation of F0 and<br />

durational patterns as well as <strong>the</strong> distribution of tone and segmental reduction suggests <strong>the</strong><br />

metrical structure is trochaic. The study contributes to <strong>the</strong> general discussion of how acoustic<br />

and perceptual evidence may shed light to phonological representations, and <strong>the</strong> discussion of<br />

tone and stress furnishes ano<strong>the</strong>r example of how tone <strong>in</strong>teracts with stress <strong>in</strong> a tone language.<br />

Selected References: Chang, Mei-Chih Laura. 1992. A prosodic account of tone, stress, and<br />

tone sandhi <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese languages. Doctoral dissertation. University of Hawaii. Deng, Dan.<br />

2010. Hanyu Yunluci Yanjiu. [The study of prosodic words <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese] Beij<strong>in</strong>g: Beij<strong>in</strong>g<br />

University. Duanmu, San. 2000. 2007. The Phonology of Standard Ch<strong>in</strong>ese. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press. Lai, C., Sui, Y. and Yuan, J. 2010. “A corpus study of <strong>the</strong> prosody of<br />

polysyllabic words <strong>in</strong> Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese,” Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of Speech Prosody 2010, 100457:1-4.<br />

Meredith, Scott. 1990. Issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> phonology of prom<strong>in</strong>ence. Doctoral dissertation. MIT.


Megan Sutton, Michael Fetters & Jeffrey Lidz (Maryland)<br />

Pars<strong>in</strong>g for Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C at 30-months<br />

In study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> acquisition of any constra<strong>in</strong>t, it is important to recognize <strong>the</strong> contribution of<br />

both children’s grammatical representations and <strong>the</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g mechanis<strong>ms</strong> required to deploy<br />

<strong>the</strong>se representations. In order to correctly understand sentences like (1), exhibit<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C,<br />

children must m<strong>in</strong>imally (a) access lexical <strong>in</strong>formation, (b) build <strong>the</strong> phrase structure and (c)<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegrate <strong>the</strong>se with Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C to constra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(1) She’s patt<strong>in</strong>g Katie!<br />

Importantly, even adult-like behavior <strong>in</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C contexts does not directly reflect adultlike<br />

knowledge: <strong>the</strong>re are a number of non-adultlike strategies children could rely on to yield <strong>the</strong><br />

same behavior. However, <strong>the</strong>se non-adultlike strategies are <strong>in</strong>dependent of structure; only adultlike,<br />

structure-dependent grammatical knowledge of Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C predicts that performance on a<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C task would be dependent on variation <strong>in</strong> speed of structure-build<strong>in</strong>g. Build<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

previous research show<strong>in</strong>g that early understand<strong>in</strong>g of sentences like (1) is affected by<br />

vocabulary size but not efficiency of lexical access ([1]), we explored <strong>the</strong> effects of Vocabulary,<br />

Lexical Access Speed (LAS), and Phrase Structure Integration Speed (PSIS) on 30-month-olds’<br />

comprehension of Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C. We show that all 30-month-olds appropriately represent Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

C, as efficiency of pars<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C contexts is dependent on speed of structure-build<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

We tested 32 30-month-olds (28;3-31;25,M=30;1) on three preferential look<strong>in</strong>g tasks. In<br />

experiment 1 (Figure 1), test<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C, children saw 8 trials which simultaneously<br />

presented a reflexive and non-reflexive event with a non-reflexive sentence (1). We measured <strong>the</strong><br />

proportion look<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> non-reflexive video. Experiments 2 and 3 tested <strong>the</strong> same children to<br />

obta<strong>in</strong> measures LAS and PSIS, respectively. In experiment 2 children saw 8 trials featur<strong>in</strong>g 2<br />

familiar objects with an audio prompt to f<strong>in</strong>d one of <strong>the</strong> objects (2). In experiment 3, children<br />

saw 3 objects of <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>the</strong> largest of which differed <strong>in</strong> color. In 12 control trials,<br />

children were prompted to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> biggest object (3), and <strong>in</strong> 12 test trials <strong>the</strong>y were prompted to<br />

f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> biggest of <strong>the</strong> two same-color objects (4). Children were divided <strong>in</strong>to ‘fast’ and ‘slow’<br />

groups for LAS and each condition of PSIS by <strong>the</strong> median response latency on distractor-<strong>in</strong>itial<br />

trials [2]. We found no significant correlation between any of <strong>the</strong>se four measures (Vocabulary,<br />

LAS, PSIS:superlative, and PSIS:superlative+adjective; all p>.1), allow<strong>in</strong>g us to use <strong>the</strong>se<br />

measures and <strong>the</strong>ir median-split groups as <strong>in</strong>dependent covariates <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g Experiment 1.<br />

(2) Where’s <strong>the</strong> fish?<br />

(3) Where’s <strong>the</strong> biggest tra<strong>in</strong>?<br />

(4) Where’s <strong>the</strong> biggest red tra<strong>in</strong>?<br />

We analyzed distractor-<strong>in</strong>itial trials (where <strong>the</strong> child was look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> reflexive event at<br />

<strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> word Katie <strong>in</strong> (1)) across <strong>the</strong> 300-3000<strong>ms</strong> post-onset w<strong>in</strong>dow. Both median split<br />

groups for all four covariate measures reach significantly above chance (all p


[1] Sutton, M., Lukyanenko, C. &<br />

Lidz, J. (2011). The Onset of<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple C at 30 Months: <strong>the</strong> role<br />

of vocabulary, syntactic<br />

development, and process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

efficiency. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of BUCLD<br />

35. Cascadilla Press: Cambridge.<br />

[2] Sw<strong>in</strong>gley, D., P<strong>in</strong>to, J., & Fernald,<br />

A. (1999). Cont<strong>in</strong>uous process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> word recognition at 24 months.<br />

Cognition, 71, 73-108.!<br />

!


North Sámi Pronouns<br />

Peter Svenonius (Tro<strong>ms</strong>ø/CASTL)<br />

This paper uses a detailed analysis of North Sámi data to clarify some important<br />

issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> analysis of pronouns crossl<strong>in</strong>guistically. A central phenomenon analyzed<br />

is shifted <strong>in</strong>dexicals, which are different <strong>in</strong> North Sámi from o<strong>the</strong>r languages previously<br />

described. The account provides support to those analyses which posit an operator <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

left periphery supply<strong>in</strong>g personal pronouns with <strong>the</strong>ir referents (e.g. Bianchi 2003 <strong>in</strong>ter<br />

alia), but at <strong>the</strong> same time it provides evidence for locat<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> semantic features <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> pronouns <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves (as <strong>in</strong> Schlenker 2003). Thus it reconciles what have been cast<br />

as alternatives <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature. In addition, <strong>the</strong> analysis of <strong>the</strong> pronouns <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves<br />

supports a more f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed approach to pronom<strong>in</strong>al semantics than is usually assumed.<br />

The k<strong>in</strong>d of shifted <strong>in</strong>dexicals which are central to <strong>the</strong> analysis are illustrated <strong>in</strong> (1),<br />

where <strong>the</strong> embedded clauses conta<strong>in</strong> shifted (i.e. non<strong>in</strong>dexical) second-person pronouns<br />

(and agreement, <strong>in</strong> (1b)), as well as unshifted third person (‘logophoric’) bound pronouns.<br />

(1) a. INgá lohkai: Ii son váldde<br />

du.<br />

Inga said not.3sg s/helog have.pres.conneg you.sg.acc<br />

‘Ingai said shei wouldn’t have “you” [<strong>in</strong> marriage]’<br />

b. De bohtet cizáˇzat ja lohket: Ehpet<br />

<strong>the</strong>n came.past.3pl sparrow.pl.nom and said.past.3pl not.2pl<br />

dii nagot<br />

váldit dan, muhto sii<br />

you.pl.nom manage.pres.conneg take.<strong>in</strong>f it but <strong>the</strong>ylog<br />

nagodit, sii leat nu ollugat.<br />

manage.pres.3pl <strong>the</strong>y are.pres.3pl so many<br />

‘Then sparrowsi came and said “you” can’t carry it, but <strong>the</strong>yi can, <strong>the</strong>yi are<br />

so numerous’<br />

Splitt<strong>in</strong>g and Lump<strong>in</strong>g. Semantic analyses of pronouns posit various k<strong>in</strong>ds of dist<strong>in</strong>ctions<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ways that <strong>the</strong>y pick up <strong>the</strong>ir reference. For example, it is often assumed that<br />

bound anaphoric and freely referr<strong>in</strong>g pronouns are underly<strong>in</strong>gly dist<strong>in</strong>ct, even when <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are <strong>the</strong> same on <strong>the</strong> surface (e.g. Cho<strong>ms</strong>ky’s 1955:525 he and he*).<br />

At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong>re is a trend <strong>in</strong> many semantic analyses toward unification of<br />

different k<strong>in</strong>ds of pronouns, e.g. different bound elements such as bound pronouns, fake<br />

reflexives, anaphors, PRO, etc. (Kratzer 2008, where <strong>the</strong> real semantic action takes place<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> verbal heads, and <strong>the</strong> spell-out of pronouns is mostly just morphology, or Elbourne<br />

2008 <strong>in</strong>ter alia, where various k<strong>in</strong>ds of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g are unified with donkey anaphora under<br />

a D-type analysis).<br />

Fake <strong>in</strong>dexicals (as <strong>in</strong> Heim’s Only I did my homework) appear to show both that<br />

one morphological form can pick up reference <strong>in</strong> different ways, and that bound pronouns<br />

can surface with more than one morphological form.<br />

This state of affairs might be taken to suggest that semantics is autonomous from<br />

morphosyntax, and that <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctions made <strong>in</strong> one system simply fail to match <strong>the</strong><br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ctions made <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. However, such a conclusion would be premature. Ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

I suggest, pronom<strong>in</strong>al elements are complex underly<strong>in</strong>gly. Bound pronom<strong>in</strong>al elements<br />

share some feature patterns with one ano<strong>the</strong>r, which is why <strong>the</strong>y can behave similarly.<br />

The surface exponents which spell out pronom<strong>in</strong>al syntactic structures are underspecified,<br />

which allows <strong>the</strong>m to match a range of different underly<strong>in</strong>g structures, which is why one<br />

surface pronoun can behave <strong>in</strong> several different ways.<br />

Crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence and Shifted <strong>in</strong>dexicals. In order to see this, it is necessary<br />

1


to consider cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence. There are many languages <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re are multiple<br />

series of pronouns, overtly reflect<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ctions which o<strong>the</strong>r languages syncretize<br />

systematically at <strong>the</strong> surface. The logophors of Ewe (Clements 1975) or <strong>the</strong> obviative<br />

markers <strong>in</strong> Algonquian languages (Goddard 1984) are examples. However, detailed<br />

descriptions of <strong>the</strong>se understudied languages are usually not semantically current, and<br />

cutt<strong>in</strong>g-edge semantics does not have access to <strong>the</strong> details of <strong>the</strong>se languages necessary<br />

for choos<strong>in</strong>g among hypo<strong>the</strong>ses.<br />

An exception is Anand & Nev<strong>in</strong>s’ (2004) <strong>in</strong>vestigation of shifted <strong>in</strong>dexicals <strong>in</strong> Zazaki.<br />

Observ<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong>dexicals shift toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y argue aga<strong>in</strong>st Schlenker’s (2003) and von<br />

Stechow’s (2002) lexical approaches. Instead, <strong>the</strong>y posit an operator at <strong>the</strong> periphery<br />

of <strong>the</strong> embedded clause which shifts <strong>the</strong> context for <strong>the</strong> entire clause. In support of<br />

this, observe that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> North Sámi examples presented above, <strong>the</strong>re is no overt b<strong>in</strong>der<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> addressee for <strong>the</strong> shifted pronouns. Instead, <strong>the</strong> only bound pronouns<br />

are third person. I argue that <strong>the</strong> operator <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> left periphery can b<strong>in</strong>d as well as shift<br />

context (mak<strong>in</strong>g it more like <strong>the</strong> operators posited by Baker, Biachi, or SigurDsson).<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>re is also evidence from North Sámi that some critical features are located<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pronoun itself. North Sámi makes a four-way dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> ‘def<strong>in</strong>ite’ pronom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

elements (sett<strong>in</strong>g aside deictics, <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites, <strong>in</strong>terrogatives, and o<strong>the</strong>rs). First, it dist<strong>in</strong>guishes<br />

locally bound anaphoric arguments and adjuncts (ieˇs, with various case for<strong>ms</strong>)<br />

both from lexical reflexives (with -d-) and from o<strong>the</strong>r pronom<strong>in</strong>al elements. Second,<br />

it uses pro-drop to dist<strong>in</strong>guish two levels of what Gundel (1999, 2003) calls referential<br />

givenness. F<strong>in</strong>ally, it has two series of overt pronouns (dat, with various case for<strong>ms</strong>, and<br />

son, with various case for<strong>ms</strong>) to dist<strong>in</strong>guish two levels of relational givenness. These are<br />

illustrated <strong>in</strong> (2).<br />

(2) a. Máhtte muitalii, ahte das lea goahti.<br />

Matte.nom told that pn.loc is hut.nom<br />

‘Matte expla<strong>in</strong>ed that he (some else) had a hut’<br />

b. Máhtte muitalii, ahte sus lea goahti.<br />

Matte.nom told that log.loc is hut.nom<br />

‘Matte expla<strong>in</strong>ed that he (Matte) had a hut’<br />

For convenience, <strong>the</strong>se can be referred to as <strong>the</strong> deictic and logophoric pronouns, respectively,<br />

though I will show how <strong>the</strong> first is not strictly deictic and <strong>the</strong> second is different<br />

from <strong>the</strong> logophoric pronouns described <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous literature. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>se two<br />

pronoun series dist<strong>in</strong>guish b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g from non-b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g like <strong>the</strong> way discussed<br />

above. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction, I suggest, is made <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r languages but systematically syncretized<br />

<strong>the</strong>re.<br />

I show that second person (but not first person) pronouns <strong>in</strong> examples like (1) can<br />

pattern with <strong>the</strong> ‘logophoric’ son-series. This requires a four-way dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> features,<br />

where most analyses posit at most a two-way dist<strong>in</strong>ction: There are strictly <strong>in</strong>dexical<br />

elements (first person), underspecified elements which can be <strong>in</strong>dexical or shifted/bound<br />

(second person), obligatory bound elements (third person ‘logophoric’ series), and obligatorily<br />

unbound non<strong>in</strong>dexicals (<strong>the</strong> ‘deictic’ third person series).<br />

2


Kriszta Szendrői (UCL)<br />

Quantifier Rais<strong>in</strong>g is blocked by passives<br />

1. Quantifier Rais<strong>in</strong>g (QR) is a covert syntactic movement operation, <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> sentences with<br />

an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite subject and a universal object:<br />

(1) A dog chased every cat. distributive read<strong>in</strong>g LF: [[every cat] i [a dog chased t i]]<br />

In psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic experiments, <strong>in</strong>verse scope is often found to be hard for native speakers to<br />

access (Ioup 1975, Van Lehn 1978, Catl<strong>in</strong> & Micham 1975; especially Kurtzmann & MacDonald<br />

1993, Tunstall 1998 and Anderson 2004). In this paper, I show that one of <strong>the</strong> reasons why <strong>the</strong><br />

distributive read<strong>in</strong>g is hard to access is <strong>the</strong> existence of an alternative derivation with (sufficiently)<br />

identical <strong>in</strong>terpretation,― <strong>the</strong> passive variant of (1):<br />

(2) Every cat was chased by a dog. distributive read<strong>in</strong>g LF: [[every cat] i [was chased e i by a dog]]<br />

2. Theoretical background: If this turns out to be correct, it has important <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

implications. Most <strong>the</strong>oreticians agree that QR is restricted by <strong>in</strong>terface considerations: Fox (1995,<br />

2000), Re<strong>in</strong>hart (2006) and Bobaljik & Wurmbrand (2011), henceforth B&W. But <strong>the</strong>y disagree<br />

about <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terface mechanis<strong>ms</strong> at play. Fox (2000:26) argued that <strong>the</strong> restriction<br />

applies locally <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic derivation, prevent<strong>in</strong>g scope-shift<strong>in</strong>g operations unless <strong>the</strong>y have an<br />

effect. So, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of QR, <strong>the</strong> movement step is disallowed if it does not lead to a change <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. Re<strong>in</strong>hart (2006:28) claimed that a global comparison of compet<strong>in</strong>g derivations is<br />

necessary, her ‘reference set’ computation: ‘<strong>the</strong> reference set consists of pairs of derivation<br />

and <strong>in</strong>terpretation, where <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation i is identical <strong>in</strong> all pairs.’ 1 So, QR is allowed if <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

alternative derivation without QR with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reference set that has <strong>the</strong> same (i.e. distributive)<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. The crucial question, which Re<strong>in</strong>hart rema<strong>in</strong>ed implicit about, is what determ<strong>in</strong>es<br />

membership <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reference set. As B&W:31, cit<strong>in</strong>g Fox (2000), correctly note, if membership is<br />

restricted to derivations with a shared numeration, <strong>the</strong> global computation can be easily reduced to a<br />

local one. With respect to <strong>the</strong> relevance of examples like (1)-(2) for QR, B&W take an explicit stand:<br />

‘[…] we assume that economy conditions only evaluate compet<strong>in</strong>g derivations from <strong>the</strong> same<br />

numeration (<strong>in</strong>put), and thus that correspond<strong>in</strong>g active and passive sentences will simply not<br />

compete with one ano<strong>the</strong>r.’ (B&W:7)<br />

3. Proposal: So, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> spirit of Re<strong>in</strong>hart’s approach and <strong>in</strong> contrast to B&W’s position, I propose<br />

that membership <strong>in</strong> a particular reference set is restricted by semantic identity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of truthconditional<br />

equivalence. In <strong>the</strong> specific case of active-passive pairs, like (1) and (2), truth-conditional<br />

equivalence is trivially true, except for marg<strong>in</strong>al cases such as utterances <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g NPs that fail to<br />

refer (such as <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g of France), as <strong>the</strong>se may lead to truth-value gaps, while <strong>the</strong>ir passive variant may<br />

not. (We also need to put generic sentences of <strong>the</strong> type Beavers build da<strong>ms</strong> to one side.) My hypo<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

makes <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g testable prediction. If passive variants of active sentences <strong>in</strong>deed block <strong>the</strong><br />

distributive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong> active variant by QR, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>in</strong>verse scope (by QR) should be more<br />

easily accessible <strong>in</strong> sentences that <strong>in</strong>volve verbs that resist passivisation. This is because <strong>in</strong> such<br />

cases, no passive competitor can be present <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reference set, as such a passive competitor does<br />

not exist, and thus, <strong>the</strong> derivation with QR could not be blocked by it. In contrast, if, as Fox<br />

suggested, decisions are taken locally, at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic derivation when QR applies, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong> passive variant would simply not be considered as a viable alternative. The same applies to<br />

B&W’s proposal, who chose to base membership on shared numeration. Thus, both for Fox and<br />

B&W, it should be irrelevant for <strong>the</strong> availability of <strong>in</strong>verse scope whe<strong>the</strong>r a particular (active) sentence<br />

1 B&W’s (p33 l6-8) <strong>in</strong>terpretation of Re<strong>in</strong>hart’s proposal is <strong>the</strong> direct opposite: ‘Re<strong>in</strong>hart holds that <strong>the</strong><br />

calculation <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> competition among <strong>the</strong> members of a ‘reference set’ consist<strong>in</strong>g of derivations (LF,PF<br />

pairs) with a common PF but different LFs.’ I have not managed to ascerta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> source of this <strong>in</strong>terpretation.


<strong>in</strong>volves a passivis<strong>in</strong>g or non-passivis<strong>in</strong>g verb.<br />

It is important to clarify that, I do not necessarily expect that passive variants always block active<br />

variants with QR. (That would mean that <strong>the</strong> distributive read<strong>in</strong>g is never accessed if <strong>the</strong> verb has a<br />

passive alternant.) They only do so if <strong>the</strong>y are actually listed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reference set at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t when<br />

<strong>the</strong> hearer considers <strong>in</strong>verse scope. This is a performance issue, and should be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by an<br />

appropriate <strong>the</strong>ory of language use. While I cannot offer a specific proposal at this po<strong>in</strong>t, it see<strong>ms</strong><br />

clear to me that general discourse considerations such as topic-focus articulation (see Sæbø 1997),<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual differences between speakers (for <strong>in</strong>stance an aptitude to consider richer mean<strong>in</strong>gs e.g.<br />

metaphors, irony), and attention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> psychological sense would be relevant factors. What matters<br />

here is that if any evidence is found that <strong>in</strong>verse scope is obta<strong>in</strong>ed more easily <strong>in</strong> sentences <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verbs that are not passivisable, that would favour Re<strong>in</strong>hart’s global <strong>the</strong>ory over its competitors.<br />

4. Experiment: I determ<strong>in</strong>ed a set of 7 passivis<strong>in</strong>g-nonpassivis<strong>in</strong>g verb pairs by a grammaticality<br />

judgment pre-test. Then, 50 native speakers were presented with a forced-choice questionnaire<br />

(adapted from Anderson 2004) with sentences like (3)-(4). Their task was to circle <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g that is<br />

closest to <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> sentence. The ‘same’-paraphrase corresponds to <strong>the</strong> overt scope<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> ‘different’-paraphrase corresponds to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse scope read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(3) Passivis<strong>in</strong>g condition: A road connects every village on <strong>the</strong> pen<strong>in</strong>sula.<br />

The same road connects <strong>the</strong> villages. Different roads connect <strong>the</strong> villages.<br />

(4) Non-passivis<strong>in</strong>g condition: A road leads to every village on <strong>the</strong> pen<strong>in</strong>sula.<br />

The same road leads to <strong>the</strong> villages. Different roads leads to <strong>the</strong> villages.<br />

All participants saw all ite<strong>ms</strong>, but <strong>in</strong> different orders. The ite<strong>ms</strong> were <strong>in</strong>terspersed with an equal<br />

number of fillers and controls, and pseudo-randomised. The paraphrases were presented <strong>in</strong> different<br />

orders, balanced across conditions. Crucially, each test item pair was identical except for <strong>the</strong> verbs.<br />

5. Results and discussion: Speakers obta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse scope read<strong>in</strong>g 25.4% of <strong>the</strong> time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

non-passivis<strong>in</strong>g condition compared with 14.3% <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> passiviz<strong>in</strong>g verb condition: a statistically<br />

significant difference (participants t=3.963, df=40, two-tailed p


Barbara Tomaszewicz (USC)<br />

A family of exclusives <strong>in</strong> Polish<br />

Polish has four different focus associat<strong>in</strong>g adverbs that can be identified as exclusives, all of<br />

<strong>the</strong>m scalar, yet not always <strong>in</strong>terparaphrasable. Tylko, ledwie, dopiero and aż all evoke<br />

alternative propositions ordered on a scale and imply an exclusion of those alternatives that<br />

are higher or lower on <strong>the</strong> scale than <strong>the</strong> prejacent. What varies is (i) <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

exclusive implication (truth-conditional or pragmatic), (ii) <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> scale (likelihood<br />

vs. time vs. highly context-dependent pragmatic scales), (iii) <strong>the</strong> place of <strong>the</strong> prejacent on <strong>the</strong><br />

scale. Their common mean<strong>in</strong>g components, scalarity and exclusivity, <strong>in</strong>teract with (i-iii)<br />

thus creat<strong>in</strong>g a range of <strong>in</strong>terpretations that cannot be subsumed under <strong>the</strong> notions of<br />

unexpectedness and/or likelihood. The Polish <strong>in</strong>ventory raises a <strong>the</strong>oretically important<br />

question whe<strong>the</strong>r scalarity and exclusivity are generally l<strong>in</strong>ked to unexpectedness/likelihood<br />

or whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> dimension of <strong>the</strong> (default) scale should ra<strong>the</strong>r be lexically specified for each<br />

adverb, e.g. even as always <strong>in</strong>terpreted wrt. a scale of likelihood (Karttunen & Peters 1979)<br />

or its dual, noteworth<strong>in</strong>ess (Herburger 2000, Rullman 2007).<br />

(i) The exclusive component can be targeted by explicit denial, thus for all four exclusives<br />

it is an at-issue entailment (part of <strong>the</strong> assertion). Tylko/ledwie, like English only, can have<br />

quantificational (1b) or scalar (1c) read<strong>in</strong>gs and, and <strong>the</strong>ir prejacents project. The prejacent of<br />

dopiero and aż is at-issue (2-3), and aż cannot have a quantificational read<strong>in</strong>g (3b).<br />

(1) a. Maria widziała tylko/ledwie menadżera.<br />

Maria saw manager<br />

b. No, that’s false. – #She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager./She saw somebody else too.<br />

c. No, that’s false. – #She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager./She saw somebody more special.<br />

(2) a. Maria widziała dopiero menadżera.<br />

Maria saw manager<br />

b. No, that’s false. – She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager (yet)./She saw somebody else too.<br />

c. No, that’s false. – She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager (yet)./She saw somebody more special.<br />

(3) a. Maria widziała aż menadżera.<br />

Maria saw manager<br />

b. No, that’s false. – She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager./#She saw somebody else too.<br />

c. No, that’s false. – She didn’t see <strong>the</strong> manager./She saw somebody less special.<br />

The family of sentences tests (Chierchia & McConnell-G<strong>in</strong>et 1990) yield <strong>the</strong> same results.<br />

(ii) The quantificational read<strong>in</strong>gs of exclusives can be seen as a subtype of scalar read<strong>in</strong>gs:<br />

<strong>the</strong> relevant scale is a entailment scale (Kle<strong>in</strong>dienst 2005, Riester 2006); <strong>the</strong> rank<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

answers to <strong>the</strong> Question Under Discussion (Roberts 1996) is a boolean lattice (Beaver and<br />

Clark’s 2008). A scale not organized accord<strong>in</strong>g to logical entailment will have its dimension<br />

set by <strong>the</strong> context, e.g. importance <strong>in</strong> (1c, 2c, 3c), or temporal order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (2b,c) (c.f. German<br />

erst, König 1979, von Stechov 2006). Thus, scalarity does not automatically lead to a sense<br />

of unexpectedness/surprise. For (4) <strong>the</strong>re is no sense <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> speaker or <strong>the</strong> hearer would<br />

expect <strong>the</strong> team to do any better; each adverb contributes <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> 30 th place is<br />

very low (i.e. lower than a contextually set degree, but not necessarily unexpected).<br />

(4) Zespół był słaby i zajął tylko/ledwie/dopiero/aż 30 miejsce.<br />

team was poor and achieved 30 th place<br />

‘The team performed poorly and earned only 30 th place.’<br />

Scalarity with evaluativity but without likelihood is commonly found with gradable<br />

predicates that license <strong>the</strong> use of very (e.g. The baby's relatives are all more than 6ft tall. The<br />

baby is go<strong>in</strong>g to be very tall.). Evaluativity does not always relate to expectations.<br />

(iii) The place of <strong>the</strong> prejacent is low on <strong>the</strong> scale with tylko/ledwie/dopiero (cf. English<br />

only, Kl<strong>in</strong>edienst 2005, König 1991, von Rooy & Schultz 2005) and high with aż, which is<br />

shown by <strong>the</strong> contrast between (1c, 2c) and (3c). The alternatives excluded with aż are higher<br />

on <strong>the</strong> scale than <strong>the</strong> prejacent, thus aż is a scalar opposite of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs (cf. beyond-operators<br />

<strong>in</strong> Gast & van der Auwera 2011). The cont<strong>in</strong>uation <strong>in</strong> (5a) and (b) sounds like a


contradiction, while <strong>in</strong> (5c) <strong>the</strong> quantity implicature is more easily cancelled (with even<br />

plac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> prejacent high on <strong>the</strong> scale of noteworth<strong>in</strong>ess.)<br />

(5) a. Marek potrafił zjeść aż 5 bananów, #a właściwie 6.<br />

Marek was.able to.eat 5 bananas and actually 6<br />

‘Marek was able to eat as many as 5 bananas, #<strong>in</strong> fact, he could eat 6’.<br />

b. Marek potrafił zjeść tylko/ledwie/dopiero 5 bananów. #a właściwie 6.<br />

Marek was.able to.eat 5 bananas and actually 6<br />

‘Marek was able to eat only 5 bananas, #<strong>in</strong> fact, he could eat 6’.<br />

c. Marek potrafił zjeść nawet 5 bananów, ?a właściwie 6.<br />

Marek was.able to.eat even 5 bananas and actually 6<br />

‘Marek was able to eat even 5 bananas, ?<strong>in</strong> fact, he could eat 6’.<br />

The reason (4) works is that <strong>the</strong> 30 th place is low on <strong>the</strong> “scale of success”, and at <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time high on <strong>the</strong> scale evoked by <strong>the</strong> numeral. (6) shows that <strong>the</strong> scale aż refers to is not<br />

coercible <strong>in</strong>to a scale of success.<br />

(6) Susan Boyle nie wygrała. Zajęła dopiero/#aż drugie miejsce.<br />

‘Susan Boyle did not w<strong>in</strong>. She only took second place.’<br />

If <strong>the</strong> dimension of <strong>the</strong> scale is underspecified <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> semantics of each adverb, we expect it<br />

to be easily manipulated by <strong>the</strong> context (<strong>the</strong> semantics of focused constituent <strong>the</strong> adverb<br />

associates with and <strong>the</strong> pragmatics). The four Polish exclusives, however, appear to be more<br />

contextually restricted. Tylko cannot always get a scalar read<strong>in</strong>g, e.g. <strong>in</strong> (7) it can only mean<br />

<strong>the</strong> Marek woke up once. Exclusively ledwie can receive approximate (8) and counterfactual<br />

(9) read<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

(7) Martwi mnie, że Marek obudził się #tylko/ledwie/dopiero/aż o godz<strong>in</strong>ie 13.<br />

worries me that Marek woke self at hour 13<br />

‘I am disappo<strong>in</strong>ted that Marek woke up as late as at 13h.’<br />

(8) #Tylko/ledwie/#Dopiero/#Aż Marek otworzył drzwi, a zadzwonił telefon.<br />

Marek opened door and rang telephone<br />

‘Marek barely opened <strong>the</strong> door, when <strong>the</strong> telephone rang.’<br />

(9) Marek #tylko/ledwie/#dopiero/#aż otworzył drzwi.<br />

Marek opened door<br />

‘Marek barely opened <strong>the</strong> door. (He thought he was not go<strong>in</strong>g to make it.)’<br />

The four Polish exclusives raise <strong>the</strong> question how much underspecified can <strong>the</strong> lexical<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g be. While all of <strong>the</strong>m share <strong>the</strong> scalar mean<strong>in</strong>g component (10a), <strong>the</strong> scale as<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> (10c) cannot be entirely context dependent, so perhaps more f<strong>in</strong>e gra<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

descriptions (as <strong>in</strong> (10a-d) for dopiero and ledwie) should be specified for <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

exclusives cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically? How much can mirativity be detached from evaluativity<br />

which is a general property of degree related expressions (Rett 2010)?<br />

(10) “tylkoC ϕ” “dopieroC ϕ” “ledwieC ϕ” “aż/čakC ϕ”<br />

a. λw.¬∃p [p ∈S & p(w) = 1 & ⟦ϕ⟧


Satoshi Tomioka (Delaware)<br />

Focus Matters <strong>in</strong> Neo-Hambl<strong>in</strong> Semantics<br />

The recent re-emergence of Hambl<strong>in</strong> semantics of <strong>in</strong>terrogatives (e.g., L<strong>in</strong> 1996, Shimoyama<br />

1999, Kratzer and Shimoyama 2005) has proved fruitful <strong>in</strong> many areas, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> analysis<br />

of wh-<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites. In Beck’s (2006) rendition of Hambl<strong>in</strong> semantics, two additional advantages<br />

are ga<strong>in</strong>ed. (i) A formal relation between a wh-phrase and a Q-morpheme is established:<br />

Wh-phrases only have focus values (= <strong>the</strong>ir Hambl<strong>in</strong> denotations), lack<strong>in</strong>g ord<strong>in</strong>ary values.<br />

Any constituent that conta<strong>in</strong>s a wh-phrase also has no ord<strong>in</strong>ary value until it meets a Q-<br />

Operator <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivation. The role of <strong>the</strong> Q-Operator is to elevate <strong>the</strong> focus value of a<br />

wh-conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g constituent to <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary value. (ii) The prosodic similarities between a<br />

wh-phrase and focus is expla<strong>in</strong>ed: Sabel (2006) and Haida (2007) enlist many languages <strong>in</strong><br />

which wh-phrases act as though <strong>the</strong>y are focused morphosyntactically. Beck’s analysis bodes<br />

well with this wh-(semantic) focus correspondence (cf. Truckenbrodt, to appear).<br />

In this paper, I will fur<strong>the</strong>r exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> wh-focus correlation with special attention<br />

to ‘double-focus’ cases (Krifka 1991, Wold 1996). Both wh-phrases and focus-associates<br />

with operators like only are required to have non-s<strong>in</strong>gleton focus values by <strong>the</strong>ir semantics,<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependently of <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>formation structural statuses. Hence, <strong>the</strong>y can be backgrounded<br />

(a.k.a second occurrence focus) or <strong>the</strong>y can be additionally focused, as shown <strong>in</strong> (1).<br />

(1) a.‘Ann asked what Sue likes, right?’ ‘No, she asked WHO she likes.’<br />

b. ‘Ann only greeted BELLA.’ ‘No, she only greeted CASEY.’<br />

The first question that arises is; how can one get <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a contrasted wh-phrase<br />

when a wh-phrase itself has no ord<strong>in</strong>ary semantic value? Beck’s semantics can actually deal<br />

with a case like (1a) with a m<strong>in</strong>imal modification: All wh-phrases, even morphologically<br />

simplex ones (e.g., who, what) are decomposed with an NP restriction and a wh-determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

Then, (i) The Hambl<strong>in</strong> denotation is derived by <strong>the</strong> choice function mean<strong>in</strong>g of a Detwh.<br />

(ii) A contrastive focus on a wh-phrase is associated with <strong>the</strong> NP restriction. (iii) Both<br />

<strong>the</strong> Detwh and <strong>the</strong> restriction get focus-<strong>in</strong>dices. The first is required by <strong>the</strong> semantics of a<br />

wh, and <strong>the</strong> second comes from <strong>the</strong> constrastiveness. (iv) The <strong>in</strong>dex on <strong>the</strong> Detwh is bound<br />

by <strong>the</strong> closest Q-morpheme, and <strong>the</strong> one on <strong>the</strong> NP ‘passes up’ to a higher focus b<strong>in</strong>der<br />

(i.e., ∼). [Note: A focus <strong>in</strong>dex corresponds to a designated variable that is <strong>in</strong>terpreted by a<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guished assignment (Kratzer 1991). And importantly; (a) � αFi� g,h = h(i) if i is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

doma<strong>in</strong> of h. O<strong>the</strong>rwise, � αFi� g,h = � α � g . (b) h beg<strong>in</strong>s with <strong>the</strong> empty doma<strong>in</strong> (= { }).<br />

(c) An F-<strong>in</strong>dex b<strong>in</strong>der <strong>in</strong>troduces its <strong>in</strong>dex <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of h.] (2) is <strong>the</strong> computation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> second sentence <strong>in</strong> (1a).<br />

(2) a. [who] contrastive focus ⇒ [ whF1 [person]F2]<br />

b. � Q1 [CP [ whF1 [ person]F2] Sue likes ] � g = {p: p = � CP � g,h{f/1}<br />

= {p: p = Sue likes f(person) | f∈D, e >}<br />

c. �∼C2 [IP Anna asked Q1 [ whF1 [ person]F2] Sue likes]] � g,h = {p: p = � IP � g,h{P/2} }<br />

= {p: p =Anna asked which P Sue likes | P∈D< e, t >}<br />

If a focus b<strong>in</strong>der ∼ is also selective, <strong>the</strong> story for (1b) is <strong>the</strong> same except that two <strong>in</strong>dices<br />

are assigned to <strong>the</strong> same constituent (cf. Wold 1996).<br />

(3) a. ∼C2 [ Anna onlyD [∼D1 greeted [[CASEY]2]1]<br />

b. � ∼D1 greeted [[CASEY]2]1� g,h{x/1} = {λy. y greeted x | x ∈ De}<br />

c. � ∼C2 [Anna only greeted [[CASEY]]1]2� g,h{x/2} = {Anna only greeted x | x ∈ De}<br />

1


However, this strategy cannot be extended to (1b) <strong>in</strong> Beck (2006). A focus operator ∼ is<br />

argued to be unselective, and <strong>the</strong> closer operator (∼D above) closes off <strong>the</strong> focus mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of Casey, after which no F-<strong>in</strong>dex is left for <strong>the</strong> higher operator (= ∼C) to b<strong>in</strong>d. In order to<br />

make <strong>the</strong> parallelism between (1a) and (1b) <strong>in</strong>tact, I propose that, while a novel ∼ operator<br />

is unselective, a second occurrence ∼ is selective. The <strong>in</strong>tuition beh<strong>in</strong>d this amendment to<br />

Beck’s <strong>the</strong>ory is as follows. Focus sensitive adverbs like only are considered ‘familiar’ not<br />

only because <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves had appeared <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous discourse but also because <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

associations with <strong>the</strong> designated foci are familiar. A familiar ∼ operator <strong>the</strong>refore does not<br />

freely extend its w<strong>in</strong>gs and b<strong>in</strong>d novel focus variables.<br />

The proposed amendment not only provides a unified analysis of contrasted wh-phrases<br />

and contrasted focus-associated phrases but also makes correct predictions <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r areas.<br />

First, <strong>in</strong> a multiple foci structure where <strong>the</strong>re are two ∼ operators, one novel and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

familiar, it is expected that <strong>the</strong> novel one must have scope over <strong>the</strong> familiar one. In <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

scope configuration, <strong>the</strong> novel ∼ operator accidentally b<strong>in</strong>ds both foci, leav<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g for<br />

<strong>the</strong> old operator to b<strong>in</strong>d. This prediction is <strong>in</strong> accordance with von F<strong>in</strong>tel’s (1994, p 49, fn.<br />

44) observation on <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g asymmetry of two focus operators. The o<strong>the</strong>r phenomenon<br />

that <strong>the</strong> amended analysis works well is what is called an <strong>in</strong>tervention effect, which Beck<br />

(2006) def<strong>in</strong>es as a focus <strong>in</strong>tervention shown <strong>in</strong> (4). In this configuration, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g ∼<br />

C (an unselective b<strong>in</strong>der) accidentally b<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase.<br />

(4) * [Qi ..... [∼ C [ ...... whi ] ]<br />

There have been several facts reported, however, that suggest that, even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure (4),<br />

discourse-familiar ∼ operators do not <strong>in</strong>duce <strong>in</strong>tervention effects (or <strong>the</strong>ir effects significantly<br />

weakened). In Beck and Kim (2006, p.167), <strong>the</strong> lack of <strong>the</strong> alternative question mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

(5) is attributed to <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>in</strong>tervention effect.<br />

(5) Does only John like Mary or Susan? a. #Mary. [*AltQ] b. Yes. [Yes/NoQ]<br />

Eilam (2011) reports, however, that native speakers more readily accept <strong>the</strong> alternative question<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation when only John is backgrounded. Second, <strong>in</strong> many wh-<strong>in</strong>-situ languages<br />

that exhibit <strong>in</strong>tervention effects (e.g., Korean, Japanese, H<strong>in</strong>di), <strong>the</strong> effects are noticeably<br />

weak (or non-existent) <strong>in</strong> why-questions (cf. Miyagawa 1998, Ko 2005 among o<strong>the</strong>rs).<br />

(6) Amwuto/?John-pakkey way ku chayk-ul ilk-ci-anh-ass-ni?<br />

Anyone/John-only why that book-Acc read-CI-Neg-Past-Q<br />

‘Why did nobody/only John read that book?’ (Korean, from Ko 2005, (8a))<br />

Tomioka (2009) attributes this effect to <strong>the</strong> presupposition of why-questions. In ‘why p?’, p is<br />

presupposed, and <strong>the</strong> materials <strong>in</strong> p, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>tervener, belong to <strong>the</strong> background. In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r constituent questions, comparable presuppositions are not guaranteed (Groenendijk<br />

and Stokhof 1984). Third, while many languages prefer plac<strong>in</strong>g phonologically reduced<br />

materials after focus, Amharic can put reduced focus expressions (e.g., only NP) before<br />

wh-phrases. Eilam (2011) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that Amharic shows no <strong>in</strong>tervention effects with those<br />

reduced focus expressions, as expected by <strong>the</strong> current proposal.<br />

Selected References: Beck, S. 2006: ‘Intervention effects follow from focus <strong>in</strong>terpretations,’ <strong>in</strong> NLS, 14:1-<br />

56. Eilam, A. 2011: Explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Informational Component, Ph.D. <strong>the</strong>sis, UPenn. Ko, H.-J. 2005:<br />

Syntax of why-<strong>in</strong>-situ: Merge <strong>in</strong>to [Spec CP] <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> overt yyntax, NLLT, 23, 867-916. Tomioka, S. 2009:<br />

‘Why-questions, presuppositions, and <strong>in</strong>tervention effects,’ JEAL 18: 253-271. Wold, D. 1996: Long distance<br />

selective b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g: The case of focus, <strong>in</strong> The Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of SALT 6, 311-328.<br />

2


Jacopo Torregrossa (Verona)<br />

Encod<strong>in</strong>g contrast at PF<br />

Introduction. This contribution is based on <strong>the</strong> assumption that contrast is an autonomous<br />

<strong>in</strong>formational notion with its own semantic content (Vallduvì/Vilkuna 1998). Its ma<strong>in</strong> aim is<br />

to <strong>in</strong>vestigate how contrast is coded. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, some scholars work<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

cartographic framework propose that contrast is licensed <strong>in</strong> an A-bar position (ContrP) with<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> C-doma<strong>in</strong> of <strong>the</strong> sentence (see Frascarelli/H<strong>in</strong>terhölz 2007). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, several<br />

works on lab speech show that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tervention of contrast activates specific prosodic effects,<br />

whenever it appears <strong>in</strong> association with ei<strong>the</strong>r focus (Breen et al. 2010) or topic (Braun/Laid<br />

2003). The aim of <strong>the</strong> work is threefold: i) to verify <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that contrast is encoded<br />

syntactically, by <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g if it triggers phras<strong>in</strong>g effects at <strong>the</strong> syntax/phonology <strong>in</strong>terface;<br />

ii) to understand which acoustic parameters play a role <strong>in</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g contrastive<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations (<strong>in</strong> both cases, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formational notion of contrast will be studied <strong>in</strong> isolation<br />

from ei<strong>the</strong>r focus or topic, <strong>in</strong> whole compliance with <strong>the</strong> assumption about its autonomy); iii)<br />

to speculate on which model of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>the</strong> different components of language<br />

best fits with <strong>the</strong> outcome of <strong>the</strong> analysis.<br />

Theoretical framework. The <strong>in</strong>vestigation of i) is couched with<strong>in</strong> Zubizarreta’s (2010)<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory on <strong>the</strong> syntax/phonology <strong>in</strong>terface. Instead of assum<strong>in</strong>g a hierarchy of prosodic<br />

constituents which is <strong>in</strong>dependent of syntax (see Selkirk 1986), <strong>the</strong> author proposes that <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ventory of prosodic categories could be reduced to boundaries which are dist<strong>in</strong>guished <strong>in</strong><br />

ter<strong>ms</strong> of strength. Crucially, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sertion of <strong>the</strong>se boundaries is sensitive to <strong>the</strong> difference<br />

among syntactic projections. Therefore, I propose that weak prosodic boundaries are <strong>in</strong>serted<br />

to <strong>the</strong> right of constituents related to lexical projections (be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir specifiers, complements<br />

or adjuncts), while strong prosodic boundaries are <strong>in</strong>serted to <strong>the</strong> right of constituents related<br />

to discourse projections (e.g., TopP, FocP). (1) shows how that weak prosodic boundaries are<br />

represented as s<strong>in</strong>gle brackets, while strong prosodic boundaries as sequences of right and left<br />

brackets.<br />

(1) (DELLA PASTA)(mangerò) stasera) per cena). [FocP DELLA PASTAi[IP pro mangerò stasera ti]]<br />

(SOME MEAT I will eat tonight for d<strong>in</strong>ner).<br />

ContrP might trigger <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sertion of a strong p-boundary, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is a discourse projection.<br />

Methods of <strong>the</strong> analysis. I set up a production experiment <strong>in</strong> which three Italian speakers<br />

were asked to read aloud some dialogues which were designed so that <strong>the</strong> same sentence<br />

appeared <strong>in</strong> five different discourse contexts. For example, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong><br />

constituent Michelangelo <strong>in</strong> (2) varied so that it ended up to be: i) an <strong>in</strong>formation focus<br />

(+FOC); ii) a contrastive focus (+FOC,+CONTR); iii) an exhaustive focus<br />

(+FOC,+EXHAUST) – <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with Horvath (2010), I assume that FocP encodes exhaustivity;<br />

iv) a ‘barely’ contrastive constituent (+CONTR) followed by an <strong>in</strong>formation focus; v) nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

focused nor contrastive (-FOC,-CONTR).<br />

(2) Ho ripassato Michelangelo con la mia amica. (I reviewed Michelangelo with my friend).<br />

Up to now, <strong>the</strong> analysis has been carried out over 70 sentences and it will be extended <strong>in</strong> future.<br />

In order to verify if contrast is encoded syntactically, I measured <strong>the</strong> duration of <strong>the</strong> poststressed<br />

str<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> target words. The rationale beh<strong>in</strong>d this choice is that syllables preced<strong>in</strong>g<br />

strong prosodic boundaries are traditionally taken to undergo leng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g processes.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, <strong>the</strong> duration of post-stressed material with<strong>in</strong> contrastive constituents might be<br />

greater than that with<strong>in</strong> non-contrastive ones, if contrast is actually encoded <strong>in</strong> a dedicated<br />

functional projection (ContrP). In order to verify if contrast triggers specific prosodic effects,<br />

I labeled <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tonation pattern of each target constituent (TOBI annotation system) and I<br />

measured both <strong>the</strong> duration and <strong>the</strong> range of its stressed syllable.<br />

Results. As for <strong>the</strong> duration of <strong>the</strong> prosodic boundaries, I found that <strong>the</strong>re is a statistically<br />

significant difference between <strong>the</strong> values relative to exhaustive foci and those relative to each<br />

of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretations (see Figure1 as an example). This suggests that only


exhaustive foci trigger <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sertion of strong prosodic boundaries (as predicted by <strong>the</strong><br />

syntax/phonology model with<strong>in</strong> which my analysis is couched). The phonological analysis<br />

reveals that <strong>the</strong>re is no systematic correlation between <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tervention of contrast and <strong>the</strong> use<br />

of a particular type of accent (Figure2). On <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong> acoustical analysis shows that<br />

contrast always correlates with a greater duration and a higher pitch range of <strong>the</strong> stressed<br />

syllable with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> target constituent (Figure3).<br />

Conclusions and implications. My analysis suggests that contrast is not encoded <strong>in</strong> a<br />

dedicated functional projection (vs. Frascarelli/H<strong>in</strong>terhölz). The hypo<strong>the</strong>sis about <strong>the</strong><br />

existence of ContrP see<strong>ms</strong> to be challenged by o<strong>the</strong>r relevant data, like <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

contrastive constituents can appear both <strong>in</strong>-situ and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> left-periphery and that <strong>the</strong>y can be<br />

freely recursive across <strong>the</strong> CP (3) and <strong>the</strong> IP, which challenges <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis of a one-to-one<br />

correspondence between syntactic projections and semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretations.<br />

(3) A: Il nonno ha lasciato l’orologio a suo fratello? B: Non lo so, ma la scacchiera a suo nipote l’ha<br />

lasciata. (A: Did <strong>the</strong> grandpa bequeath <strong>the</strong> clock to his bro<strong>the</strong>r? B: I don’t know, but it is to his<br />

grandson that he bequea<strong>the</strong>d <strong>the</strong> chessboard).<br />

More <strong>in</strong> general, <strong>the</strong> analysis suggests that on <strong>the</strong> one hand <strong>the</strong>re is no phonological correlate<br />

of contrast and on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand <strong>the</strong>re are several acoustic parameters that express contrastive<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations. If this l<strong>in</strong>e of analysis is correct, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation on <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic encod<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

contrast provides empirical and conceptual evidence for <strong>the</strong> necessity to dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

phonology and phonetics as two different modules of grammar. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong><br />

syntax/phonology model assumed <strong>in</strong> this paper, phonology has a more direct connection with<br />

syntax than it is traditionally assumed <strong>in</strong> prosodic phonology. Assum<strong>in</strong>g C<strong>in</strong>que’s (1993)<br />

Stress Rule, both stress assignment and prosodic boundaries <strong>in</strong>sertion turn out to apply<br />

directly to <strong>the</strong> syntactic tree. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, phonetics has been shown to be syntax-bl<strong>in</strong>d<br />

and sensitive to <strong>in</strong>terpretive dist<strong>in</strong>ctions. This last claim has significant implications for <strong>the</strong><br />

general model of <strong>the</strong> architecture of grammar.<br />

Figure1: Duration (<strong>ms</strong>.) of post-stressed<br />

material <strong>in</strong> contrastive foci and exhaustive<br />

foci.<br />

200<br />

150<br />

100<br />

50<br />

40<br />

30<br />

20<br />

10<br />

50<br />

0<br />

(+CONTR,+F<br />

OC)<br />

(+FOC,+EXH<br />

AUST)<br />

(+CONTR)<br />

(-CONTR,-<br />

FOC)<br />

0<br />

Figure3: Values of <strong>the</strong> range (Hz) of <strong>the</strong><br />

accented syllables <strong>in</strong> contrastive and noncontrastive<br />

contexts.<br />

Figure2: Frequency of <strong>in</strong>formational functions<br />

expressed by each type of accent.<br />

25<br />

20<br />

15<br />

10<br />

5<br />

0<br />

(+CONTR)<br />

(-FOC) (-CONTR)<br />

(+FOC)<br />

(+EXHAUST.)<br />

(+FOC)<br />

Essential bibliography: Breen M./E. Federenko/M.<br />

Wagner/E. Gibson, 2010, Acoustic correlates of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

structure, Language and Cognitive Processes 25(7/9), 1044-<br />

1098; C<strong>in</strong>que G., 1993, A null <strong>the</strong>ory of phrase and compound<br />

stress, LI 24(2), 239-282; Frascarelli, M./R. H<strong>in</strong>terhölzl, 2007,<br />

Types of topics <strong>in</strong> German and Italian, <strong>in</strong> S. W<strong>in</strong>kler/K.<br />

Schwabe (eds.), On Information Structure Mean<strong>in</strong>g and Form,<br />

A<strong>ms</strong>terdam/Philadelphia: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s, 87-116. Horvath J.,<br />

2010, "Discourse-Features", Syntactic Displacement and <strong>the</strong><br />

Status of Contrast, L<strong>in</strong>gua 120, 1346-1369; Selkirk E., 1986,<br />

On derived doma<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> sentence phonology, Phonology<br />

Yearbook3, 371-405; Zubizarreta M.L., 2010, The Syntax and<br />

Prosody of Focus: The Bantu-Italian Connection, Iberia 2(1),<br />

131-168.


Coppe van Urk (MIT)<br />

!<br />

" " "<br />

" #<br />

"<br />

$ %&'<br />

%&' ( $ ) * + * #*<br />

* , - "* ./ * * 0 * * / ,1<br />

2 " 2 % $3 4 5 6776869:'<br />

; % 4 5<br />

6776' / < % 677= 67&7'<br />

- 4 % 67&7' "<br />

" *<br />

; %6' %> 4<br />

"<br />

&?:&3 @ 6777'<br />

%6' " A A<br />

* %B'<br />

%B' C! A 4 A<br />

" " ; 8<br />

%9' ! C!<br />

> " "<br />

! " 4"<br />

" % 67&7'<br />

%D' C! A A<br />

%D' %@ 6777' " 4"<br />

" 8<br />

" 4"<br />

" " "<br />

! "#<br />

! "<br />

" ; 4" "<br />

;<br />

, % %= ''8<br />

%=' CE 2 A E 2<br />

" * "<br />

4 " * 8<br />

%:' CE 2 A<br />

,<br />

- ; $ 8<br />

%F' C, " A 4<br />

2 " A # 2<br />

"<br />

8


4 %677:' "<br />

< %< ' % &?=:' , ;<br />

4 ; 8<br />

%?' C< A A " . ! ( ! A " +<br />

< 8 ;<br />

; %G 5 E 4 677B3<br />

/ 677:' ><br />

* % " #$<br />

" C% '<br />

" # 4 ;<br />

%, H . I 677D'8<br />

%&7' CJ A


Kai von F<strong>in</strong>tel (MIT), Danny Fox (Hebrew U./MIT) & Sab<strong>in</strong>e Iatridou (MIT)<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>iteness as Maximal Informativeness<br />

The unified L<strong>in</strong>k-style semantics for <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite article relies on an <strong>in</strong>herent order<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

objects, a part-whole order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>in</strong>dividuals.<br />

(1) �<strong>the</strong>�(φ〈α,t〉) is def<strong>in</strong>ed only if <strong>the</strong>re is a maximal object x (based on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>herent<br />

order<strong>in</strong>g of elements <strong>in</strong> Dα), such that φ(x). When def<strong>in</strong>ed, �<strong>the</strong>�(φ) refers to<br />

that maximal object.<br />

The φ refers to <strong>the</strong> maximal φ-object: <strong>the</strong> unique φ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular case, <strong>the</strong> maximal<br />

plurality conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g all φ-<strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> plural case, and <strong>the</strong> maximal collection of<br />

φ-stuff <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mass case.<br />

We propose an alternative account: maximality is def<strong>in</strong>ed with respect to a different<br />

order<strong>in</strong>g, that of “relative <strong>in</strong>formativity” i.e. asymmetrical entailment. Strength relates<br />

propositions, but, when given a property, can be def<strong>in</strong>ed derivatively for <strong>in</strong>dividuals.<br />

(2) �<strong>the</strong>�(φ〈α,st〉) is def<strong>in</strong>ed only if <strong>the</strong>re is an object x such that φ(x) is <strong>the</strong> maximally<br />

<strong>in</strong>formative proposition among <strong>the</strong> true propositions of <strong>the</strong> form φ(. . .)<br />

(henceforth <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>formative object <strong>in</strong> φ). When def<strong>in</strong>ed, �<strong>the</strong>�(φ) refers to<br />

that most <strong>in</strong>formative φ-object.<br />

The most <strong>in</strong>formative <strong>in</strong>dividual with respect to property φ is that <strong>in</strong>dividual from<br />

whose be<strong>in</strong>g φ we can deduce <strong>the</strong> φ-ness of all o<strong>the</strong>r φ-<strong>in</strong>dividual.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> basic cases discussed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature, L<strong>in</strong>k’s def<strong>in</strong>ition and our alternative<br />

co<strong>in</strong>cide. Assume that John, Bill, and Sam are <strong>the</strong> only boys. Then <strong>the</strong> boys will denote<br />

<strong>the</strong> maximal plurality made up of those three <strong>in</strong>dividuals, both on L<strong>in</strong>k’s account (s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

that is <strong>the</strong> maximal boy-plurality) and on ours: <strong>the</strong> plurality made up of those three<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals is exactly that plurality from whose be<strong>in</strong>g all boys we can deduce <strong>the</strong> boyness<br />

of any of its components. Any smaller plurality would be less <strong>in</strong>formative (from<br />

John and Bill be<strong>in</strong>g boys we can’t deduce that Sam is a boy).<br />

In fact, both L<strong>in</strong>k’s proposal and ours make <strong>the</strong> same prediction for any property<br />

that is upward monotone <strong>in</strong> a technical sense. Properties of degrees such as λd. John<br />

is d tall or λd. John has n many children are upward monotone (say<strong>in</strong>g that John has<br />

4 children is more <strong>in</strong>formative than say<strong>in</strong>g that he has 3). Hence under both accounts<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions such as John’s height or <strong>the</strong> number of children that John has will<br />

refer (<strong>in</strong> any world w) to <strong>the</strong> maximal object <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension of <strong>the</strong> property <strong>in</strong> w.<br />

Once we look at properties that are not upward monotone wrt <strong>in</strong>formativity, L<strong>in</strong>k’s<br />

proposal and ours make different predictions. First consider properties that are downward<br />

monotone. These are cases where <strong>the</strong> smallest amount/object is more <strong>in</strong>formative<br />

— unlike <strong>the</strong> earlier examples, which characterized cases where <strong>the</strong> largest object/amount<br />

is <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>formative. Here is such a case:<br />

(3) I have <strong>the</strong> amount of flour sufficient to bake a cake.<br />

Propositions of <strong>the</strong> form d-much flour is sufficient to bake a cake become more <strong>in</strong>formative<br />

<strong>the</strong> smaller d is. We thus correctly predict that <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description <strong>in</strong> (3) should<br />

refer to <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imum amount of flour that would yield a true proposition, i.e. to <strong>the</strong><br />

m<strong>in</strong>imum amount that would suffice for cake bak<strong>in</strong>g. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

1


L<strong>in</strong>k’s account, <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description <strong>in</strong> this sentence should be undef<strong>in</strong>ed, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re<br />

can be no maximal amount of flour that is sufficient to bake a cake; as noted by Beck<br />

and Rullmann (1999), <strong>in</strong> a slightly different context, if an amount of flour, f , suffices to<br />

bake a cake, so does any amount larger than f .<br />

So we see that a def<strong>in</strong>ite description of <strong>the</strong> form <strong>the</strong> φ alternates between referr<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

<strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imal or <strong>the</strong> maximal <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> monotonicity<br />

of <strong>the</strong> property φ. We get a maximality effect when φ is upward monotone and a<br />

m<strong>in</strong>imality effect when φ is downward monotone as <strong>in</strong> (3).<br />

Once <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is clear, it is easy to construct fur<strong>the</strong>r cases show<strong>in</strong>g a m<strong>in</strong>imality<br />

effect: consider, for example, <strong>the</strong> number of Greek soldiers who toge<strong>the</strong>r can destroy<br />

<strong>the</strong> Trojan army. For L<strong>in</strong>k, this would result <strong>in</strong> a presupposition failure, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no maximal number of Greek soldiers that toge<strong>the</strong>r can destroy <strong>the</strong> Trojan army (<strong>the</strong><br />

more <strong>the</strong> merrier). For us, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong> description will pick out <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imal<br />

number of soldiers that toge<strong>the</strong>r can destroy <strong>the</strong> Trojan army, because that is <strong>the</strong> most<br />

<strong>in</strong>formative such number (once we know that number we can deduce that all larger<br />

numbers would also do).<br />

We conclude that L<strong>in</strong>k’s <strong>the</strong>ory got <strong>the</strong> right results only because <strong>the</strong> focus was<br />

limited to upward monotone properties.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>the</strong>re are properties that are non-monotone. For <strong>the</strong>se, we predict a presupposition<br />

failure when <strong>the</strong>re is no unique <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension of <strong>the</strong> property.<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g. You are try<strong>in</strong>g to fit books (x, y, z, w, v . . . ) on shelves of various<br />

size (a, b, c . . . ). Suppose that book x toge<strong>the</strong>r with book y fit perfectly on shelf a, and<br />

book x, y, and z toge<strong>the</strong>r fit perfectly on shelf b. Suppose also that no o<strong>the</strong>r comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

of books fits perfectly on a shelf. Under L<strong>in</strong>k’s proposal, <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description <strong>in</strong><br />

#Pass me <strong>the</strong> books that toge<strong>the</strong>r fit perfectly on a shelf should be acceptable: it should<br />

refer to <strong>the</strong> larger collection of books that fit perfectly on a shelf, namely, x + y + z. Our<br />

analysis, <strong>in</strong> contrast, correctly predicts that <strong>the</strong> description suffers from presupposition<br />

failure.<br />

An alternation similar to <strong>the</strong> one between m<strong>in</strong>imality and maximality shows up <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of times as well. In (4) <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description refers to <strong>the</strong> latest time, t,<br />

such that Bill lived <strong>in</strong> Boston until t, while <strong>in</strong> (5) <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite refers to <strong>the</strong> earliest time, t,<br />

such that Bill has lived <strong>in</strong> Boston s<strong>in</strong>ce t.<br />

(4) January 5th 1999 is <strong>the</strong> date until which Bill had lived <strong>in</strong> Boston.<br />

(5) January 5th 1999 is <strong>the</strong> date s<strong>in</strong>ce which Bill has lived <strong>in</strong> Paris.<br />

We expect this alternation and do not need to stipulate it <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> semantics of <strong>the</strong><br />

temporal operators until or s<strong>in</strong>ce. In both cases, <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description refers to <strong>the</strong><br />

most <strong>in</strong>formative time that satisfies <strong>the</strong> relevant property (λt. Bill had lived <strong>in</strong> Boston<br />

until t, <strong>in</strong> (6) and λt. Bill has lived <strong>in</strong> Paris s<strong>in</strong>ce t, <strong>in</strong> (7)). The difference, once aga<strong>in</strong>, has<br />

to do with <strong>the</strong> monotonicity of <strong>the</strong> property.<br />

2


Mat<strong>the</strong>w Wagers (UC Santa Cruz), Manuel Borja (Inetnon Amot yan Kutturan Natibu) & Sandra Chung (UC Santa Cruz)<br />

WH Agreement and <strong>the</strong> Tim<strong>in</strong>g of Unbounded Dependency Formation:<br />

a Chamorro perspective on <strong>in</strong>crementality and accuracy <strong>in</strong> language comprehension<br />

SUMMARY. The comprehension of unbounded 1iller-­‐gap dependencies proceeds actively<br />

and predictively: comprehenders posit gaps <strong>in</strong> particular syntactic positions before direct<br />

evidence that a constituent does not already occupy that position [1]. Evidence for active<br />

comprehension comes from a number of psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic paradig<strong>ms</strong> and varied (majority)<br />

languages [2]. An important question concerns <strong>the</strong> sources and timecourse availability of<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation that shapes a comprehender’s expectations about <strong>the</strong> unbounded dependency.<br />

Island constra<strong>in</strong>ts are known to immediately restrict comprehenders’ hypo<strong>the</strong>ses: gaps are<br />

not predicted <strong>in</strong> doma<strong>in</strong>s where <strong>the</strong>y could not be licensed [3]. Lexically-­‐projected<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation, like subcategorization and argument structure, can also provide clues to <strong>the</strong><br />

likely role of <strong>the</strong> extracted phrase. There is less empirical clarity about how those clues<br />

affect <strong>the</strong> comprehender’s predictions [4-­‐6], and, <strong>in</strong> particular, what happens when<br />

expectations are formed before lexical access of <strong>the</strong> verb [7].<br />

Here we <strong>in</strong>vestigate real-­‐time sentence comprehension <strong>in</strong> Chamorro, whose<br />

grammar provides a morphological cue to <strong>the</strong> extraction site via its system of WH<br />

Agreement [8]. We report two major 1<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs: 1irst, displaced objects are only actively<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically when <strong>the</strong> verb is (optionally) <strong>in</strong>1lected for WH Agreement.<br />

Secondly, when <strong>the</strong> verb occurs <strong>in</strong> its un<strong>in</strong>1lected form, comprehenders none<strong>the</strong>less have<br />

dif1iculty re-­‐analyz<strong>in</strong>g an extraction which term<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong> a non-­‐object position -­‐ <strong>in</strong> our case,<br />

as a possessor. We argue this dif1iculty is a Chamorro analogue of <strong>the</strong> 1illed gap effect [9]. It<br />

suggests that comprehenders do actively posit a syntactic gap <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> un<strong>in</strong>1lected for<strong>ms</strong> even<br />

if <strong>the</strong>y don’t synchronously <strong>in</strong>terpret it, a conjecture recently made for English data [10].<br />

DESIGN. Chamorro is a verb-­‐<strong>in</strong>itial Austronesian language with some 40-­‐50,000 speakers,<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mariana Islands [8]. Of particular <strong>in</strong>terest is its system of WH Agreement: a<br />

transitive verb whose argument has been A-­‐bar extracted can be specially <strong>in</strong>1lected to<br />

re1lect <strong>the</strong> grammatical role of <strong>the</strong> extractee (as well as verbs along <strong>the</strong> extraction path) [8].<br />

As <strong>in</strong> example (1a), a subject extraction from a realis, transitive verb obligatorily triggers<br />

<strong>in</strong>1ixation of -­‐um-­‐ to <strong>the</strong> verb (cf. (1b), <strong>the</strong> unextracted version). Likewise, extractions of<br />

obliques obligatorily trigger a special verb form.<br />

(1)! (a)!Håyi na såstri l umåksi ! i magågu-mu?<br />

! ! who !L sea<strong>ms</strong>tress WH[nom].sew D clo<strong>the</strong>s-AGR?<br />

! ! “Which sea<strong>ms</strong>tress sewed your clo<strong>the</strong>s?”<br />

! (b)! Ha-låksi i såstri i magågu-mu<br />

! ! AGR-sew D sea<strong>ms</strong>tress D clo<strong>the</strong>s-AGR<br />

“The sea<strong>ms</strong>tress sewed your clo<strong>the</strong>s”<br />

Crucially, however, WH <strong>in</strong>1lection for object extractions is optional. Thus <strong>in</strong> (2a), <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

penta (‘pa<strong>in</strong>t’) is realized with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>1ix -­‐<strong>in</strong>-­‐ and a 2nd Person agreement suf1ix -mu. But <strong>in</strong><br />

(2b), <strong>the</strong> agreement, un-, is <strong>the</strong> same as found <strong>in</strong> clauses with no extractions.<br />

(2)! (a)!Håfa na tråk p <strong>in</strong>entåm-mu! ta’lu un biåhi?<br />

! ! what!L truck WH[obj].pa<strong>in</strong>t-AGR aga<strong>in</strong> a time<br />

! (b)! Håfa na tråk un penta ta’lu un biåhi?<br />

! ! what!L truck AGR-pa<strong>in</strong>t aga<strong>in</strong> a time<br />

! ! BOTH: “Which truck did you pa<strong>in</strong>t over aga<strong>in</strong>?


The optionality of WH <strong>in</strong>1lection for object extractions for<strong>ms</strong> <strong>the</strong> basis for two real-­‐<br />

time sentence comprehension studies that might elucidate how predictions with different<br />

sources <strong>in</strong>teract with <strong>the</strong> time-­‐courses of active comprehension. The WH <strong>in</strong>1lection<br />

morpheme provides a clear cue <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put for a particular analysis of <strong>the</strong> extractee,<br />

whereas an un<strong>in</strong>1lected form supplies a more <strong>in</strong>direct cue: <strong>the</strong> absence of obligatory subject<br />

or oblique extraction morphology is compatible with an object extraction. Moreover a non-­‐<br />

WH-­‐<strong>in</strong>1lected form is also used when <strong>the</strong> possessor of <strong>the</strong> object phrase is extracted (3).<br />

(3)! ! Håfa na tråk un penta ta’lu sanme’nåñ-ña?<br />

! ! what L truck! AGR pa<strong>in</strong>t aga<strong>in</strong> truck-AGR<br />

! ! “Which truck did you pa<strong>in</strong>t its front aga<strong>in</strong>?”<br />

Previous research suggests that comprehenders can immediately discard an object analysis<br />

if an extractee’s semantic features are <strong>in</strong>compatible with <strong>the</strong> verb and <strong>the</strong> verb’s argument<br />

structure signals o<strong>the</strong>r gap sites (e.g. object control verbs like persuade)[4]. Thus a non-­‐<br />

WH-­‐<strong>in</strong>1lected verb could forestall active comprehension ei<strong>the</strong>r by (a) signall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> object<br />

analysis more slowly; or (b) clue<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> possibility of possessor extraction.<br />

To test whe<strong>the</strong>r active comprehension was dim<strong>in</strong>ished for un<strong>in</strong>1lected for<strong>ms</strong>, we<br />

crossed <strong>the</strong> semantic plausibility of an extractee as verb’s object [±PLAUS.OBJ] with <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of WH <strong>in</strong>1lection [±WH.INFLECT]: (4)-­‐(5). We probed for an effect of semantic<br />

anomaly on <strong>the</strong> verb <strong>in</strong> two paradig<strong>ms</strong>: <strong>in</strong> Self-paced Listen<strong>in</strong>g, 40 native Chamorro<br />

speakers listened <strong>in</strong> an auditory mov<strong>in</strong>g w<strong>in</strong>dow paradigm and judged whe<strong>the</strong>r sentence<br />

made sense. In Passive Listen<strong>in</strong>g+Eye track<strong>in</strong>g, 72 native speakers listened to <strong>the</strong><br />

sentences passively and made <strong>the</strong> same judgement. Large ‘yes’/’no’ buttons were depicted<br />

on screen; participants’ gaze was recorded via a laptop webcam and later coded bl<strong>in</strong>d by a<br />

team of RAs unaware of <strong>the</strong> experimental manipulation. In both experiments <strong>the</strong>re were 12<br />

target ite<strong>ms</strong> and 28 ite<strong>ms</strong> counterbalanc<strong>in</strong>g for o<strong>the</strong>r factors. Experiments took place on<br />

Saipan, T<strong>in</strong>ian & Luta and all <strong>in</strong>structions, audio and text were <strong>in</strong> Chamorro.<br />

(4) (a)! [+PLAUS.OBJ, +WH.INFLECT]:! ! ⇢(2a)<br />

! (b)! [-PLAUS.OBJ, +WH.INFLECT]:<br />

! ! Håyi na ma’estru p<strong>in</strong>entåm-mu! ta’lu un biåhi?<br />

! ! who! L teacher WH[obj].pa<strong>in</strong>t-AGR aga<strong>in</strong> a time<br />

! ! “Which teacher did you pa<strong>in</strong>t over aga<strong>in</strong>?”<br />

(5)! (a)! [+PLAUS.OBJ, -WH.INFLECT]:! ⇢(3)<br />

! (b)! [-PLAUS.OBJ, -WH.INFLECT]:<br />

! ! Håyi na ma’estru un penta ta’lu tråk-ña?<br />

! ! what L teacher AGR pa<strong>in</strong>t aga<strong>in</strong> truck-AGR<br />

! ! “Which teacher did you pa<strong>in</strong>t his truck aga<strong>in</strong>?”<br />

For WH <strong>in</strong>1lected for<strong>ms</strong>, we 1<strong>in</strong>d clear evidence of active <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong><br />

extractee, as <strong>in</strong>dicated by <strong>in</strong>creased listen<strong>in</strong>g times on <strong>the</strong> verb or <strong>in</strong>creased likelihood of<br />

look<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> ‘no’ response button when -PLAUS.OBJ. For un<strong>in</strong>1lected for<strong>ms</strong>, nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

those effects are observed. However participants did systematically disprefer <strong>the</strong> possessor<br />

extractions if <strong>the</strong> extractee were -PLAUS.OBJ. We <strong>in</strong>terpret this as evidence that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

do beg<strong>in</strong> syntactic construction of <strong>the</strong> object analysis but have dif1iculty reanalyz<strong>in</strong>g<br />

[1] Frazier, L., & Flores D’Arcais, G. B. (1989). [2] Aoshima, S., Phillips, C., and We<strong>in</strong>berg, A. S. (2004).<br />

[3] Phillips, C. (2006). [4] Boland, J.E., et al. (1995) [5] Picker<strong>in</strong>g, M. & Traxler, M. (2003). [6] Staub<br />

2007. [7] Omaki et al. (2011) [8] Chung (1998) [9] Stowe (1986). [10] Wagers & Phillips (2009) [11]<br />

Ferreira et al. (1996).


Conjunct
Morphology
Marks
Property
Self­Ascription
<br />


<br />

Conjunct/Disjunct
(CJ/DJ)
languages
lack
person
mark<strong>in</strong>g
on
verbs,
employ<strong>in</strong>g
<strong>in</strong>stead
a
<br />

special
 CJ
 verb
 form
 when
 (i)
 <strong>the</strong>
 subject
 of
 a
 declarative
 is
 1st
 person
 (1),
 (ii)
 <strong>the</strong>
<br />

subject
of
a
question
is
2nd
person
(5),
or
(iii)
<strong>the</strong>
verb
appears
<strong>in</strong>
a
de
se
attitude
report
<br />

(7).

The
DJ
form
appears
elsewhere.

Exs.
from
Kathmandu
Newar
(Hargreaves
2005):
<br />


<br />

1. jī:
 a:pwa
 twan‐ā.
<br />


 1.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.CJ
<br />


 ‘I
drank
a
lot/too
much.’
<br />


<br />

2. chā
 a:pwa
 twan‐a.
<br />


 2.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.DJ
<br />


 ‘You
drank
a
lot/too
much.’
<br />


<br />

3. wā:
 a:pwa
 twan‐a.
<br />


 
 3.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.DJ
<br />


 ‘S/he
drank
a
lot/too
much.’
<br />


<br />

Stephen Wechsler (Texas)<br />

4. jī:
 a:pwa
 twan‐a
 lā?
<br />


 
 1.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.DJ
Q
<br />


 ‘Did
I
dr<strong>in</strong>k
a
lot/too
much?’
<br />


<br />

5. chā
 a:pwa
 twan‐ā
 lā?
<br />


 2.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.CJ
Q
<br />


 ‘Did
you
dr<strong>in</strong>k
a
lot/too
much?’
<br />


<br />

6. wā:
 a:pwa
 twan‐a
 lā?
<br />


 
 3.ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.DJ
Q
<br />


 ‘Did
s/he
dr<strong>in</strong>k
a
lot/too
much?’
<br />

7. Syām‐ā
 a:pwa
 twan‐ā
 hā.
<br />


 Syam‐ERG
 much
 dr<strong>in</strong>k‐PST.CJ
 EVD
<br />


 ‘Syami
said
that
hei
drank
too
much.’
<br />


<br />

CJ/DJ
syste<strong>ms</strong>
have
been
observed
<strong>in</strong>
S<strong>in</strong>o‐Tibetan,
e.g.
Newar
(Hale
1980;
Hargreaves
<br />

2005);
 Nakh‐Daghestanian,
 e.g.
Akhvakh
 (Creissels
 2008)
 and
Mehwb
 Dargwa
(Bickel
<br />

2008);
 Tsafiki
 (Barbacoan;
 Dick<strong>in</strong>son
 2000);
 Trans
 New
 Gu<strong>in</strong>ea,
 e.g.
 Oksapm<strong>in</strong>
<br />

(Loughnane
 2009),
 Duna
 and
 Kaluli
 (San
 Roque
 2011);
 Guambiano
 (Norcliffe
 2011);
<br />

Cha’palaa
(Floyd
2011).


<br />


 Conjunct
mark<strong>in</strong>g
forces
a
hard
look
at
a
key
question
of
<strong>the</strong>
GLOW
colloquium:
<br />

<strong>the</strong>
pragmatics‐grammar
<strong>in</strong>terface.

We
put
forth
<strong>the</strong>
hypo<strong>the</strong>sis
that
conjunct
(CJ)
verb
<br />

morphology
 marks
 a
 verb
 phrase
 as
 denot<strong>in</strong>g
 a
 doxastic
 self­ascribed
 property.

<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g
recent
work
by
Hans
Kamp,
reference
de
se
is
modeled
under
<strong>the</strong>
assumption
<br />

that
‘self‐attribut<strong>in</strong>g
thoughts
take
<strong>the</strong>
form
of
predications
of
a
special
s<strong>in</strong>gular
term
<br />

that
‘represents
<strong>the</strong>
self’
to
<strong>the</strong>
agent
as
her
self.

We
use
<strong>the</strong>
symbol
i
to
play
this
part.’
<br />

(Kamp
2011,
7).

Crucially,
we
posit
a
special
type
for
i.

A
conjunct‐VP
is
a
function
from
<br />

i‐type
 ter<strong>ms</strong>
 to
 beliefs.
 We
 dist<strong>in</strong>guish
 <strong>in</strong>dividual
 <strong>in</strong>terlocutors’
 discourse
<br />

representations,
as
well
as
participant‐neutral
ones.
<br />


 This
hypo<strong>the</strong>sis
applies
to
uses
of
CJ
as
follows:

(i)
A
declarative
utterance
is
a
<br />

declaration
of
speaker
belief.

In
1st
person
subject
CJ
declaratives
<strong>the</strong>
speaker
declares
<br />

<strong>the</strong>
belief
that
results
from
self­ascrib<strong>in</strong>g
<strong>the</strong>
VP­denoted
property:
e.g.
<strong>in</strong>
1
that
belief
is
<br />

BEL(drank­too­much(i)).

(ii)
A
question
is
an
<strong>in</strong>ducement
to
<strong>the</strong>
addressee
to
declare
a
<br />

belief
iff
she
holds
it.

In
2nd
person
subject
CJ
questions
<strong>the</strong>
addressee
is
<strong>in</strong>duced
to
<br />

declare
<strong>the</strong>
belief
that
results
from
self‐ascrib<strong>in</strong>g
<strong>the</strong>
VP‐denoted
property
iff
she
holds
<br />

that
belief.

(iii)
Reported
speech
us<strong>in</strong>g
CJ
reports
someone’s
self‐ascription.



<br />


 Illustrat<strong>in</strong>g
 with
 1,4,
 7,
 [a:pwa
 twanā]VP
 translates
 roughly
 as
 BEL(λi.drank­toomuch(i)).
<br />

(More
 precisely,
 an
 attitude
 is
 modeled
 as
 a
 set
 with
 two
 elements,
 <strong>in</strong>
 this
<br />

case:
 an
 anchored
 entity
 representation
 designat<strong>in</strong>g
 i
 as
 speaker;
 and
 a
 pair<strong>in</strong>g
 of
 an
<br />

attitud<strong>in</strong>al
 mode,
 here
 BEL(ief),
 with
 a
 DRS
 whose
 universe
 conta<strong>in</strong>s
 a
 propositional
<br />

discourse
referent
s
and
a
condition
s:
drank­too­much’(i).)

In
1
<strong>the</strong>
speaker
declares



<strong>the</strong>
 belief
 result<strong>in</strong>g
 from
 self‐ascrib<strong>in</strong>g
 that
 property,
 namely
 β
 =
 BEL(drank­toomuch(i)).
<br />


 In
 4
 <strong>the</strong>
 addressee
 is
 <strong>in</strong>duced
 to
 declare
 β
 iff
 she
 hold
 it.
 
 In
 7
 Syam’s
<br />

declaration
of
β
is
reported.


<br />


 This
 hypo<strong>the</strong>sis
 leads
 to
 <strong>the</strong>
 follow<strong>in</strong>g
 explanation
 for
 why
 CJ/DJ
 languages
<br />

generally
lack
normal
person
mark<strong>in</strong>g
on
<strong>the</strong>
verb.

By
hypo<strong>the</strong>sis
CJ
is
for
property
self‐<br />

ascription.
 
In
 person‐mark<strong>in</strong>g,
 a
 subject
 pronoun
 is
 <strong>in</strong>corporated
 <strong>in</strong>to
 <strong>the</strong>
 verb.
 
 But
<br />

<strong>the</strong>n
it
saturates
<strong>the</strong>
subject
role,
produc<strong>in</strong>g
a
proposition,
so
<strong>the</strong>
property
is
no
longer
<br />

available
 and
 <strong>the</strong>
 form
 of
 <strong>the</strong>
 verb
 cannot
 specify
 <strong>the</strong>
 mode
 of
 ascription
 as
 self‐<br />

ascription.


<br />



 This
 also
 offers
 an
 approach
 to
 two
 cross‐l<strong>in</strong>guistic
 tendencies
 that
 have
 been
<br />

observed.
 
 (i)
 CJ
 is
 favored
 for
 properties
 for
 which
 self‐ascription
 is
 <strong>the</strong>
 most
 likely.

<br />

(Example:
Newar
CJ
is
restricted
to
verbs
of
<strong>in</strong>tentional
action
(Hargreaves
2005).)
(ii)
<br />

CJ
 is
 favored
 where
 non‐self‐ascription
 would
 violate
 social
 proscriptions
 aga<strong>in</strong>st
<br />

presum<strong>in</strong>g
 to
 know
 o<strong>the</strong>r
 people’s
 thoughts
 better
 than
 <strong>the</strong>y
 know
 <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves.
 
 The
<br />

particular
 restrictions
 vary
 cross‐l<strong>in</strong>guistically
 and
 can
 be
 grammaticalized.
 
 E.g.
 <strong>the</strong>
<br />

Newar
 restriction
 just
 noted
 applies
 even
 <strong>in</strong>
 a
 third
 person
 de
 se
 report
 (Hargreaves
<br />

2005,
ex.
64).


<br />


 As
far
as
we
know
this
is
<strong>the</strong>
first
formal
semantic
analysis
of
conjunct/disjunct
<br />

syste<strong>ms</strong>
to
be
proposed.

It
will
be
compared
to
previous
<strong>in</strong>formal
analyses
that
treat
CJ
<br />

mark<strong>in</strong>g
 as
 specify<strong>in</strong>g
 that
 <strong>the</strong>
 subject
 of
 <strong>the</strong>
 clause
 is
 <strong>the</strong>
 epistemic
 authority
 or
<br />

<strong>in</strong>formant:
 speaker
 of
 a
 declarative,
 addressee
 of
 a
 question.
 
 Bickel
 2008
 treats
 such
<br />

mark<strong>in</strong>g
 as
 <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g
 epistemic
 scope
 on
 an
 <strong>in</strong>dividual
 argument
 and
 reasons
 that
<br />

‘def<strong>in</strong>ite
 knowledge
 is
 possible
 only
 if
 <strong>the</strong>
 <strong>in</strong>formant
 is
 <strong>in</strong>
 fact
 identical
 with
 <strong>the</strong>
<br />

argument.’
(Bickel
2008,
6).

But
this
assumption
of
‘privileged
access’
is
controversial.

<br />

We
take
a
slightly
different
tack,
tak<strong>in</strong>g
de
se
attribution
as
<strong>the</strong>
basic
significance
of
CJ
<br />

and
o<strong>the</strong>r
effects
as
derivative.


<br />


 The
account
is
fairly
elegant,
but
requires
agent‐relative
DRS’s.


These
have
been
<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependently
 motivated
 by
 speaker‐addressee
 knowledge
 asymmetries
 <strong>in</strong>
 epistemic
<br />

specificity
(H.
Kamp
and
Bende‐Farkas
2006)
and
person‐number
paradigm
universals
<br />

(Wechsler
2010).



<br />


<br />

Bickel,
 Balthasar.
 2008.
 VerbAgreement
 and
 EpistemicMark<strong>in</strong>g:
 a
 Typological
 Journey
<br />

from
 <strong>the</strong>
 Himalayas
 to
 <strong>the</strong>
 Caucasus.
 In
 Festschrift
 für
 Roland
 Bielmeier,
 ed.
<br />

Chomolangma,
 Demawend,
 and
 Kasbek,
 1–14.
 •
 Creissels,
 Denis.
 2008.
 “Person
<br />

variations
 <strong>in</strong>
 Akhvakh
 verb
 morphology:
 functional
 motivation
 and
 orig<strong>in</strong>
 of
 an
<br />

uncommon
 pattern.”
 STUF­Language
 Typology
 and
 Universals
 61
 (4):
 309–325.
 •
<br />

Dick<strong>in</strong>son,
C.
2000.
“Mirativity
<strong>in</strong>
Tsafiki.”
Studies
<strong>in</strong>
Language
24
(2)
(September):
379‐<br />

422.

•
Floyd,
Simeon.
2011.
Conjunct/disjunct
mark<strong>in</strong>g
<strong>in</strong>
Cha’palaa
HANDOUT.
•
Hale,
<br />

A.
1980.
“Person
markers:
F<strong>in</strong>ite
conjunct
and
disjunct
verb
for<strong>ms</strong>
<strong>in</strong>
Newari.”
Papers
<strong>in</strong>
<br />

South­East
 Asian
 <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>
 7:
 95–106.
 •
 Hargreaves,
 David.
 2005.
 “Agency
 and
<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional
action
<strong>in</strong>
Kathmandu
Newar.”
Himalayan
<strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>
5:
1–48.
•
Kamp,
H.,
and
<br />

A.
 Bende‐Farkas.
 2006.
 “Epistemic
 specificity
 from
 a
 communication‐<strong>the</strong>oretic
<br />

perspective.”
unpublished
<strong>ms</strong>.,
University
of
Stuttgart.
•
Kamp,
Hans.
2011.
Represent<strong>in</strong>g
<br />

De
Se
Thoughts
and
<strong>the</strong>ir
Reports
presented
at
<strong>the</strong>
Workshop
on
De
Se
Attitudes,
March
<br />

16‐18,
 2011,
 Rio
 de
 Janeiro.
 •
 Loughnane,
 Robyn.
 2009.
 A
 grammar
 of
 Oksapm<strong>in</strong>.
 •
<br />

Norcliffe,
Elisabeth.
2011.
Conjunct/disjunct
patterns
<strong>in</strong>
Guambiano.
LSA
<strong>in</strong>stitute.
•
San
<br />

Roque,
 Lila.
 2011.
 An
 <strong>in</strong>troduction
 to
 conjunct/disjunct
 alignment
 <strong>in</strong>
 Duna
 and
 Kaluli
<br />

(Trans
New
Gu<strong>in</strong>ea).
•
Wechsler,
Stephen.
2010.
“What
‘you’
and
‘I’
mean
to
each
o<strong>the</strong>r:
<br />

Person
<strong>in</strong>dexicals,
self‐ascription,
and
<strong>the</strong>ory
of
m<strong>in</strong>d.”
Language
86
(2):
332‐365.



Masaya Yoshida (Northwestern), Chizuru Nakao (Daito Bunka) & Iván Ortega-Santos (Memphis)<br />

On ellipsis structures <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a wh-remnant and a non-wh-remnant simultaneously<br />

Introduction: While both Sluic<strong>in</strong>g and Stripp<strong>in</strong>g have received detailed attention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field<br />

of generative grammar, this is not <strong>the</strong> case for ellipsis structures that <strong>in</strong>volve both a whremnant<br />

and a non-wh-remnant simultaneously. Typical examples are found <strong>in</strong> (1)-(2).<br />

(1) A: He oído que Juan ama a María. Spanish<br />

I heard that Juan loves to María.<br />

B: Por qué [XP a María] (y no a Susana)?<br />

Why [XP to Mary] (but not to Susana)?<br />

B: Why [XP Mary] (but not Susan)?<br />

(2) A: Alguno de estos tíos estaba comiendo chorizo.<br />

One of <strong>the</strong>se guys was eat<strong>in</strong>g chorizo.<br />

B: ¿Y cuál de ellos PAELLA?<br />

and which of <strong>the</strong>m paella?<br />

In spite of <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se constructions look superficially similar, one <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> goals of<br />

this paper is to show that <strong>the</strong>y are two dist<strong>in</strong>ct construction types, namely, Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

where <strong>the</strong> wh-element is restricted to why, and ano<strong>the</strong>r phrase, a remnant, which is identical<br />

to an element <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent clause, (e.g. María), show up fragmentally, (1), as opposed to<br />

Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g, that is to say, which <strong>in</strong>volves a wh-element o<strong>the</strong>r than why, and a remnant<br />

which contrasts with a phrase <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent clause, (2). We show that remnants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

two constructions go through different operations and are located <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> different positions <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> syntactic structure. More specifically, we establish <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g clai<strong>ms</strong>: (a) Why-<br />

Stripp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>volves a a base-generated why and leftward movement of a focused non-wh<br />

phrase followed by clausal ellipsis; (b) Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>volves movement of wh-remnant<br />

followed by rightward movement of a focused phrase and clausal ellipsis (Nev<strong>in</strong>s 2008). To<br />

<strong>the</strong> best of our knowledge it is <strong>the</strong> first time those two construction types are thoroughly<br />

compared.<br />

Analysis: Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> clear opposition to Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g, allows for preposition<br />

strand<strong>in</strong>g (cf. (3) & (4)), shows effects of repair by ellipsis (cf. (5) & (6)), <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

clause may precede elided clause (cf. (7) & (8)), and is not clause-bound (cf. (5) & (9):<br />

(3) A: Juan habló con María en la fiesta. Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Juan talked with María <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> party<br />

B: Por qué (con) María?<br />

Why (with) María<br />

(4) A: Alguno de estos tíos habló con María. Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

B: ¿(Y) cuál de ellos *(CON) SUSANA?<br />

(and) which of <strong>the</strong>m with Susana?<br />

“(and) Which of <strong>the</strong>se guys with Susana?”<br />

(5) A: Juan jura que va a conocer [a una chica que habla francés]. Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Juan swears that he will meet to a girl who speaks French<br />

B: Por qué francés (y no alemán)?<br />

Why French (and not German)<br />

(6) A: Juan jura que va a conocer al hombre al que algunos de estos tíos le sirvió la<br />

Juan swears that he-will to meet <strong>the</strong> man to whom some of <strong>the</strong>se guys served <strong>the</strong><br />

paella. Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

paella<br />

B: *Y cuál de ellos el chorizo?<br />

And which of <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> chorizo<br />

(7) No sé por qué a ti, pero María quiere verte. Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Not know why to you, but María want to see-you<br />

(8) ?*No sé cuáles de ellos el chorizo, pero algunos de estos tíos se comieron la paella.


Not know which of <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> chorizo, but some of <strong>the</strong>se guys ate <strong>the</strong> paella Wh-Str.<br />

(9) A: Alguno de estos tíos negó que Juan hubiera hablado con María. Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Some of <strong>the</strong>se guys denied that Juan had talked with María<br />

B: *Y cuál de ellos con Susana?<br />

And which of <strong>the</strong>m with Susana<br />

Thus, Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g shows signature properties of leftward movement (e.g., Sluic<strong>in</strong>g; see<br />

Merchant 1999), whereas Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g shows signature properties of rightwards movement.<br />

As is well-known, rightward movement such as Heavy NP Shift (HNPS) does nei<strong>the</strong>r allow<br />

for long-distance movement, e.g. (10), nor for P-strand<strong>in</strong>g (Jayaseelan 1990, a.o.); see <strong>the</strong><br />

unacceptability of (11)b, as opposed to (11)c. Needless to say, if we are deal<strong>in</strong>g with<br />

movement to <strong>the</strong> right, this would expla<strong>in</strong> (8).<br />

(10) *Mary said [that John broke tx] to her mo<strong>the</strong>r [<strong>the</strong> statue that he had spent <strong>the</strong><br />

whole summer carv<strong>in</strong>g]x.<br />

(11) a. John counted on a total stranger for support.<br />

b. *John counted on for support a total stranger.<br />

c. John counted for support on a total stranger. (Jayaseelan 1990: 66)<br />

Crucially, both Why and Wh-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>volve a full-fledged syntactic structure at <strong>the</strong><br />

ellipsis site as shown by connectivity effects such as selectional restrictions and b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

connectivity. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, w.r.t. analysis of Why-Stripp<strong>in</strong>g, given <strong>the</strong> standard assumption<br />

that wh-phrases o<strong>the</strong>r than Why land <strong>in</strong> [Spec,FocP], we expect those o<strong>the</strong>r wh-phrases to be<br />

unable to co-occur with <strong>the</strong> (repeated) focused XP. The prediction is fulfilled, (12).<br />

(12) A: Juan besó a María.<br />

Juan kissed to María<br />

B: Por qué a María?/ *Dónde a María?/*Cuándo a María?/*Quién a María?<br />

B: Why to María?/*Where to María?/*When to María?/*Who to María?<br />

In turn, we assume that <strong>the</strong> remnants must escape <strong>the</strong> ellipsis <strong>in</strong> order to be pronounced, and<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rwise-covert focus movement is manifested overtly only under ellipsis (see Nakao 2008<br />

for a similar approach to Stripp<strong>in</strong>g). Under current <strong>the</strong>oretical assumption where <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

overt/covert movement dist<strong>in</strong>ction, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a choice on which copy of <strong>the</strong> movement cha<strong>in</strong><br />

to pronounce, this means that PF constra<strong>in</strong>ts force <strong>the</strong> pronunciation of <strong>the</strong> upper copy. We<br />

claim that <strong>the</strong> situation is parallel to Multiple Sluic<strong>in</strong>g. Although <strong>the</strong> second wh-phrase<br />

usually undergoes covert wh-movement, (13), it can escape <strong>the</strong> TP only when <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

ellipsis, (14) (see Lasnik 2006 and references <strong>the</strong>re<strong>in</strong>, for discussions on Multiple Sluic<strong>in</strong>g):<br />

(13) a. Qué compré yo para quién?<br />

What bought I for who?<br />

b. *Qué para quién compré yo?<br />

What for who bought I<br />

(14) (?)Yo compré algo para alguien, pero no recuerdo [CP qué1 para quién2 [IP<br />

I bought someth<strong>in</strong>g for somebody, but not remember.I what for who<br />

yo compré t1 t2]].<br />

I bought t1 t2<br />

References<br />

Jayaseelan, Karattuparambil. A. 1990. Incomplete Vp Deletion and Gapp<strong>in</strong>g. L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Analysis 20:64-81.<br />

Lasnik, Howard. 2006. Multiple Sluic<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> English. Ms. University of Maryland, College<br />

Park.<br />

Nev<strong>in</strong>s, Andrew. 2008. “Sluic<strong>in</strong>g ≠ Stripp<strong>in</strong>g: Evidence from P-Strand<strong>in</strong>g”. Paper presented<br />

at The 3rd Annual Moscow Student Conference on <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong>, Moscow, April 2008.<br />

Merchant, J. 1999. The syntax of silence: Sluic<strong>in</strong>g, islands and identity <strong>in</strong> ellipsis. Ph.D. Diss,<br />

UCSC.


Association with traces and <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory of movement<br />

In this talk I give a pr<strong>in</strong>cipled account for <strong>the</strong> observation that exclusive only must associate with a focus<br />

with<strong>in</strong> its complement (Tancredi’s (1990) Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Lexical Association; PLA), utiliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

of movement and associated work on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of traces. Previous explanations for this fact come<br />

from <strong>the</strong> idea that traces cannot be F-marked. I argue contra Beaver and Clark (2008) that traces (lower<br />

copies of movement cha<strong>in</strong>s) can <strong>in</strong> fact be F-marked and that this is exemplified <strong>in</strong> F-mark<strong>in</strong>g conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong><br />

quantifiers which undergo QR. Instead, PLA effects arise through <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of focus alternatives of<br />

<strong>the</strong> predicate <strong>in</strong> both <strong>the</strong> higher and lower copies of of <strong>the</strong> moved constituent. When <strong>the</strong> higher copy and<br />

lower copy are not both under <strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> exclusive operator, we yield <strong>in</strong>compatible requirements on<br />

<strong>the</strong> variables be<strong>in</strong>g quantified over, caus<strong>in</strong>g ei<strong>the</strong>r presupposition failure or contradiction.<br />

PLA and <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> art<br />

Michael Yoshitaka Erlew<strong>in</strong>e (MIT)<br />

Tancredi (1990) described <strong>the</strong> ungrammaticality of (1) as due to <strong>the</strong> PLA: a requirement that only associate<br />

with a constituent <strong>in</strong> its c-command doma<strong>in</strong> at S-structure. Beaver and Clark (2008) argue that this is an<br />

expected result if traces cannot be F-marked: without F-marked material <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> complement of only <strong>the</strong><br />

focus alternatives computed will be a s<strong>in</strong>gleton set and we cannot make a mean<strong>in</strong>gful assertion. In support<br />

of this view, Beaver and Clark note that “by def<strong>in</strong>ition, extraction gaps cannot be prosodically prom<strong>in</strong>ent”<br />

(Beaver and Clark, 2008, 172).<br />

(1) * [Which boy]i does John only like ti? (Tancredi, 1990)<br />

Intended: ‘Which boy x is such that John only likes [x]F ?’<br />

(2) ✓ Which boy is such thati John only likes [himi]F ?<br />

Example (2) shows that a bound variable, however, can <strong>in</strong>deed carry F-mark<strong>in</strong>g and give us <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g. This contrast between unpronounced traces and bound variables lends credence to this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis.<br />

F-mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower position: evidence from QR<br />

Aoun and Li (1993) noted that <strong>the</strong> PLA see<strong>ms</strong> to also affect <strong>the</strong> possible scopes of QR: (3) does not have an<br />

<strong>in</strong>verse-scope read<strong>in</strong>g due to <strong>the</strong> only and <strong>the</strong> F-mark<strong>in</strong>g on (part of) <strong>the</strong> QP. That <strong>the</strong> scope of focus-sensitive<br />

only <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>in</strong>terferes with QR can also be verified <strong>in</strong> Antecedent Conta<strong>in</strong>ed Deletion examples which must<br />

<strong>in</strong>voke QR <strong>in</strong> order to satisfy <strong>the</strong> identity requirements on ellipsis (Larson and May, 1990, a.o.). The two<br />

ellipsis resolutions <strong>in</strong> (4a) correspond to a choice of how high <strong>the</strong> quantifier is raised to—ei<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> edge<br />

of vP1 or vP2. However, <strong>in</strong> (4b) <strong>the</strong> larger ellipsis resolution is unavailable, <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>ability of <strong>the</strong> QP<br />

to move across only to <strong>the</strong> edge of vP1.<br />

(3) Someone only loves [QP every [boy]F <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> room]. (Aoun and Li, 1993)<br />

✓ someone > every boy, *every boy > someone<br />

(4) a. John [vP1 wanted to [vP2 read [QP every book that Mary did . ✓ “want to read,” ✓ “read”<br />

b. John [vP1 wanted to only [vP2 read [QP every book that [M]F did . *“want to read,” ✓ “read”<br />

As a covert movement operation, QR has been analyzed as movement with pronunciation of <strong>the</strong> foot of <strong>the</strong><br />

cha<strong>in</strong>. Examples such as (3) and (4b) <strong>the</strong>n arguably realize F-mark<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> lower position, correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to a trace position of an overt movement cha<strong>in</strong>. When <strong>the</strong> full paradigm of <strong>the</strong> PLA <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g its effect on<br />

QR is considered, its explanation as an <strong>in</strong>ability to realize F-mark<strong>in</strong>g on traces becomes untenable.<br />

Solution: F-mark<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> both higher and lower copies via <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory of movement<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory of movement, movement does not leave “traces” but <strong>in</strong>stead leaves full, lower copies.<br />

The lower copy is <strong>the</strong>n converted <strong>in</strong>to a def<strong>in</strong>ite description (with <strong>the</strong> restriction that it be equal to <strong>the</strong> variable<br />

<strong>in</strong> question) through a process of Trace Conversion (TC) (Fox, 2002; Rullmann and Beck, 1998).<br />

(5) “John read many books.” QR: [many books] λxi John read [many books]i<br />

TC: [many books] λx John read [<strong>the</strong> book x]<br />

F-mark<strong>in</strong>g itself is simply a syntactic feature on constituents (Jackendoff, 1972), and thus when a constituent


conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g F-mark<strong>in</strong>g moves, <strong>the</strong> F-mark<strong>in</strong>g is reta<strong>in</strong>ed on both copies. This triggers <strong>the</strong> generation of<br />

focus alternatives <strong>in</strong> both positions. If this movement happens with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope of only (Case I), we yield a<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gful assertion by elim<strong>in</strong>ation of self-contradictory alternatives when evaluat<strong>in</strong>g only. However, this<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ation of contradictory alternatives does not occur when <strong>the</strong> movement is out of <strong>the</strong> scope of only and<br />

we yield fatal presupposition failure (Case II).<br />

Case I (XP conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g F-mark<strong>in</strong>g moves with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope of only):<br />

“Every boy” QRs to <strong>the</strong> edge of vP, with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope of only, and <strong>the</strong> lower copy undergoes TC (a). There are<br />

now two F-marked boys <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure, and <strong>the</strong>y each <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> alternatives {boy, girl}. Compute �vP�f po<strong>in</strong>twise, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> four alternatives (b). (Box <strong>in</strong>dicates prejacent.) Elim<strong>in</strong>ate alternatives which produce<br />

logical contradictions (strikeouts <strong>in</strong> b). Compute only as normal: assert<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conjunction of negations of<br />

alternatives which are not entailed by <strong>the</strong> prejacent. The result<strong>in</strong>g assertion (c) is well-formed.<br />

(3a) a. TC: Someone λy . only [vP [every [boy]F ] λx . y loves [<strong>the</strong> [boy]F x] ]<br />

b. �vP�f { }<br />

=<br />

[every boy] λx . y loves [<strong>the</strong> boy x] , [every boy] λx . y loves [<strong>the</strong> girl x],<br />

[every girl] λx . y loves [<strong>the</strong> boy x], [every girl] λx . y loves [<strong>the</strong> girl x]<br />

c. Assert: <strong>the</strong>re exists a person y for which it is not <strong>the</strong> case that y loves every girl. �<br />

Case II (XP conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g F-mark<strong>in</strong>g moves out of <strong>the</strong> scope of only):<br />

“Every boy” QRs out above only, and <strong>the</strong> lower copy undergoes TC (a). Only <strong>the</strong> lower copy is with<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> vP, so <strong>the</strong>re are two alternatives computed at vP (b). The exclusive assertion <strong>the</strong>n makes reference to<br />

<strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description “<strong>the</strong> girl x” (c). The higher boy will trigger alternatives, but <strong>the</strong> assertion simply<br />

asserts <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary semantic value of <strong>the</strong> root, mean<strong>in</strong>g we will quantify over “every boy x.” The complete<br />

computation (d) attempts to compute <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description “<strong>the</strong> girl x” for “every boy x,” necessarily<br />

result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> presupposition failure for every <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantification!<br />

(3b) a. TC: [every [boy]F ] λx . someone λy . only [vP y loves [<strong>the</strong> [boy]F x] ]<br />

b. �vP� f = { y loves [<strong>the</strong> boy x] , y loves [<strong>the</strong> girl x] }<br />

c. �only vP� = ¬ y loves [<strong>the</strong> girl x]<br />

d. Assert: for every boy x, <strong>the</strong>re exists y, such that it is not <strong>the</strong> case that y loves [<strong>the</strong> girl x] �<br />

The contrast between traces and bound variables<br />

If <strong>the</strong> PLA is not due to a simple lack of F-mark<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> complement of only, we lose <strong>the</strong> trivial<br />

explanation for <strong>the</strong> contrast <strong>in</strong> (1–2). However, <strong>the</strong> contrast above (Case I–II) crucially arises due to <strong>the</strong><br />

presuppositions <strong>in</strong>troduced by <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite description <strong>in</strong>terpretation of lower copies via TC. Bound variables,<br />

however, are simple variables and thus can host F-mark<strong>in</strong>g without <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g conflict<strong>in</strong>g presuppositions.<br />

(6) No boy is such thati John only likes [himi]F = [no boy](λx.only John likes [x]F ) �<br />

Prediction: <strong>the</strong> PLA does not affect F-marked quantificational determ<strong>in</strong>ers<br />

As TC reta<strong>in</strong>s all of <strong>the</strong> predicative restriction of a quantifier but replaces <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>er with ι, F-mark<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ers <strong>the</strong><strong>ms</strong>elves are predicted to be immune to <strong>the</strong> PLA. As alternatives are not <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> two copies of <strong>the</strong> predicate, we avoid <strong>the</strong> issues <strong>in</strong> Case II above. This prediction is borne out.<br />

(3 ′ ) Someone only loves [ [most]F boys]. ✓ someone > most boys, ✓ most boys > someone<br />

Summary and implications<br />

The novel proposal presented here gives a unified explanation for PLA effects on both overt and covert<br />

movement, <strong>in</strong> a manner compatible with our recent, <strong>in</strong>dependently-motivated understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> copy <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

of movement. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction drawn here between bound variables and traces highlights <strong>the</strong> importance<br />

of our semantic denotations for “variables,” particularly as <strong>the</strong> lack of focus-islands has been used as an<br />

argument for non-movement analyses of wh-<strong>in</strong>-situ (Aoun and Li, 1993).


Peng Zhou, Stephen Cra<strong>in</strong> & Likan Zhan (Macquarie)<br />

Children’s pragmatic use of prosody <strong>in</strong> sentence process<strong>in</strong>g<br />

This study exam<strong>in</strong>ed 4-year-old Mandar<strong>in</strong>-speak<strong>in</strong>g children’s sensitivity to prosodic cues <strong>in</strong><br />

resolv<strong>in</strong>g speech act ambiguities, us<strong>in</strong>g eye-movement record<strong>in</strong>gs. Most previous on-l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

studies have focused on children’s use of prosody <strong>in</strong> resolv<strong>in</strong>g structural ambiguities and<br />

have found that, although children are able to use prosodic <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> on-l<strong>in</strong>e sentence<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>y use such <strong>in</strong>formation less effectively than adults. The present study takes<br />

advantage of special properties of Mandar<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese to <strong>in</strong>vestigate <strong>the</strong> role of prosody <strong>in</strong><br />

children’s on-l<strong>in</strong>e process<strong>in</strong>g of ambiguities <strong>in</strong> which prosody serves to signal <strong>the</strong><br />

illocutionary mean<strong>in</strong>g of an utterance (i.e., whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> speaker is ask<strong>in</strong>g a question or<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g a statement). Negative sentences with a wh-word like (1) are ambiguous <strong>in</strong> Mandar<strong>in</strong><br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>se. This sentence can ei<strong>the</strong>r be used to pose a question, as <strong>in</strong> (1a), or to make a statement,<br />

as <strong>in</strong> (1b). Prosodic cues are used to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between <strong>the</strong>se two speech acts. Ris<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase shenme shuiguo ‘what fruit’ <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> question read<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

whereas level <strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> same wh-phrase signals <strong>the</strong> statement read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(1) Yuehan meiyou zhai shenme shuiguo<br />

John not pick what fruit<br />

a. What fruit did John not pick? (ris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase)<br />

b. John didn’t pick any fruit. (level <strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase)<br />

Thirty-four monol<strong>in</strong>gual Mandar<strong>in</strong>-speak<strong>in</strong>g children (mean age 4;8, range 4;1 to 5; 5) and 30<br />

Mandar<strong>in</strong>-speak<strong>in</strong>g adults (mean age 25, range 23 to 26) were tested us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> visual world<br />

paradigm. Participants were presented with a spoken sentence (e.g., (1)) while view<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

picture (e.g., Fig.1.). Two prosodic versions of each target sentence were presented, one with<br />

ris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase (Question Prosody condition) and one with level<br />

<strong>in</strong>tonation on <strong>the</strong> same wh-phrase (Statement Prosody condition). Eye-movements were<br />

recorded us<strong>in</strong>g an EyeL<strong>in</strong>k 1000 eye tracker (remote function). Participants’ fixations were<br />

coded <strong>in</strong> three categories (see Fig.1.): <strong>the</strong> statement-compatible area (objects correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to <strong>the</strong> statement <strong>in</strong>terpretation), <strong>the</strong> question-compatible area (objects correspond<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong><br />

question <strong>in</strong>terpretation) and <strong>the</strong> irrelevant area (objects correspond<strong>in</strong>g to nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation). The proportion of fixations follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> subject NP (e.g.,<br />

Yuehan ‘John’) was computed <strong>in</strong> a time w<strong>in</strong>dow of 6000 <strong>ms</strong> for <strong>the</strong> two critical categories:<br />

<strong>the</strong> statement-compatible area and <strong>the</strong> question-compatible area. This 6000 <strong>ms</strong> time w<strong>in</strong>dow<br />

was broken down <strong>in</strong>to 20 segments, each with a duration of 300 <strong>ms</strong>.<br />

Figure 2 shows <strong>the</strong> proportion of fixations of adults and children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> question-compatible<br />

area (III) across <strong>the</strong> two prosodic conditions. Figure 3 summarizes <strong>the</strong> fixation proportions <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> statement-compatible area (I). The two figures <strong>in</strong>dicate that adults and children exhibited<br />

similar eye gaze patterns <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two critical areas <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two prosodic conditions. Hear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

wh-word with ris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tonation triggered <strong>in</strong>creased looks to <strong>the</strong> question-compatible area<br />

(Fig.2.) and hear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wh-word with level <strong>in</strong>tonation triggered <strong>in</strong>creased looks to <strong>the</strong><br />

statement-compatible area (Fig.3.). This prosodic effect found <strong>in</strong> children was as robust as it<br />

was <strong>in</strong> adults. The patterns were supported by fur<strong>the</strong>r statistical modell<strong>in</strong>g (mixed-effects<br />

logistic regression models). This f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g suggests that children are as sensitive as adults <strong>in</strong><br />

us<strong>in</strong>g prosody <strong>in</strong> on-l<strong>in</strong>e sentence process<strong>in</strong>g, when prosody is used to resolve a pragmatic<br />

ambiguity. Children are as good as adults <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pragmatic use of prosody <strong>in</strong> on-l<strong>in</strong>e sentence<br />

process<strong>in</strong>g.


Fig.1. Example of <strong>in</strong>terest areas<br />

Fig.2. Average fixation proportions over time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> question-compatible area (III) <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> two prosodic conditions, adults (left) and children (right)<br />

Fig.3. Average fixation proportions over time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> statement-compatible area (I) <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> two prosodic conditions, adults (left) and children (right)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!