06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

physical symbol system hypothesis: “the necessary and sufficient condition for a<br />

physical system to exhibit general intelligent action is that it be a physical symbol<br />

system” (Newell, 1980, p. 170). By necessary, Newell meant that if an artifact exhibits<br />

general intelligence, then it must be an instance <strong>of</strong> a physical symbol system. By<br />

sufficient, Newell claimed that any device that is a physical symbol system can be<br />

configured to exhibit general intelligent action—that is, he claimed the plausibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> machine intelligence, a position that Descartes denied.<br />

What did Newell (1980) mean by general intelligent action? He meant,<br />

the same scope <strong>of</strong> intelligence seen in human action: that in real situations behavior<br />

appropriate to the ends <strong>of</strong> the system and adaptive to the demands <strong>of</strong> the environment<br />

can occur, within some physical limits. (Newell, 1980, p. 170)<br />

In other words, human cognition must be the product <strong>of</strong> a physical symbol system.<br />

Thus human cognition must be explained by adopting all <strong>of</strong> the different levels <strong>of</strong><br />

investigation that were described in Chapter 2.<br />

3.7 Componentiality, Computability, and Cognition<br />

In 1840, computer pioneer Charles Babbage displayed a portrait <strong>of</strong> loom inventor<br />

Joseph Marie Jacquard for the guests at the famous parties in his home (Essinger,<br />

2004). The small portrait was incredibly detailed. Babbage took great pleasure in<br />

the fact that most people who first saw the portrait mistook it to be an engraving. It<br />

was instead an intricate fabric woven on a loom <strong>of</strong> the type that Jacquard himself<br />

invented.<br />

The amazing detail <strong>of</strong> the portrait was the result <strong>of</strong> its being composed <strong>of</strong> 24,000<br />

rows <strong>of</strong> weaving. In a Jacquard loom, punched cards determined which threads<br />

would be raised (and therefore visible) for each row in the fabric. Each thread in the<br />

loom was attached to a rod; a hole in the punched card permitted a rod to move,<br />

raising its thread. The complexity <strong>of</strong> the Jacquard portrait was produced by using<br />

24,000 punched cards to control the loom.<br />

Though Jacquard’s portrait was impressively complicated, the process used to<br />

create it was mechanical, simple, repetitive—and local. With each pass <strong>of</strong> the loom’s<br />

shuttle, weaving a set <strong>of</strong> threads together into a row, the only function <strong>of</strong> a punched<br />

card was to manipulate rods. In other words, each punched card only controlled<br />

small components <strong>of</strong> the overall pattern. While the entire set <strong>of</strong> punched cards represented<br />

the total pattern to be produced, this total pattern was neither contained<br />

in, nor required by, an individual punched card as it manipulated the loom’s rods.<br />

The portrait <strong>of</strong> Jacquard was a global pattern that emerged from a long sequence <strong>of</strong><br />

simple, local operations on the pattern’s components.<br />

78 Chapter 3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!