06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

and strong equivalence are reviewed, with the latter serving as the primary goal <strong>of</strong><br />

classical cognitive science.<br />

To say that two systems—such as a simulation and a human subject—are<br />

strongly equivalent is to say that both are solving the same information processing<br />

problem, using the same algorithm, based on the same architecture. Establishing<br />

strong equivalence requires collecting behavioural evidence <strong>of</strong> the types introduced<br />

in Chapter 2 (relative complexity, intermediate state, and error evidence) to reverse<br />

engineer a subject’s algorithm. It also requires discovering the components <strong>of</strong> a<br />

subject’s architecture, which involves behavioural evidence concerning cognitive<br />

impenetrability as well as biological evidence about information processing in the<br />

brain (e.g., evidence about which areas <strong>of</strong> the brain might be viewed as being information<br />

processing modules). In general, the search for strong equivalence by classical<br />

cognitive scientists involves conducting a challenging research program that can<br />

be described as functional analysis or reverse engineering.<br />

The reverse engineering in which classical cognitive scientists are engaged<br />

involves using a variety <strong>of</strong> research methods adopted from many different disciplines.<br />

This is because this research strategy explores cognition at all four levels<br />

<strong>of</strong> investigation (computational, algorithmic, architectural, and implementational)<br />

that were introduced in Chapter 2. The current chapter is organized in a fashion<br />

that explores computational issues first, and then proceeds through the remaining<br />

levels to end with some considerations about implementational issues <strong>of</strong> importance<br />

to classical cognitive science.<br />

3.1 <strong>Mind</strong>, Disembodied<br />

In the seventh century, nearly the entire Hellenistic world had been conquered<br />

by Islam. The Greek texts <strong>of</strong> philosophers such as Plato and Aristotle had already<br />

been translated into Syriac; the new conquerors translated these texts into Arabic<br />

(Kuhn, 1957). Within two centuries, these texts were widely available in educational<br />

institutions that ranged from Baghdad to Cordoba and Toledo. By the tenth century,<br />

Latin translations <strong>of</strong> these Arabic texts had made their way to Europe. Islamic<br />

civilization “preserved and proliferated records <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek science for later<br />

European scholars” (Kuhn, 1957, p. 102).<br />

The availability <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek texts gave rise to scholasticism in Europe<br />

during the middle ages. Scholasticism was central to the European universities that<br />

arose in the twelfth century, and worked to integrate key ideas <strong>of</strong> Greek philosophy<br />

into the theology <strong>of</strong> the Church. During the thirteenth century, scholasticism<br />

achieved its zenith with the analysis <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s philosophy by Albertus Magnus<br />

and Thomas Aquinas.<br />

56 Chapter 3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!