06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

perspectives could be taken? To accomplish this, the framework <strong>of</strong> cybernetics was<br />

exclusively mathematical. Cyberneticists investigated the input-output mappings <strong>of</strong><br />

machines by making general statements or deriving pro<strong>of</strong>s that were expressed in<br />

some logical or mathematical formalism.<br />

By the late 1950s, research in cybernetics proper had begun to wane (Conway<br />

& Siegelman, 2005); at this time cybernetics began to evolve into the modern field <strong>of</strong><br />

cognitive science (Boden, 2006; Gardner, 1984; Miller, 2003). Inspired by advances<br />

in digital computers, cognitive science was not interested in generic “machines” as<br />

such, but instead focused upon particular devices that could be described as information<br />

processors or symbol manipulators.<br />

Given this interest in symbol manipulation, one goal <strong>of</strong> cognitive science is to<br />

describe a device <strong>of</strong> interest in terms <strong>of</strong> the specific information processing problem<br />

that it is solving. Such a description is the result <strong>of</strong> performing an analysis at the<br />

computational level (Dawson, 1998; Marr, 1982; Pylyshyn, 1984).<br />

A computational analysis is strongly related to the formal investigations<br />

carried out by a cyberneticist. At the computational level <strong>of</strong> analysis, cognitive<br />

scientists use formal methods to prove what information processing problems a<br />

system can—and cannot—solve. The formal nature <strong>of</strong> computational analyses lend<br />

them particular authority: “The power <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> analysis resides in the fact<br />

that the discovery <strong>of</strong> valid, sufficiently universal constraints leads to conclusions<br />

. . . that have the same permanence as conclusions in other branches <strong>of</strong> science”<br />

(Marr, 1982, p. 331).<br />

However, computational accounts do not capture all aspects <strong>of</strong> information<br />

processing. A pro<strong>of</strong> that a device is solving a particular information processing<br />

problem is only a pro<strong>of</strong> concerning the device’s input-output mapping. It does not<br />

say what algorithm is being used to compute the mapping or what physical aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> the device are responsible for bringing the algorithm to life. These missing details<br />

must be supplied by using very different methods and vocabularies.<br />

2.8 Behaviour by Design and by Artifact<br />

What vocabulary is best suited to answer questions about the how a particular inputoutput<br />

mapping is calculated? To explore this question, let us consider an example<br />

calculating device, a Turing machine (Turing, 1936). This calculator processes symbols<br />

that are written on a ticker-tape memory divided into cells, where each cell can hold a<br />

single symbol. To use a Turing machine to add (Weizenbaum, 1976), a user would write<br />

a question on the tape, that is, the two numbers to be added together. They would be<br />

written in the format that could be understood by the machine. The Turing machine<br />

would answer the input question by reading and rewriting the tape. Eventually, it<br />

would write the sum <strong>of</strong> the two numbers on the tape—its answer—and then halt.<br />

Multiple Levels <strong>of</strong> Investigation 41

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!