06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mentioned in the current section are considered to be calculators for this reason.<br />

In spite <strong>of</strong> the many-levelled differences between the abacus, electronic calculator,<br />

difference engine, THROBACK, and slide rule, at a very abstract level—the level<br />

concerned with input-output mappings—these devices are equivalent.<br />

To summarize the discussion to this point, how might one explain calculating<br />

devices? There are at least four different approaches that could be taken, and each<br />

approach involves answering a different question about a device. What is its physical<br />

nature? What is its architecture? What procedures does it use to calculate? What<br />

input-output mapping does it compute?<br />

Importantly, answering each question involves using very different vocabularies<br />

and methods. The next few pages explore the diversity <strong>of</strong> these vocabularies.<br />

This diversity, in turn, accounts for the interdisciplinary nature <strong>of</strong> cognitive science.<br />

2.7 Formal Accounts <strong>of</strong> Input-Output Mappings<br />

For a cyberneticist, a machine was simply a device for converting some input into<br />

some output—and nothing more (Ashby, 1956, 1960; Wiener, 1948, 1964). A cyberneticist<br />

would be concerned primarily with describing a machine such as a calculating<br />

device in terms <strong>of</strong> its input-output mapping. However, underlying this simple<br />

definition was a great deal <strong>of</strong> complexity.<br />

First, cybernetics was not interested in the relation between a particular input<br />

and output, but instead was interested in a general account <strong>of</strong> a machine’s possible<br />

behaviour “by asking not ‘what individual act will it produce here and now?’ but<br />

‘what are all the possible behaviours that it can produce?’” (Ashby, 1956, p. 3).<br />

Second, cybernetics wanted not only to specify what possible input-outputs<br />

could be generated by a device, but also to specify what behaviours could not be<br />

generated, and why: “Cybernetics envisages a set <strong>of</strong> possibilities much wider than<br />

the actual, and then asks why the particular case should conform to its usual particular<br />

restriction” (Ashby, 1956, p. 3).<br />

Third, cybernetics was particularly concerned about machines that were nonlinear,<br />

dynamic, and adaptive, which would result in very complex relations between<br />

input and output. The nonlinear relationships between four simple machines that<br />

interact with each other in a network are so complex that they are mathematically<br />

intractable (Ashby, 1960).<br />

Fourth, cybernetics viewed machines in a general way that not only ignored<br />

their physical nature, but was not even concerned with whether a particular<br />

machine had been (or could be) constructed or not. “What cybernetics <strong>of</strong>fers is the<br />

framework on which all individual machines may be ordered, related and understood”<br />

(Ashby, 1956, p. 2).<br />

How could cybernetics study machines in such a way that these four different<br />

40 Chapter 2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!