06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

However, it is clear that Miller, Galanter, and Pribram’s (1960) message about<br />

the environment had little substantive impact. Why else would Norman (1980) be<br />

conveying the same message twenty years later? It is less clear why this was the<br />

case. One possibility is that as cognitivism took root in experimental psychology,<br />

and as cognitive psychology in turn influenced empirical research within cognitive<br />

science, interest in the environment was a minority position. <strong>Cognitive</strong> psychology<br />

was clearly in a leading position to inform cognitive science about its prototypical<br />

domain (i.e., adult human cognition; see von Eckardt, 1995). Perhaps this informing<br />

included passing along antagonist views against core behaviourist ideas.<br />

Of course, cognitive psychology’s antagonism towards behaviourism and<br />

the behaviourist view <strong>of</strong> the environment is not the only reason for cognitive science’s<br />

rise as a classical science. Another reason is that cognitive science was not so<br />

much inspired by cybernetics, but was instead inspired by computer science and<br />

the implications <strong>of</strong> the digital computer. Furthermore, the digital computer that<br />

inspired cognitive science—the von Neumann architecture, or the stored-program<br />

computer (von Neumann, 1993)—was a device that was primarily concerned with<br />

the manipulation <strong>of</strong> internal representations.<br />

Finally, the early successes in developing classical models <strong>of</strong> a variety <strong>of</strong> highlevel<br />

cognitive phenomena such as problem solving (Newell et al., 1958; Newell &<br />

Simon, 1961, 1972), and <strong>of</strong> robots that used internal models to plan before executing<br />

actions on the world (Nilsson, 1984), were successes achieved without worrying<br />

much about the relationship between world and agent. Sense-think-act processing,<br />

particularly the sort that heavily emphasized thinking or planning, was promising<br />

new horizons for the understanding <strong>of</strong> human cognition. Alternative approaches,<br />

rooted in older traditions <strong>of</strong> cybernetics or behaviourism, seemed to have been completely<br />

replaced.<br />

One consequence <strong>of</strong> this situation was that cognitive science came to be defined<br />

in a manner that explicitly excluded non-classical perspectives. For example, consider<br />

von Eckardt’s (1995) attempt to characterize cognitive science. Von Eckardt<br />

argued that this can be done by identifying a set <strong>of</strong> domain-specifying assumptions,<br />

basic research questions, substantive assumptions, and methodological assumptions.<br />

Importantly, the specific members <strong>of</strong> these sets that von Eckardt identified<br />

reflect a prototypical classical cognitive science and seem to exclude both connectionist<br />

and embodied varieties.<br />

Consider just one feature <strong>of</strong> von Eckardt’s (1995) project. She began by specifying<br />

the identification assumption for cognitive science—its assumed domain <strong>of</strong><br />

study. According to von Eckardt, the best statement <strong>of</strong> this assumption is to say<br />

that cognitive science’s domain is human cognitive capacities. Furthermore, her discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> this assumption—and <strong>of</strong> possible alternatives to it—rejects non-classical<br />

variants <strong>of</strong> cognitive science.<br />

410 Chapter 9

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!