06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

thinking was logic, then thinking machines—machines that could do logic—existed<br />

in the late nineteenth century.<br />

The logic machines <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century were, in fact, quite limited in ability,<br />

as we see later in this chapter. However, they were soon replaced by much more<br />

powerful devices. In the first half <strong>of</strong> the twentieth century, the basic theory <strong>of</strong> a general<br />

computing mechanism had been laid out in Alan Turing’s account <strong>of</strong> his universal<br />

machine (Hodges, 1983; Turing, 1936). The universal machine was a device<br />

that “could simulate the work done by any machine. . . . It would be a machine to<br />

do everything, which was enough to give anyone pause for thought” (Hodges, 1983,<br />

p. 104). The theory was converted into working universal machines—electronic<br />

computers—by the middle <strong>of</strong> the twentieth century (Goldstine, 1993; Reid, 2001;<br />

Williams, 1997).<br />

The invention <strong>of</strong> the electronic computer made logicism practical. The computer’s<br />

general ability to manipulate symbols made the attainment <strong>of</strong> machine intelligence<br />

seem plausible to many, and inevitable to some (Turing, 1950). Logicism was<br />

validated every time a computer accomplished some new task that had been presumed<br />

to be the exclusive domain <strong>of</strong> human intelligence (Kurzweil, 1990, 1999). The<br />

pioneers <strong>of</strong> cognitive science made some bold claims and some aggressive predictions<br />

(McCorduck, 1979): in 1956, Herbert Simon announced to a mathematical modelling<br />

class that “Over Christmas Allen Newell and I invented a thinking machine”<br />

(McCorduck, 1979, p. 116). It was predicted that by the late 1960s most theories in<br />

psychology would be expressed as computer programs (Simon & Newell, 1958).<br />

The means by which computers accomplished complex information processing<br />

tasks inspired theories about the nature <strong>of</strong> human thought. The basic workings<br />

<strong>of</strong> computers became, at the very least, a metaphor for the architecture <strong>of</strong> human<br />

cognition. This metaphor is evident in philosophy in the early 1940s (Craik, 1943).<br />

My hypothesis then is that thought models, or parallels, reality—that its essential<br />

feature is not ‘the mind,’ ‘the self,’ ‘sense data’ nor ‘propositions,’ but is symbolism,<br />

and that this symbolism is largely <strong>of</strong> the same kind which is familiar to us in<br />

mechanical devices which aid thought and calculation. (Craik, 1943, p. 57)<br />

Importantly, many modern cognitive scientists do not see the relationship between<br />

cognition and computers as being merely metaphorical (Pylyshyn, 1979a, p. 435):<br />

“For me, the notion <strong>of</strong> computation stands in the same relation to cognition as<br />

geometry does to mechanics: It is not a metaphor but part <strong>of</strong> a literal description <strong>of</strong><br />

cognitive activity.”<br />

Computers are special devices in another sense: in order to explain how they<br />

work, one must look at them from several different perspectives. Each perspective<br />

requires a radically different vocabulary to describe what computers do. When cognitive<br />

science assumes that cognition is computation, it also assumes that human<br />

cognition must be explained using multiple vocabularies.<br />

22 Chapter 2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!