06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Language acquisition can be described as solving the projection problem:<br />

determining the mapping from primary linguistic data to the acquired grammar<br />

(Baker, 1979; Peters, 1972). When language learning is so construed, the poverty<br />

<strong>of</strong> the stimulus becomes a problem <strong>of</strong> underdetermination. That is, the projection<br />

from data to grammar is not unique, but is instead one-to-many: one set <strong>of</strong> primary<br />

linguistic data is consistent with many potential grammars.<br />

For sighted individuals, our visual experience makes us take visual perception<br />

for granted. We have the sense that we simply look at the world and see it. Indeed,<br />

the phenomenology <strong>of</strong> vision led artificial intelligence pioneers to expect that building<br />

vision into computers would be a straightforward problem. For instance, Marvin<br />

Minsky assigned one student, as a summer project, the task <strong>of</strong> programming a computer<br />

to see (Horgan, 1993). However, failures to develop computer vision made it<br />

apparent that the human visual system was effortlessly solving, in real time, enormously<br />

complicated information processing problems. Like language learning,<br />

vision is dramatically underdetermined. That is, if one views vision as the projection<br />

from primary visual data (the proximal stimulus on the retina) to the internal<br />

interpretation or representation <strong>of</strong> the distal scene, this projection is one-to-many.<br />

A single proximal stimulus is consistent with an infinite number <strong>of</strong> different interpretations<br />

(Gregory, 1970; Marr, 1982; Pylyshyn, 2003c; Rock, 1983; Shepard, 1990).<br />

One reason that vision is underdetermined is because the distal world is<br />

arranged in three dimensions <strong>of</strong> space, but the primary source <strong>of</strong> visual information<br />

we have about it comes from patterns <strong>of</strong> light projected onto an essentially two<br />

dimensional surface, the retina. “According to a fundamental theorem <strong>of</strong> topology,<br />

the relations between objects in a space <strong>of</strong> three dimensions cannot all be preserved<br />

in a two-dimensional projection” (Shepard, 1990, pp. 173–175).<br />

This source <strong>of</strong> underdetermination is illustrated in Figure 8-1, which illustrates<br />

a view from the top <strong>of</strong> an eye observing a point in the distal world as it moves from<br />

position X 1<br />

to position Y 1<br />

over a given interval <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

X 1<br />

X 2<br />

Y 1<br />

Y 2<br />

X 3<br />

X 4<br />

Y 3<br />

A<br />

B<br />

Figure 8-1. Underdetermination <strong>of</strong> projected movement.<br />

364 Chapter 8

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!