06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

thus, perceptions, presentations, volitions, and emotions, in short the whole inner<br />

and outer world, are put together, in combinations <strong>of</strong> varying evanescence and permanence,<br />

out <strong>of</strong> a small number <strong>of</strong> homogeneous elements. Usually, these elements<br />

are called sensations. (Mach, 1959, p. 22)<br />

From this perspective, a key issue facing any theory <strong>of</strong> seeing or visualizing is determining<br />

where sensation ends and where perception begins.<br />

Unfortunately, the demarcation between sensation and perception is not easily<br />

determined by introspection. Subjective experience can easily lead us to the intentional<br />

fallacy in which a property <strong>of</strong> the content <strong>of</strong> a mental representation is mistakenly<br />

attributed to the representation itself (Pylyshyn, 2003c). We see in the next<br />

section that the transparency <strong>of</strong> visual processing hides from our awareness a controversial<br />

set <strong>of</strong> processes that must cope with tremendously complex information<br />

processing problems.<br />

8.2 The Poverty <strong>of</strong> the Stimulus<br />

Some researchers have noted a striking tension between experience and science<br />

(Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991). On the one hand, our everyday experience<br />

provides a compelling and anchoring sense <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness. On the other<br />

hand, cognitive science assumes a fundamental self-fragmentation, because much<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought is putatively mediated by mechanisms that are modular, independent,<br />

and completely incapable <strong>of</strong> becoming part <strong>of</strong> conscious experience. “Thus cognitivism<br />

challenges our conviction that consciousness and the mind either amount<br />

to the same thing or [that] there is an essential or necessary connection between<br />

them” (p. 49).<br />

The tension between experience and science is abundantly evident in vision<br />

research. It is certainly true that the scientific study <strong>of</strong> visual perception relies heavily<br />

on the analysis <strong>of</strong> visual experience (Pylyshyn, 2003c). However, researchers are<br />

convinced that this analysis must be performed with caution and be supplemented<br />

by additional methodologies. This is because visual experience is not complete, in<br />

the sense that it does not provide direct access to or experience <strong>of</strong> visual processing.<br />

Pylyshyn (2003b) wrote,<br />

what we do [experience] is misleading because it is always the world as it appears<br />

to us that we see, not the real work that is being done by the mind in going from the<br />

proximal stimuli, generally optical patterns on the retina, to the familiar experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> seeing (or imagining) the world. (Pylyshyn, 2003b, p. xii)<br />

Vision researchers have long been aware that the machinery <strong>of</strong> vision is not a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> our visual experience. Helmholtz noted that “it might seem that nothing could be<br />

easier than to be conscious <strong>of</strong> one’s own sensations; and yet experience shows that<br />

362 Chapter 8

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!