06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

constraints on symbol manipulations and constraints on symbolic content.<br />

To summarize this section: The interdisciplinary nature <strong>of</strong> cognitive science<br />

arises because cognitive systems require explanations at multiple levels. Two multiple<br />

level approaches are commonly found in the cognitive science literature.<br />

The first is Marr’s (1982) tri-level hypothesis, which requires cognitive systems<br />

to be explained at the implementational, algorithmic, and computational levels.<br />

It is argued above that all three schools <strong>of</strong> thought in cognitive science adhere to<br />

the tri-level hypothesis. Though at each level there are technical differences to be<br />

found between classical, connectionist, and embodied cognitive science, all three<br />

approaches seem consistent with Marr’s approach. The tri-level hypothesis cannot<br />

be used to distinguish one cognitive science from another.<br />

The second is a tri-level approach that emerges from the physical symbol system<br />

hypothesis. It argues that information processing requires explanation at three<br />

independent levels: the physical, the symbolic, and the semantic (Dennett, 1987;<br />

Newell, 1982; Pylyshyn, 1984). The physical and symbolic levels in this approach<br />

bear a fairly strong relationship to Marr’s (1982) implementational and algorithmic<br />

levels. The semantic level, though, differs from Marr’s computational level in calling<br />

for a cognitive vocabulary that captures regularities by appealing to the contents <strong>of</strong><br />

mental representations. This cognitive vocabulary has been proposed as a mark <strong>of</strong><br />

the classical that distinguishes classical theories from those proposed by connectionist<br />

and embodied researchers. However, it has been suggested that this view<br />

may not hold, because the formalist’s motto makes the proposal <strong>of</strong> an independent<br />

cognitive vocabulary difficult to defend.<br />

7.9 From Classical Marks to Hybrid Theories<br />

Vera and Simon’s (1993) analysis <strong>of</strong> situated action theories defines one extreme<br />

pole <strong>of</strong> a continuum for relating different approaches in cognitive science. At this<br />

end <strong>of</strong> the continuum, all theories in cognitive science—including situated action<br />

theories and connectionist theories—are classical or symbolic in nature. “It follows<br />

that there is no need, contrary to what followers <strong>of</strong> SA seem sometimes to claim, for<br />

cognitive psychology to adopt a whole new language and research agenda, breaking<br />

completely from traditional (symbolic) cognitive theories” (p. 46).<br />

The position defined by Vera and Simon’s (1993) analysis unites classical, connectionist,<br />

and cognitive science under a classical banner. However, it does so<br />

because key terms, such as symbolic, are defined so vaguely that their value becomes<br />

questionable. Critics <strong>of</strong> their perspective have argued that anything can be viewed as<br />

symbolic given Vera and Simon’s liberal definition <strong>of</strong> what symbols are (Agre, 1993;<br />

Clancey, 1993).<br />

Marks <strong>of</strong> the Classical? 355

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!