06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

primarily is the work” (p. 99). Another example <strong>of</strong> readiness-to-hand is the blind person’s<br />

cane, which is not experienced as such when it is being used to navigate, but is<br />

instead experienced as an extension <strong>of</strong> the person themselves (Bateson, 1972, p. 465):<br />

“The stick is a pathway along which transforms <strong>of</strong> difference are being transmitted.”<br />

Heidegger’s philosophy played a dominant role in the embodied theory proposed<br />

by Winograd and Flores (1987b). They took readiness-to-hand as evidence<br />

<strong>of</strong> direct engagement with the world; we only become aware <strong>of</strong> equipment itself<br />

when the structural coupling between world, equipment, and agent breaks down.<br />

Winograd and Flores took the goal <strong>of</strong> designing equipment, such as human-computer<br />

interfaces, to be creating artifacts that are invisible to us when they are used.<br />

“A successful word processing device lets a person operate on the words and paragraphs<br />

displayed on the screen, without being aware <strong>of</strong> formulating and giving<br />

commands” (Winograd & Flores, 1987b, p. 164). The invisibility <strong>of</strong> artifacts—the<br />

readiness-to-hand <strong>of</strong> equipment—is frequently characterized as being evidence <strong>of</strong><br />

good design (Dourish, 2001; Norman, 1998, 2002, 2004).<br />

Importantly, readiness-to-hand was also used by Winograd and Flores (1987b)<br />

as evidence for rejecting the need for classical representations, and to counter<br />

the claim that tool use is mediated by symbolic thinking or planning (Miller,<br />

Galanter, & Pribram, 1960). From the classical perspective, it might be expected<br />

that an agent is consciously aware <strong>of</strong> his or her plans; the absence <strong>of</strong> such awareness,<br />

or readiness-to-hand, must therefore indicate the absence <strong>of</strong> planning. Thus<br />

readiness-to-hand reflects direct, non-symbolic links between sensing and acting.<br />

If we focus on concernful activity instead <strong>of</strong> on detached contemplation, the status<br />

<strong>of</strong> this representation is called into question. In driving a nail with a hammer (as<br />

opposed to thinking about a hammer), I need not make use <strong>of</strong> any explicit representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hammer. (Winograd & Flores, 1987b, p. 33)<br />

Vera and Simon (1993, p. 19) correctly noted, though, that our conscious awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> entities is mute with respect to either the nature or the existence <strong>of</strong> representational<br />

formats: “Awareness has nothing to do with whether something is represented<br />

symbolically, or in some other way, or not at all.” That is, consciousness <strong>of</strong><br />

contents is not a defining feature <strong>of</strong> physical symbol systems. This position is a deft<br />

dismissal <strong>of</strong> using readiness-to-hand to support an anti-representational position.<br />

After dealing with the implications <strong>of</strong> readiness-to-hand, Vera and Simon<br />

(1993) considered alternate formulations <strong>of</strong> the critiques raised by situated action<br />

researchers. Perhaps the prime concern <strong>of</strong> embodied cognitive science is that the<br />

classical approach emphasizes internal, symbolic processing to the near total exclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> sensing and acting. We saw in Chapter 3 that production system pioneers<br />

admitted that their earlier efforts ignored sensing and acting (Newell, 1990). (We<br />

also saw an attempt to rectify this in more recent production system architectures<br />

[Meyer et al., 2001; Meyer & Kieras, 1997a, 1997b]).<br />

320 Chapter 7

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!