06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

orchestra brings the score to life exactly as instructed by the score, and the (passive)<br />

audience unpacks the delivered music to get the composer’s message.<br />

We thus hear people say that music can only have meaning if it is seen to be a<br />

type <strong>of</strong> language, with elements akin to words, phrases and sentences, and with<br />

elements that refer beyond themselves to extramusical things, events, or ideas.<br />

(Johnson, 2007, p. 207)<br />

In other words, the classical view <strong>of</strong> musical meaning is very similar to the view <strong>of</strong><br />

meaning espoused by classical cognitive science: music is a symbolic, intentional<br />

medium.<br />

The view <strong>of</strong> music as a symbolic medium that conveys intended meaning has<br />

generated a long history <strong>of</strong> resistance. The autonomist school <strong>of</strong> aesthetics (see<br />

Hanslick, 1957) argued against the symbolic theories <strong>of</strong> musical meaning, as well<br />

as against theories that music communicated emotion. Hanslick’s (1957) position<br />

was that music was a medium whose elements were pure and nonrepresentational.<br />

Hanslick famously argued that “the essence <strong>of</strong> music is sound and motion” (p. 48).<br />

Modern positions that treat musical meaning in an embodied fashion are related to<br />

Hanslick’s (Johnson, 2007; Leman, 2008).<br />

Embodied alternatives to musical meaning become attractive because the conduit<br />

metaphor breaks down in modern music. If control is taken away from the<br />

score and the conductor, if the musicians become active contributors to the composition<br />

(Benson, 2003), if the audience is actively involved in completing the composition<br />

as well, and if music is actually a “cool medium,” then what is the intended<br />

message <strong>of</strong> the piece?<br />

Modern embodied theories <strong>of</strong> music answer this question by taking a position<br />

that follows naturally from Hanslick’s (1957) musical aesthetics. They propose that<br />

the sound and motion <strong>of</strong> music literally have bodily effects that are meaningful. For<br />

instance, Johnson (2007) noted that,<br />

to hear music is just to be moved and to feel in the precise way that is defined by<br />

the patterns <strong>of</strong> musical motion. Those feelings are meaningful in the same way that<br />

any pattern <strong>of</strong> emotional flow is meaningful to us at a pre-reflective level <strong>of</strong> awareness.<br />

(Johnson, 2007, p. 239)<br />

Similarly, Leman (2008, p. 17) suggested that “moving sonic forms do something<br />

with our bodies, and therefore have a signification through body action rather than<br />

through thinking.” Some implications <strong>of</strong> this position are considered in the next<br />

section.<br />

Minimalist composers themselves adopt a McLuhanesque view <strong>of</strong> the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> their compositions: the music doesn’t deliver a message, but is itself the<br />

message. After being schooled in the techniques <strong>of</strong> serialism, which deliberately<br />

300 Chapter 6

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!