06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mighty Alps, whose white and shining pyramids and domes towered above all, as<br />

belonging to another earth, the habitations <strong>of</strong> another race <strong>of</strong> beings” (p. 97). To be<br />

sublime was to reflect a greatness that could not be completely understood. “The<br />

immense mountains and precipices that overhung me on every side—the sound <strong>of</strong><br />

the river raging among the rocks, and the dashing <strong>of</strong> the waterfalls around, spoke <strong>of</strong><br />

a power mighty as Omnipotence” (p. 97).<br />

Sublime Nature appeared frequently in musical Romanticism. Longyear’s<br />

(1988, p. 12) examples include “the forest paintings in Weber’s Der Freischütz or<br />

Wagner’s; the landscapes and seascapes <strong>of</strong> Mendelssohn and Gade; the Alpine pictures<br />

in Schumann’s or Tchaikovsky’s Manfred” to name but a few.<br />

Musical Romanticism also took great pains to convey the imaginary or the<br />

indescribable (Whittall, 1987). In some striking instances, Romantic composers<br />

followed the advice in John Keats’ 1819 Ode on a Grecian Urn, “Heard melodies<br />

are sweet, but those unheard / Are sweeter.” Consider Schumann’s piano work<br />

Humoreske (Rosen, 1995). It uses three staves: one for the right hand, one for the<br />

left, and a third—containing the melody!—which is not to be played at all. Though<br />

inaudible, the melody “is embodied in the upper and lower parts as a kind <strong>of</strong> after<br />

resonance—out <strong>of</strong> phase, delicate, and shadowy” (p. 8). The effects <strong>of</strong> the melody<br />

emerge from playing the other parts.<br />

In certain respects, connectionist cognitive science is sympathetic to musical<br />

Romanticism’s emphasis on nature, the sublime, and the imaginary. Cartesian philosophy,<br />

and the classical cognitive science that was later inspired by it, view the<br />

mind as disembodied, being separate from the natural world. In seeking theories that<br />

are biologically plausible and neuronally inspired (McClelland & Rumelhart, 1986;<br />

Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986c), connectionists took a small step towards embodiment.<br />

Whereas Descartes completely separated the mind from the world, connectionists<br />

assume that brains cause minds (Searle, 1984).<br />

Furthermore, connectionists recognize that the mental properties caused by<br />

brains may be very difficult to articulate using a rigid set <strong>of</strong> rules and symbols.<br />

One reason that artificial neural networks are used to study music is because they<br />

may capture regularities that cannot be rationally expressed (Bharucha, 1999;<br />

Rowe, 2001; Todd & Loy, 1991). These regularities emerge from the nonlinear interactions<br />

amongst network components (Dawson, 2004; Hillis, 1988). And the difficulty<br />

in explaining such interactions suggests that networks are sublime. Artificial<br />

neural networks seem to provide “the possibility <strong>of</strong> constructing intelligence without<br />

first understanding it” (Hillis, 1988, p. 176).<br />

Musical Romanticism also celebrated something <strong>of</strong> a scale less grand than<br />

sublime Nature: the individual. Romantic composers broke away from the established<br />

system <strong>of</strong> musical patronage. They began to write music for its own (or for<br />

the composer's own) sake, instead <strong>of</strong> being written for commission (Einstein, 1947).<br />

282 Chapter 6

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!