06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

To see that this is analogous to methodological solipsism, consider how we differentiate<br />

compositions from one another. Traditionally, this is done by referring to a<br />

composition’s score (Benson, 2003). That is, compositions are identified in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> a particular set <strong>of</strong> symbols, a particular formal structure. The identification <strong>of</strong> a<br />

composition does not depend upon identifying which audience has heard it. A composition<br />

can exist, and be identified, in the absence <strong>of</strong> its audience-as-environment.<br />

Another parallel between the classical mind and classical music is that there<br />

have been significant modern reactions against the Austro-German musical tradition<br />

(Griffiths, 1994, 1995). Interestingly, these reactions parallel many <strong>of</strong> the reactions<br />

<strong>of</strong> embodied cognitive science against the classical approach. In later sections <strong>of</strong><br />

this chapter we consider some <strong>of</strong> these reactions, and explore the idea that they make<br />

plausible the claim that “non-cognitive” processes are applicable to classical music.<br />

However, before we do so, let us first turn to consider how the parallels considered<br />

above are reflected in how classical cognitive scientists study musical cognition.<br />

6.2 The Classical Approach to Musical Cognition<br />

In Chapter 8 on seeing and visualizing, we see that classical theories take the purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> visual perception to be the construction <strong>of</strong> mental models <strong>of</strong> the external,<br />

visual world. To do so, these theories must deal with the problem <strong>of</strong> underdetermination.<br />

Information in the world is not sufficient, on its own, to completely determine<br />

visual experience.<br />

Classical solutions to the problem <strong>of</strong> underdetermination (Bruner, 1973;<br />

Gregory, 1970, 1978; Rock, 1983) propose that knowledge <strong>of</strong> the world—the contents<br />

<strong>of</strong> mental representations—is also used to determine visual experience. In other<br />

words, classical theories <strong>of</strong> perception describe visual experience as arising from<br />

the interaction <strong>of</strong> stimulus information with internal representations. Seeing is a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> thinking.<br />

Auditory perception has also been the subject <strong>of</strong> classical theorization. Classical<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> auditory perception parallel classical theories <strong>of</strong> visual perception in<br />

two general respects. First, since the earliest psychophysical studies <strong>of</strong> audition<br />

(Helmholtz & Ellis, 1954), hearing has been viewed as a process for building internal<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the external world.<br />

We have to investigate the various modes in which the nerves themselves are<br />

excited, giving rise to their various sensations, and finally the laws according to<br />

which these sensations result in mental images <strong>of</strong> determinate external objects,<br />

that is, in perceptions. (Helmholtz & Ellis, 1954, p. 4)<br />

Second, in classical theories <strong>of</strong> hearing, physical stimulation does not by itself determine<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> auditory percepts. Auditory stimuli are actively organized, being<br />

Classical Music and <strong>Cognitive</strong> <strong>Science</strong> 273

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!