06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

usually in the form <strong>of</strong> differential equations. Its utility was illustrated in Randall<br />

Beer’s (2003) analysis <strong>of</strong> an agent that learns to categorize objects, <strong>of</strong> circuits for<br />

associative learning (Phattanasri, Chiel, & Beer, 2007), and <strong>of</strong> a walking leg controlled<br />

by a neural mechanism (Beer, 2010).<br />

While dynamical systems theory provides a medium in which embodied cognitive<br />

scientists can conduct computational analyses, it is also intimidating and<br />

difficult. “A common criticism <strong>of</strong> dynamical approaches to cognition is that they<br />

are practically intractable except in the simplest cases” (Shapiro, 2011, pp. 127–<br />

128). This was exactly the situation that led Ashby (1956, 1960) to study feedback<br />

between multiple devices synthetically, by constructing the Homeostat. This does<br />

not mean, however, that computational analyses are impossible or fruitless. On the<br />

contrary, it is possible that such analyses can co-operate with the synthetic exploration<br />

<strong>of</strong> models in an attempt to advance both formal and behavioural investigations<br />

(Dawson, 2004; Dawson, Dupuis, & Wilson, 2010).<br />

In the preceding paragraphs we presented an argument that embodied cognitive<br />

scientists study cognition at the same multiple levels <strong>of</strong> investigation that characterize<br />

classical cognitive science. Also acknowledged is that embodied cognitive<br />

scientists are likely to view each <strong>of</strong> these levels slightly differently than their classical<br />

counterparts. Ultimately, that embodied cognitive science explores cognition at<br />

these different levels <strong>of</strong> analysis also implies that embodied cognitive scientists are<br />

also committed to the notion <strong>of</strong> validating their theories by seeking strong equivalence.<br />

It stands to reason that the validity <strong>of</strong> a theory created within embodied cognitive<br />

science would be best established by showing that this theory is supported at<br />

all <strong>of</strong> the different levels <strong>of</strong> investigation.<br />

5.14 What Is Embodied <strong>Cognitive</strong> <strong>Science</strong>?<br />

To review, the central claim <strong>of</strong> classical cognitive science is that cognition is computation,<br />

where computation is taken to be the manipulation <strong>of</strong> internal representations.<br />

From this perspective, classical cognitive science construes cognition as an<br />

iterative sense-think-act cycle. The “think” part <strong>of</strong> this cycle is emphasized, because<br />

it is responsible for modelling and planning. The “thinking” also stands as a required<br />

mentalistic buffer between sensing and acting, producing what is known as the classical<br />

sandwich (Hurley, 2001). The classical sandwich represents a modern form <strong>of</strong><br />

Cartesian dualism, in the sense that the mental (thinking) is distinct from the physical<br />

(the world that is sensed, and the body that can act upon it) (Devlin, 1996).<br />

Embodied cognitive science, like connectionist cognitive science, arises from the<br />

view that the core logicist assumptions <strong>of</strong> classical cognitive science are not adequate<br />

to explain human cognition (Dreyfus, 1992; Port & van Gelder, 1995b; Winograd &<br />

Flores, 1987b).<br />

260 Chapter 5

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!