06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Embodied cognitive science does not share this exclusive focus, because it attributes<br />

some behavioural complexities to environmental influences. Apart from this<br />

important difference, though, algorithmic investigations—specifically in the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> behavioural observations—are central to the embodied approach. Descriptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> behaviour are the primary product <strong>of</strong> forward engineering; examples in behaviour-based<br />

robotics span the literature from time lapse photographs <strong>of</strong> Tortoise trajectories<br />

(Grey Walter, 1963) to modern reports <strong>of</strong> how, over time, robots sort or<br />

rearrange objects in an enclosure (Holland & Melhuish, 1999; Melhuish et al., 2006;<br />

Scholes et al., 2004; Wilson et al., 2004). At the heart <strong>of</strong> such behavioural accounts<br />

is acceptance <strong>of</strong> Simon’s (1969) parable <strong>of</strong> the ant. The embodied approach cannot<br />

understand an architecture by examining its inert components. It must see what<br />

emerges when this architecture is embodied in, situated in, and interacting with an<br />

environment.<br />

When embodied cognitive science moves beyond behaviour-based robotics,<br />

it relies on some sorts <strong>of</strong> behavioural observations that are not employed as frequently<br />

in classical cognitive science. For example, many embodied cognitive scientists<br />

exhort the phenomenological study <strong>of</strong> cognition (Gallagher, 2005; Gibbs, 2006;<br />

Thompson, 2007; Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991). Phenomenology explores how<br />

people experience their world and examines how the world is meaningful to us via<br />

our experience (Brentano, 1995; Husserl, 1965; Merleau-Ponty, 1962).<br />

Just as enactive theories <strong>of</strong> perception (Noë, 2004) can be viewed as being<br />

inspired by Gibson’s (1979) ecological account <strong>of</strong> perception, phenomenological<br />

studies within embodied cognitive science (Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991) are<br />

inspired by the philosophy <strong>of</strong> Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1962). Merleau-Ponty rejected<br />

the Cartesian separation between world and mind: “Truth does not ‘inhabit’ only<br />

‘the inner man,’ or more accurately, there is no inner man, man is in the world, and<br />

only in the world does he know himself ” (p. xii). Merleau-Ponty strove to replace this<br />

Cartesian view with one that relied upon embodiment. “We shall need to reawaken<br />

our experience <strong>of</strong> the world as it appears to us in so far as we are in the world through<br />

our body, and in so far as we perceive the world with our body” (p. 239).<br />

Phenomenology with modern embodied cognitive science is a call to further<br />

pursue Merleau-Ponty’s embodied approach.<br />

What we are suggesting is a change in the nature <strong>of</strong> reflection from an abstract, disembodied<br />

activity to an embodied (mindful), open-ended reflection. By embodied,<br />

we mean reflection in which body and mind have been brought together. (Varela,<br />

Thompson, & Rosch, 1991, p. 27)<br />

However, seeking evidence from such reflection is not necessarily straightforward<br />

(Gallagher, 2005). For instance, while Gallagher acknowledges that the body is<br />

critical in its shaping <strong>of</strong> cognition, he also notes that many aspects <strong>of</strong> our bodily<br />

258 Chapter 5

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!