06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

For example, consider the work <strong>of</strong> Edward Tolman (1932, 1948). Tolman<br />

appealed to representational concepts to explain behaviour, such as his proposal<br />

that rats navigate and locate reinforcers by creating and manipulating a cognitive<br />

map. The mentalistic nature <strong>of</strong> Tolman’s theories was a source <strong>of</strong> harsh criticism:<br />

Signs, in Tolman’s theory, occasion in the rat realization, or cognition, or judgment,<br />

or hypotheses, or abstraction, but they do not occasion action. In his concern<br />

with what goes on in the rat’s mind, Tolman has neglected to predict what the<br />

rat will do. So far as the theory is concerned the rat is left buried in thought; if he<br />

gets to the food-box at the end that is his concern, not the concern <strong>of</strong> the theory.<br />

(Guthrie, 1935, p. 172)<br />

The later successes, and current dominance, <strong>of</strong> cognitive theory make such criticisms<br />

appear quaint. But classical theories are nonetheless being rigorously reformulated<br />

by embodied cognitive science.<br />

Embodied cognitive scientists argue that classical cognitive science, with its<br />

emphasis on the disembodied mind, has failed to capture important aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking. For example, Hutchins (1995, p. 171) noted that “by failing to understand<br />

the source <strong>of</strong> the computational power in our interactions with simple ‘unintelligent’<br />

physical devices, we position ourselves well to squander opportunities with<br />

so-called intelligent computers.” Embodied cognitive science proposes that the<br />

modern form <strong>of</strong> dualism exhibited by classical cognitive science is a mistake. For<br />

instance, Scribner hoped that her studies <strong>of</strong> mind in action conveyed “a conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> mind which is not hostage to the traditional cleavage between the mind and the<br />

hand, the mental and the manual” (Scribner & Tobach, 1997, p. 307).<br />

5.8 The Extended <strong>Mind</strong><br />

In preceding pages <strong>of</strong> this chapter, a number <strong>of</strong> interrelated topics that are central<br />

to embodied cognitive science have been introduced: situation and embodiment,<br />

feedback between agents and environments, stigmergic control <strong>of</strong> behaviour,<br />

affordances and enactive perception, and cognitive scaffolding. These topics show<br />

that embodied cognitive science places much more emphasis on body and world,<br />

and on sense and action, than do other “flavours” <strong>of</strong> cognitive science.<br />

This change in emphasis can have pr<strong>of</strong>ound effects on our definitions <strong>of</strong> mind<br />

or self (Bateson, 1972). For example, consider this famous passage from anthropologist<br />

Gregory Bateson:<br />

But what about ‘me’? Suppose I am a blind man, and I use a stick. I go tap, tap,<br />

tap. Where do I start? Is my mental system bounded at the handle <strong>of</strong> the stick? Is it<br />

bounded by my skin? (Bateson, 1972, p. 465)<br />

230 Chapter 5

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!