06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

5.6 Horizontal Layers <strong>of</strong> Control<br />

Classical cognitive science usually assumes that the primary purpose <strong>of</strong> cognition is<br />

planning (Anderson, 1983; Newell, 1990); this planning is used to mediate perception<br />

and action. As a result, classical theories take the form <strong>of</strong> the sense-think-act<br />

cycle (Pfeifer & Scheier, 1999). Furthermore, the “thinking” component <strong>of</strong> this cycle<br />

is emphasized far more than either the “sensing” or the “acting.” “One problem with<br />

psychology’s attempt at cognitive theory has been our persistence in thinking about<br />

cognition without bringing in perceptual and motor processes” (Newell, 1990, p. 15).<br />

Embodied cognitive science (Agre, 1997; Brooks, 1999, 2002; Chemero, 2009;<br />

Clancey, 1997; Clark, 1997, 2003, 2008; Pfeifer & Scheier, 1999; Robbins & Aydede, 2009;<br />

Shapiro, 2011; Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991) recognizes the importance <strong>of</strong> sensing<br />

and acting, and reacts against central cognitive control. Its more radical proponents<br />

strive to completely replace the sense-think-act cycle with sense-act mechanisms.<br />

This reaction is consistent with several themes in the current chapter: the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the environment, degrees <strong>of</strong> embodiment, feedback between the<br />

world and the agent, and the integral relationship between an agent’s body and its<br />

umwelt. Given these themes, it becomes quite plausible to reject the proposal that<br />

cognition is used to plan, and to posit instead that the purpose <strong>of</strong> cognition is to<br />

guide action:<br />

The brain should not be seen as primarily a locus <strong>of</strong> inner descriptions <strong>of</strong> external<br />

states <strong>of</strong> affairs; rather, it should be seen as a locus <strong>of</strong> internal structures that act as<br />

operators upon the world via their role in determining actions. (Clark, 1997, 47)<br />

Importantly, these structures do not stand between sensing and acting, but instead<br />

provide direct links between them.<br />

The action-based reaction against classical cognitivism is typified by pioneering<br />

work in behaviour-based robotics (Brooks, 1989, 1991, 1999, 2002; Brooks &<br />

Flynn, 1989). Roboticist Rodney Brooks construes the classical sandwich as a set<br />

<strong>of</strong> vertical processing layers that separate perception and action. His alternative<br />

is a hierarchical arrangement <strong>of</strong> horizontal processing layers that directly connect<br />

perception and action.<br />

Brooks’ action-based approach to behaviour is called the subsumption architecture<br />

(Brooks, 1999). The subsumption architecture is a set <strong>of</strong> modules. However,<br />

these modules are somewhat different in nature than those that were discussed in<br />

Chapter 3 (see also Fodor, 1983). This is because each module in the subsumption<br />

architecture can be described as a sense-act mechanism. That is, every module can<br />

have access to sensed information, as well as to actuators. This means that modules<br />

in the subsumption architecture do not separate perception from action. Instead,<br />

each module is used to control some action on the basis <strong>of</strong> sensed information.<br />

The subsumption architecture arranges modules hierarchically. Lower-level<br />

222 Chapter 5

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!