06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

location to the first. In this condition, the linearly increasing relationship between<br />

distance and time disappeared. Image scanning appears to be cognitively penetrable,<br />

challenging some <strong>of</strong> the architectural claims <strong>of</strong> depictive theory. “Images can<br />

be examined without the putative constraints <strong>of</strong> the surface display postulated by<br />

Kosslyn and others” (Pylyshyn, 1981a, p. 40).<br />

The cognitive penetrability paradigm has also been applied to the mental rotation<br />

task (Pylyshyn, 1979b). Pylyshyn reasoned that if mental rotation is accomplished<br />

by primitive mechanisms, then it must be cognitively impenetrable. One<br />

prediction that follows from this reasoning is that the rate <strong>of</strong> mental rotation should<br />

be independent <strong>of</strong> the content being rotated—an image depicting simple content<br />

should, by virtue <strong>of</strong> its putative architectural nature, be rotated at the same rate as<br />

a different image depicting more complex content.<br />

Pylyshyn (1979b) tested this hypothesis in two experiments and found evidence<br />

<strong>of</strong> cognitive penetration. The rate <strong>of</strong> mental rotation was affected by practice, by the<br />

content <strong>of</strong> the image being rotated, and by the nature <strong>of</strong> the comparison task that<br />

subjects were asked to perform. As was the case with image scanning, it would seem<br />

that the “analog” rotation <strong>of</strong> images is not primitive, but is instead based on simpler<br />

processes that do belong to the architecture.<br />

The more carefully we examine phenomena, such as the mental rotation findings,<br />

the more we find that the informally appealing holistic image-manipulation views<br />

must be replaced by finer grained piecemeal procedures that operate upon an analyzed<br />

and structured stimulus using largely serial, resource-limited mechanisms.<br />

(Pylyshyn, 1979b, p. 27)<br />

<strong>Cognitive</strong> penetrability has played an important role in domains other than mental<br />

imagery. For instance, in the literature concerned with social perception and prediction,<br />

there is debate between a classical theory called theory-theory (Gopnik &<br />

Meltz<strong>of</strong>f, 1997; Gopnik & Wellman, 1992) and a newer approach called simulation<br />

theory (Gordon, 1986, 2005b), which is nicely situated in the embodied cognitive<br />

science that is the topic <strong>of</strong> Chapter 5. There is a growing discussion about<br />

whether cognitive penetrability can be used to discriminate between these two theories<br />

(Greenwood, 1999; Heal, 1996; Kuhberger et al., 2006; Perner et al., 1999; Stich<br />

& Nichols, 1997). <strong>Cognitive</strong> penetrability has also been applied to various topics in<br />

visual perception (Raftopoulos, 2001), including face perception (Bentin & Golland,<br />

2002) and the perception <strong>of</strong> illusory motion (Dawson, 1991; Dawson & Wright, 1989;<br />

Wright & Dawson, 1994).<br />

While cognitive penetrability is an important tool when faced with the challenge<br />

<strong>of</strong> examining the architectural equivalence between model and subject, it is<br />

not without its problems. For instance, in spite <strong>of</strong> it being applied to the study <strong>of</strong><br />

mental imagery, the imager debate rages on, suggesting that penetrability evidence<br />

112 Chapter 3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!