06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Cognitive</strong> penetrability provides a paradigm for testing whether a function <strong>of</strong><br />

interest is part <strong>of</strong> the architecture or not. First, some function is measured as part <strong>of</strong><br />

a pre-test. For example, consider Figure 3-13, which presents the Müller-Lyer illusion,<br />

which was discovered in 1889 (Gregory, 1978). In a pre-test, it would be determined<br />

whether you experience this illusion. Some measurement would be made<br />

to determine whether you judge the horizontal line segment <strong>of</strong> the top arrow to be<br />

longer than the horizontal line segment <strong>of</strong> the bottom arrow.<br />

Second, a strong manipulation <strong>of</strong> a belief related to the function that produces<br />

the Müller-Lyer illusion would be performed. You, as a subject, might be told that<br />

the two horizontal line segments were equal in length. You might be given a ruler,<br />

and asked to measure the two line segments, in order to convince yourself that your<br />

experience was incorrect and that the two lines were <strong>of</strong> the same length.<br />

Figure 3-13. The Müller-Lyer illusion.<br />

Third, a post-test would determine whether you still experienced the illusion. Do<br />

the line segments still appear to be <strong>of</strong> different length, even though you are armed<br />

with the knowledge that this appearance is false? This illusion has had such a long<br />

history because its appearance is not affected by such cognitive content. The mechanism<br />

that is responsible for the Müller-Lyer illusion is cognitively impenetrable.<br />

This paradigm has been applied to some <strong>of</strong> the standard mental imagery tasks<br />

in order to show that some <strong>of</strong> the privileged properties <strong>of</strong> images are cognitively<br />

penetrable and therefore cannot be part <strong>of</strong> the architecture. For instance, in his 1981<br />

dissertation, Liam Bannon examined the map scanning task for cognitive penetrability<br />

(for methodological details, see Pylyshyn, 1981a). Bannon reasoned that the<br />

instructions given to subjects in the standard map scanning study (Kosslyn, Ball,<br />

& Reiser, 1978) instilled a belief that image scanning was like scanning a picture.<br />

Bannon was able to replicate the Kosslyn, Ball, & Reiser results in one condition.<br />

However, in other conditions the instructions were changed so that the images had<br />

to be scanned to answer a question, but no beliefs about scanning were instilled. In<br />

one study, Bannon had subjects shift attention from the first map location to the<br />

second (named) location, and then judge the compass direction from the second<br />

Elements <strong>of</strong> Classical <strong>Cognitive</strong> <strong>Science</strong> 111

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!