06.09.2021 Views

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

Mind, Body, World- Foundations of Cognitive Science, 2013a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ased on informed judgment, and how much is convenience? (Oreskes, Shrader-<br />

Frechette, & Belitz, 1994, p. 644)<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> similar concerns, mathematical psychologists have argued that computer<br />

simulations are impossible to validate in the same way as mathematical models <strong>of</strong><br />

behaviour (Estes, 1975; Luce, 1989, 1999). Evolutionary biologist John Maynard<br />

Smith called simulation research “fact free science” (Mackenzie, 2002).<br />

Computer simulation researchers are generally puzzled by such criticisms,<br />

because their simulations <strong>of</strong> cognitive phenomena must conform to a variety <strong>of</strong><br />

challenging constraints (Newell, 1980, 1990; Pylyshyn, 1984). For instance, Newell’s<br />

(1980, 1990) production system models aim to meet a number <strong>of</strong> constraints that<br />

range from behavioural (flexible responses to environment, goal-oriented, operate<br />

in real time) to biological (realizable as a neural system, develop via embryological<br />

growth processes, arise through evolution).<br />

In validating a computer simulation, classical cognitive science becomes an<br />

intrinsically comparative discipline. Model validation requires that theoretical<br />

analyses and empirical observations are used to evaluate both the relationship<br />

between a simulation and the subject being simulated. In adopting the physical<br />

symbol system hypothesis, classical cognitive scientists are further committed<br />

to the assumption that this relation is complex, because it can be established<br />

(as argued in Chapter 2) at many different levels (Dawson, 1998; Marr, 1982;<br />

Pylyshyn, 1984). Pylyshyn has argued that model validation can take advantage <strong>of</strong><br />

this and proceed by imposing severe empirical constraints. These empirical constraints<br />

involve establishing that a model provides an appropriate account <strong>of</strong> its<br />

subject at the computational, algorithmic, and architectural levels <strong>of</strong> analysis. Let<br />

us examine this position in more detail.<br />

First, consider a relationship between model and subject that is not listed<br />

above—a relationship at the implementational level <strong>of</strong> analysis. Classical cognitive<br />

science’s use <strong>of</strong> computer simulation methodology is a tacit assumption that the<br />

physical structure <strong>of</strong> its models does not need to match the physical structure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subject being modelled.<br />

The basis for this assumption is the multiple realization argument that we have<br />

already encountered. <strong>Cognitive</strong> scientists describe basic information processes in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> their functional nature and ignore their underlying physicality. This is<br />

because the same function can be realized in radically different physical media. For<br />

instance, AND-gates can be created using hydraulic channels, electronic components,<br />

or neural circuits (Hillis, 1998). If hardware or technology were relevant—if<br />

the multiple realization argument was false—then computer simulations <strong>of</strong> cognition<br />

would be absurd. Classical cognitive science ignores the physical when models<br />

are validated. Let us now turn to the relationships between models and subjects<br />

that classical cognitive science cannot and does not ignore.<br />

94 Chapter 3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!