06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 2. Intentional Harms<br />

Notes<br />

1. Intent required. Though not emphasized in the Fisher case, offensive battery requires that<br />

the defendant have acted with intent—in the Restatement formulation, “inten[t] to cause a harmful<br />

or offensive contact with the person of the other or a third person, or an imminent apprehension of<br />

such a contact.” RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 18 (1965). This language is identical to the<br />

language found in the Restatement provision on conventional (harmful) battery, discussed in the<br />

previous section. The key distinction between harmful battery <strong>and</strong> offensive battery is the nature<br />

of the contact that results.<br />

2. Why recognize offensive battery? It will become very clear as this book goes on that tort<br />

law does not supply a remedy for all types of wrongful conduct, even conduct that is widely<br />

reviled. Some types of wrongful conduct have gone untouched because judges have worried<br />

about interfering in particular relationships (e.g., husb<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> wife, parent <strong>and</strong> child), or about<br />

creating incentives for fraud, or simply about opening the door to an unmanageable number of<br />

cases. Judges have deemed other types of wrongful conduct too trivial, too petty. Why, then, has<br />

the law long recognized a cause of action for physical contacts that offend but do not harm? What<br />

about the maxim “no harm, no foul”? The 1872 case Alcorn v. Mitchell, 63 Ill. 533, involving a<br />

defendant who deliberately spit in the face of the plaintiff, offers a classic explanation for the<br />

law’s recognition of offensive battery. The spitting, according to the concise statement of facts,<br />

occurred in a court room, at the close of a legal proceeding between the two men (adjudicating a<br />

charge of trespass), <strong>and</strong> “in the presence of a large number of persons.” Id. at 553. In<br />

consequence, a trial court awarded the defendant to pay $1,000, a hefty sum at the time. In<br />

upholding the award, the Illinois Supreme Court characterized the spitting as an act “of the<br />

greatest indignity, highly provocative of retaliation by force.” Id. at 554. To “sav[e] the necessity<br />

of resort to personal violence as the only means of redress” <strong>and</strong> thereby preserve “public<br />

tranquility,” the court explained, the law “should afford substantial protection against such<br />

outrages, in the way of liberal damages.” Id.<br />

How does this justification hold up in an age of modern policing, when we disapprove, at<br />

least formally, of individual citizens taking the law into their own h<strong>and</strong>s? Does it appear<br />

anachronistic now that the concepts of honor <strong>and</strong> reputation no longer play such important roles in<br />

everyday life? Professor Scott Hershovitz defends damage awards in cases like this on the ground<br />

that, even if they do not prevent violence, they recognize <strong>and</strong> rebut a moral injury; judgment by<br />

judgment, they create <strong>and</strong> recreate the world we want to live in. “We are the agents of morality,”<br />

Hershovitz argues. “There is no one else to do the job. If we think that, as a matter of morality,<br />

Mitchell’s dignity confers on him a right to be free from insults like Alcorn’s spit, then we must<br />

live as if he has that right. . . . Tort is a way for us to do that.” Scott Hershovitz, Treating Wrongs<br />

as Wrongs: An Expressive Argument for Tort Law, 10 J. TORT L. 1, 15 (2018); see also Leslie<br />

Bender, Tort Law’s Role as a Tool for Social Justice Struggle, 37 WASHBURN L.J. 249 (1998)<br />

(“Giving people who are injured compensation from their harm-causers is one way our social<br />

order can help promote their dignity <strong>and</strong> their ability to be social equals.”). Do you buy it? In the<br />

big scheme of things, are cases of offensive battery a good use of judicial resources?<br />

49

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!