06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 10. Damages<br />

disabilities to make hedonic adjustments to their conditions.” Samuel R. Bagenstos & Margo<br />

Schlanger, Hedonic Damages, Hedonic Adaptation, <strong>and</strong> Disability, 60 VAND. L. REV. 745, 750<br />

(2007); see also Anne Bloom with Paul Steven Miller, Blindsight: How We See Disabilities in<br />

Tort Litigation, 86 WASH. L. REV. 709, 731-37 (2011) (describing tort law’s influence on<br />

perceptions of disability). Might the damages phase of tort litigation present an opportunity to re-<br />

“frame” disability, to borrow Professor Elizabeth Emens’s phrase, encouraging more respectful<br />

treatment of disabled people <strong>and</strong> a more realistic <strong>and</strong> positive underst<strong>and</strong>ing of what it means to<br />

be disabled? Elizabeth A. Emens, Framing Disability, 2012 U. ILL. L. REV. 1381 (2012). Does it<br />

matter that this particular re-framing seems to involve taking money away from people with<br />

disabilities?<br />

Doubts have surfaced in the psychology literature, however, about the extent to which<br />

Brickman’s study serves as evidence of hedonic adaptation. A 2006 article pointed out that the<br />

Brickman study actually reveals modest but significant differences between the happiness levels<br />

of persons with paraplegia <strong>and</strong> persons without. See Ed Diener et al., Beyond the Hedonic<br />

Treadmill: Revising the Adaptation Theory of Well-Being, 61 AM. PSYCHOL. 305 (2006).<br />

Similarly, newer studies of persons with paraplegia <strong>and</strong> other groups with disabilities<br />

demonstrated that, although these groups are not as unhappy as typical observers seem to expect,<br />

disability does have a significant negative impact on their happiness levels. See Richard E. Lucas,<br />

Adaptation <strong>and</strong> the Set-Point Model of Subjective Well-Being: Does Happiness Change after<br />

Major Life Events?, 16 CURRENT DIRECTIONS IN PSYCH. SCI. 75 (2007); see also Andrew J.<br />

Oswald & Nattavudh Powdthavee, Does Happiness Adapt?: A Longitudinal Study with<br />

Implications for Economists <strong>and</strong> Judges, 92 J. PUB. ECON. 1061 (2008) (finding that hedonic<br />

adaptation to disability, while significant, is partial: 30 to 50 percent rather than 100 percent).<br />

Moreover, just because a person can adapt to disability <strong>and</strong> live a happy, meaningful<br />

life—this does not mean that a particular plaintiff will, or that the plaintiff has not experienced a<br />

kind of loss that extends beyond medical bills <strong>and</strong> lost income. If tort law were to disallow<br />

damages for loss of enjoyment of life, would it both undercompensate injured plaintiffs <strong>and</strong><br />

under-deter actors in the defendant’s position? As writer s. e. smith puts it, in a piece on the<br />

connection between environmental toxins <strong>and</strong> disability (including her own), “There’s nothing<br />

wrong with being disabled. But there can be something wrong with the way you become disabled,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to pretend otherwise is to perpetuate injustice.” How might tort law insist, as smith does, that<br />

“[d]isability is not wrong or tragic or bad,” while also, recognizing that sometimes it is a symptom<br />

of a grave injustice”? s. e. smith, When Disability Is a Toxic Legacy, CATAPULT (Apr. 23, 2019)<br />

available at https://perma.cc/4QWP-XAD8. One idea, advanced by legal scholar Anne Bloom, is<br />

for tort law to focus less on restoring the plaintiff to a pre-tort level of well-being, which requires<br />

constantly looking back to an idealized iteration of the plaintiff’s body, <strong>and</strong> more on holding the<br />

defendant accountable, both for the losses <strong>and</strong> suffering the defendant’s actions have caused <strong>and</strong><br />

the difficulties that the plaintiff is likely to encounter going forward in the pursuit of a meaningful<br />

life. Bloom also raises the possibility of damages for “unjust enrichment”—forcing a defendant<br />

to acknowledge <strong>and</strong> disgorge any benefit gained from the act of disabling others. Anne Bloom<br />

with Paul Steven Miller, Blindsight: How We See Disabilities in Tort Litigation, 86 WASH. L.<br />

REV. 709 (2011); see also Sagit Mor, The Meaning of Injury: A Disability Perspective, in INJURY<br />

AND INJUSTICE: THE CULTURAL POLITICS OF HARM AND REDRESS 27 (Anne Bloom, David M.<br />

Engel, & Michael McCann, eds., 2018) (discussing ways to compensate plaintiffs for disabling<br />

harms <strong>and</strong> promote human resilience without reinforcing a tragic view of disability).<br />

632

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!