06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 9. Liability without Fault?<br />

Why would one select a liability rule rather than a property rule as the better remedy?<br />

Calabresi <strong>and</strong> Melamed focus on transaction costs. In those settings in which we think that<br />

transaction costs are low enough that the market will allocate resources to their highest value<br />

users, property rules will be perfectly adequate. But when transaction costs lead us to think that<br />

the market will not allocate resources to their highest value users, liability rules allow actors to<br />

decide to go ahead with conduct so long as that conduct can pay its way.<br />

At this stage, Calabresi <strong>and</strong> Melamed make a breathtaking claim. They contend that the<br />

ongoing character of the injury in nuisance cases, <strong>and</strong> the availability of the injunction remedy for<br />

such ongoing cases, reveal for us a logic underlying tort cases more generally. In those cases, too,<br />

the tort remedy is simply a substitute for the marketplace. <strong>Cases</strong> of completed injuries between<br />

strangers, they suggest, are essentially cases in which the transaction costs were sufficiently high<br />

that we allowed the defendant to impose the risk <strong>and</strong> indeed injury on the plaintiff without her<br />

consent, at the cost of having to pay damages after the fact. We could of course protect plaintiffs’<br />

interests in their bodily integrity or property as against negligent conduct by a property rule; such<br />

a regime might lead to punitive damages or perhaps even criminal punishment in order to force<br />

actors to negotiate up front with possible victims. But we don’t adopt this approach. In tort law,<br />

we allow people to impose risk <strong>and</strong> injury on others—so long as they are willing to pay for it.<br />

Calabresi <strong>and</strong> Melamed’s “View of the Cathedral” (to echo the title of their classic article)<br />

posits a logic for private law generally—for the law of contract, property, <strong>and</strong> tort. In this logic,<br />

tort law’s liability rules substitute for the entitlements of property law when market failures<br />

prevent the law of contract from achieving the right social outcomes. Tort law, in other words,<br />

allows actors like the cement plant in Boomer or a driver in an ordinary automobile accident case<br />

to compel others to bear some of the risks generated by their activity in return for a price set by<br />

the courts. And it typically does so in areas in which the transaction cost obstacles to getting<br />

consent up front are simply too great, either because the consent would have to come from<br />

unreachable strangers (the highway case) or because collective action problems <strong>and</strong> strategic<br />

behavior are likely to prevent an actor from gaining consent.<br />

3. Tort <strong>and</strong> contract in “the Cathedral.” Some say that the Calabresi / Melamed view of tort<br />

reduces tort law to a sort of contract law substitute: one designed to recreate contract’s virtues in<br />

those areas that contracts <strong>and</strong> the market are otherwise unable to reach. How plausible a reading<br />

of the law of torts is this? Consider the cases <strong>and</strong> materials we have reviewed in the past nine<br />

chapters. What, for example, would the Calabresi / Melamed theory hold for relational cases, i.e.,<br />

cases where there is a contract or relationship between the parties such that transaction costs have<br />

not been insuperable? Are these cases in which the terms of the contract itself ought to govern the<br />

torts resolution? Would tort be swallowed up into contract in such cases? Or does tort law supply<br />

something independent in such cases such that it is not simply reduceable to contract?<br />

4. Markets <strong>and</strong> inequality. One critique of the Cathedral is that market-mimicking liability<br />

rules may reflect <strong>and</strong> reproduce economic inequality. In the context of pollution, if liability rules<br />

are imposed, polluting defendants are incentivized to relocate to poorer neighborhoods where the<br />

damages to the neighbors will be less. Even more troublingly, it may sometimes be the case that<br />

the residents of poorer neighborhoods will accept lower monetary compensation for putting up<br />

with pollution. Imagining for the moment that this is so, should we respect such deals?<br />

513

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!