06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 8. Duty Problem<br />

Richard A. Posner, Epstein’s Tort Theory: A Critique, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 457, 460-61 (1979).<br />

Others have argued that taking a potential rescuer’s previous contributions into account would<br />

supply the principled stopping point that Epstein worries does not exist. See T. M. SCANLON,<br />

WHAT WE OWE EACH Other 224 (1998).<br />

6. Moral heuristics? Still another view—one rooted deep in the nineteenth-century<br />

intellectual history of utilitarianism—is that the rule against a duty to rescue is the kind of moral<br />

mistake that “common sense morality” (in philosopher Henry Sidgwick’s phrase from his The<br />

Methods of Ethics 425 (1907)) or the “morality of the multitude” (in John Stuart Mill’s cutting<br />

formulation from his Utilitarianism (1879)) makes when it encounters unusual situations in which<br />

the conventional moral norms fail to advance the general happiness. Cass Sunstein has recently<br />

advanced this argument in an updated form:<br />

It is worth considering the possibility that the act-omission distinction operates as a<br />

heuristic . . . . From the moral point of view, harmful acts are generally worse than<br />

harmful omissions, in terms of both the state of mind of the wrongdoer <strong>and</strong> the likely<br />

consequences of the wrong. A murderer is typically more malicious than a<br />

byst<strong>and</strong>er who refuses to come to the aid of someone who is drowning; the murderer<br />

wants his victim to die, whereas the byst<strong>and</strong>er need have no such desire. In addition,<br />

a murderer typically guarantees death, whereas a byst<strong>and</strong>er may do no such thing.<br />

(I put to one side some complexities about causation.) But in terms of either the<br />

wrongdoer’s state of mind or the consequences, harmful acts are not always worse<br />

than harmful omissions. The moral puzzles arise when life, or a clever interlocutor,<br />

comes up with a case in which there is no morally relevant distinction between acts<br />

<strong>and</strong> omissions, but when moral intuitions . . . strongly suggest that there must be<br />

such a difference. . . .<br />

In such cases, we might hypothesize that moral intuitions reflect an<br />

overgeneralization of principles that usually make sense—but that fail to make<br />

sense in the particular case . . . .<br />

Cass Sunstein, Moral Heuristics, 28 BEHAV. & BRAIN SCI. 531 (2005).<br />

If Mill, Sidgwick, <strong>and</strong> Sunstein are correct—if the confusion around the no-duty rule is<br />

the result of what Sidgwick called the “Unconscious Utilitarianism” of everyday moral<br />

distinctions such as act <strong>and</strong> omission—what should the law do? On the one h<strong>and</strong>, Mill urged us<br />

to see such situations as ones of moral confusion to be corrected by an explicit utilitarian calculus<br />

such as the one contained in Ames’s proposal. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, common sense morality’s value<br />

as a proxy or heuristic for complex utilitarian calculations might be undermined if the law<br />

dropped the pretense of common sense morality in hard cases. The use of everyday morality as a<br />

proxy for utilitarianism might, as Sidgwick observed, require the rule makers to mislead the<br />

public about the real basis of the moral rules. HENRY SIDGWICK, THE METHODS OF ETHICS 447<br />

(7th ed. 1981).<br />

387

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!