06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 5. Plaintiffs’ Conduct<br />

The basic point is that if both sides have good information, it makes no difference<br />

that consumers can’t haggle in particular transactions, <strong>and</strong> it makes no difference<br />

that the sellers’ lawyers draft the contracts. The profit motive will induce them to<br />

provide any legal duty consumers will pay for. Consumers exercise power in the<br />

market not through their conduct during individual transactions, but through the<br />

mechanism of dem<strong>and</strong>, backed by dollars. They can control according to their<br />

desires what is offered for sale even if each of them is individually powerless in<br />

every single transaction. . . .<br />

Id. It follows for Kennedy that unequal bargaining power cannot be an explanation of particular<br />

substantive terms in consumer contracts. There should thus be no need for courts to impose<br />

compulsory duties in such contexts:<br />

Id.<br />

[U]nder our assumptions the compulsory term must be worth less to buyers than it<br />

costs sellers (or sellers would provide it without compulsion), [yet] it is also true<br />

that the term will almost certainly be worth something. Buyers would, in a free<br />

market, pay more for the commodity with the duties attached than for the<br />

commodity alone . . . .<br />

4. Poverty. What arguments (if any) remain against enforcing the terms of the contract<br />

struck between Dalury <strong>and</strong> S-K-I? Professor Kennedy does note at least one limit on his analysis:<br />

[D]em<strong>and</strong>, of course, is limited by income. If buyers had a lot more income, they<br />

might well dem<strong>and</strong> all the duties the decision maker is now requiring them to<br />

purchase. Buyers as a group may regard a transaction without these duties as a<br />

moral horror. They may buy only with deep regret, believing that they have a right<br />

to the commodity-plus-the-duty rather than just the commodity. They may believe<br />

that a just society would allocate them enough purchasing power so that it was open<br />

to them to buy the commodity-plus-the-duty without having to sacrifice some other<br />

good they regard as a necessity. In all these senses, it is true that consumers lack<br />

the bargaining power to make the sellers provide the duty. Consumers are too poor,<br />

given the other things they want to do or have to do with their money, to induce<br />

sellers to provide something that, under the free contract model, sellers don’t have<br />

to provide unless the price is right.<br />

Kennedy, Distributive <strong>and</strong> Paternalist Motives, supra. If Kennedy is right that poverty rather<br />

than unequal bargaining power explains the substantive terms of consumer contracts, what is the<br />

implication for adjudication? Should pro-consumer terms be compulsory, as the Dalury court<br />

concluded? Or are compulsory terms counterproductive from the perspective of the poor<br />

consumer’s welfare?<br />

5. Arbitration. One striking feature of the world of tort waivers is that consumers are<br />

typically not asked to agree to arbitrate tort claims. They are more typically asked to waive those<br />

claims altogether. Why would that be? Note that some medical care providers such as Kaiser<br />

287

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!