06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 5. Plaintiffs’ Conduct<br />

If primary assumption of the risk <strong>and</strong> secondary assumption of the risk are both different<br />

doctrines in disguise, perhaps we should not have them at all. For much of the twentieth century,<br />

leading jurists thought so. In a Federal Employers’ Liability Act case from 1943, Associate<br />

Justice Felix Frankfurter put it this way:<br />

The phrase “assumption of risk” is an excellent illustration of the extent to which<br />

uncritical use of words bedevils the law. A phrase begins life as a literary<br />

expression; its felicity leads to its lazy repetition; <strong>and</strong> repetition soon establishes it<br />

as a legal formula, undiscriminatingly used to express different <strong>and</strong> sometimes<br />

contrary ideas.<br />

Tiller v. Atlantic Coast Line R. Co., 318 U.S. 54, 68 (1943) (Frankfurter, J., concurring). As<br />

Justice Frankfurter saw it, “the phrase ‘assumption of risk’ gave judicial expression to a social<br />

policy that entailed much human misery.” Id. at 69. Indeed, some commentators sympathetic to<br />

Frankfurter’s view took him a step further <strong>and</strong> concluded that the “doctrine [of implied<br />

assumption of risk] deserves no separate existence . . . <strong>and</strong> is simply a confusing way of stating<br />

certain no-duty rules.” Fleming James, Jr., Assumption of Risk: Unhappy Reincarnation, 78 YALE<br />

L.J. 185, 187–188 (1968); see also Francis H. Bohlen, Voluntary Assumption of Risk, 20 HARV. L.<br />

REV. 14 (1906).<br />

2. The durability of assumption of the risk. Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing the withering critique in the<br />

middle of the last century, the doctrinal label “assumption of the risk” has proven exceedingly<br />

durable. The Restatement (Second) of <strong>Torts</strong> retained the language, despite criticism. And in<br />

some jurisdictions, assumption of the risk in the secondary sense has neither been done away<br />

with, nor treated as a mere subcategory of comparative negligence. That is the lesson of the<br />

L<strong>and</strong>ings Association case: Georgia is a comparative fault state, but the Georgia Supreme Court<br />

treated Mrs. Williams’s conduct as different from ordinary unreasonable conduct. Her conscious<br />

decision to take the risk in question did not get factored in on the balance alongside that of the<br />

L<strong>and</strong>ings Association in a comparative fault analysis, as the California approach of Knight v.<br />

Jewett would require. To the contrary, the court treated her conscious decision to walk as grounds<br />

for holding the L<strong>and</strong>ings Association not liable at all.<br />

One observer views L<strong>and</strong>ings Association <strong>and</strong> similar cases as indicating that “[r]eports of<br />

the death of assumption of risk are slightly exaggerated.” Professor Simons acknowledges that<br />

the majority of states have folded secondary assumption of risk into their comparative negligence<br />

regimes, but he suggests that the doctrine’s legacy lives on, especially in courts’ duty analyses:<br />

[T]he supposed legal irrelevance of “consent” to a risk of harm, celebrated by the<br />

modern “merger” approach, is overstated. And the supposition that consensual<br />

norms have been completely replaced by norms of reasonableness is also incorrect.<br />

A number of courts do continue to recognize assumption of risk as a distinct<br />

substantive doctrine (<strong>and</strong> not simply as a label for other doctrines). Moreover, even<br />

abolitionist courts recognize numerous no-duty doctrines that implicitly rely upon<br />

a consensual rationale of the sort that underlies many versions of assumption of risk.<br />

Kenneth W. Simons, Reflections on Assumption of Risk, 50 U.C.L.A. L. REV. 481, 483 (2002).<br />

280

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!