06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 4. Negligence St<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

Judgment for the defendant. All concurred.<br />

Notes<br />

1. A social endeavor. The plaintiff in Cooley tried to prove negligence by focusing on the<br />

costs <strong>and</strong> benefits of the defendant’s actions in relation to her. Judge Page rejected this argument,<br />

demonstrating the courts’ use of cost-benefit analysis as a social—rather than private—<br />

calculation; he analyzes the reasonableness of the defendant’s safety technology as applied to all<br />

foreseeable plaintiffs. Does this make sense? How well do you think a social cost-benefit<br />

analysis fits into the plaintiff-driven, two-party nature of the tort system?<br />

2. Activities <strong>and</strong> activity levels—<strong>and</strong> the strict liability alternative. The plaintiff in Cooley<br />

offers an alternative technology to make operating phone lines safer. But what if the act of<br />

operating phone lines with due care is not enough? What if engaging in the activity itself is<br />

negligent? Can the tort system deter activities that are unsafe because of the levels of the activity<br />

that people engage in? Steven Shavell criticizes the negligence regime for failing to adequately<br />

address the problem of over-participation in unsafe activities:<br />

By definition, under the negligence rule all that an injurer needs to do to avoid the<br />

possibility of liability is to make sure to exercise due care if he engages in his<br />

activity. Consequently he will not be motivated to consider the effect on accident<br />

losses of his choice of whether to engage in his activity or, more generally, of the<br />

level at which to engage in his activity; he will choose his level of activity in<br />

accordance only with the personal benefits so derived. But surely any increase in<br />

his level of activity will typically raise expected accident losses (holding constant<br />

the level of care). Thus he will be led to choose too high a level of activity; the<br />

negligence rule is not “efficient.” . . .<br />

However, under a rule of strict liability, the situation is different. Because an injurer<br />

must pay for losses whenever he is involved in an accident, he will be induced to<br />

consider the effect on accident losses of both his level of care <strong>and</strong> his level of<br />

activity. His decisions will therefore be efficient. Because drivers will be liable for<br />

losses sustained by pedestrians, they will decide not only to exercise due care in<br />

driving but also to drive only when the utility gained from it outweighs expected<br />

liability payments to pedestrians.<br />

Steven Shavell, Strict Liability versus Negligence, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 1, 2-3 (1980).<br />

Is there a way to incorporate unsafe levels of activity into a cost-benefit analysis of due<br />

care? Calabresi offers another alternative to the negligence regime to address this problem in his<br />

classic “The Decision for Accidents”:<br />

There are acts or activities that we would bar in our society regardless of the<br />

willingness of the doer to pay for the harm they cause. It is these that we call<br />

“useless” <strong>and</strong> feel that there is no societal loss in deterring them specifically. But<br />

certainly even if some such activities can be isolated, there are a great many other<br />

176

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!