06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 4. Negligence St<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

There are exceptions to the principle that every man is presumed to possess ordinary<br />

capacity to avoid harm to his neighbors, which illustrate the rule, <strong>and</strong> also the moral basis of<br />

liability in general. When a man has a distinct defect of such a nature that all can recognize it as<br />

making certain precautions impossible, he will not be held answerable for not taking them. A<br />

blind man is not required to see at his peril; <strong>and</strong> although he is, no doubt, bound to consider his<br />

infirmity in regulating his actions, yet if he properly finds himself in a certain situation, the<br />

neglect of precautions requiring eyesight would not prevent his recovering for an injury to<br />

himself, <strong>and</strong>, it may be presumed, would not make him liable for injuring another. So it is held<br />

that, in cases where he is the plaintiff, an infant of very tender years is only bound to take the<br />

precautions of which an infant is capable; the same principle may be cautiously applied where he<br />

is defendant. Insanity is a more difficult matter to deal with, <strong>and</strong> no general rule can be laid down<br />

about it. There is no doubt that in many cases a man may be insane, <strong>and</strong> yet perfectly capable of<br />

taking the precautions, <strong>and</strong> of being influenced by the motives, which the circumstances dem<strong>and</strong>.<br />

But if insanity of a pronounced type exists, manifestly incapacitating the sufferer from complying<br />

with the rule which he has broken, good sense would require it to be admitted as an excuse.<br />

Notes<br />

1. The “reasonable man” is born. Together, Vaughan v. Menlove <strong>and</strong> the Holmes excerpt<br />

above sketch the contours of the “reasonable man,” the st<strong>and</strong>ard at the heart of modern negligence<br />

law. They do so by taking up the question of which features, if any, particular to the party ought<br />

to be relevant to the evaluation of that person’s conduct. Vaughan concludes that lack of ordinary<br />

intelligence is not an excuse for failing to live up to the st<strong>and</strong>ard of ordinary care. It adopts what<br />

we call an objective approach to the reasonableness inquiry: rather than asking whether the<br />

defendant acted reasonably in light of the defendant’s personal characteristics <strong>and</strong> capabilities<br />

(which would privilege the defendant’s subjectivity), the chosen approach abstracts away from the<br />

particular features of the defendant <strong>and</strong> asks whether the defendant’s conduct was reasonable on<br />

the basis of an external social st<strong>and</strong>ard. The Restatement puts it this way: “Unless the actor is a<br />

child” (more on this in the pages that follow), “the st<strong>and</strong>ard of conduct to which he must conform<br />

to avoid being negligent is that of a reasonable man under like circumstances.” RESTATEMENT<br />

(SECOND) OF TORTS § 283 (1965); see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PHYS. & EMOT.<br />

HARM § 3 & cmt. a (2010) (defining negligence as failure to “exercise reasonable care under all<br />

the circumstances,” where “the ‘reasonable care st<strong>and</strong>ard . . . is basically the same as a st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

expressed in terms of the ‘reasonably careful person’”). If a person does their best within the<br />

limits of their own intellectual or cognitive capacities to act reasonably carefully—acting “bona<br />

fide to the best of their judgment,” as the defendant’s lawyer put it in Vaughan—have they acted<br />

wrongfully when they nonetheless fall short of society’s expectations? If not, why does tort law<br />

embrace a st<strong>and</strong>ard that allows liability in this situation?<br />

2. Is the reasonable person a rational actor? One view of the facts in Vaughan is that the<br />

defendant acted in accordance with what a rational person in his circumstances might do. “[H]is<br />

stock,” after all, “was insured.” Why not “chance it”? Does tort law’s “reasonable person”<br />

behave in the same way as a “rational person”? If not, when might their actions diverge?<br />

136

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!