06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 3. Strict Liability <strong>and</strong> Negligence<br />

Notes<br />

1. Is strict liability possible? In Ryl<strong>and</strong>s, the Court of Exchequer <strong>and</strong> the House of Lords<br />

purported to identify a basis for liability other than negligence. Many have characterized the<br />

Ryl<strong>and</strong>s case as a form of “strict liability.” But what does that mean? Strict liability, as Professor<br />

Stephen Perry points out, may not be conceptually available, at least not if it simply means causebased<br />

liability. After all, both the plaintiff <strong>and</strong> the defendant in Ryl<strong>and</strong>s were causes of the injury<br />

at issue; no injury would have taken place had the plaintiff not been mining coal, just as no injury<br />

would have taken place had the defendant not built a reservoir. See Stephen R. Perry, The<br />

Impossibility of Strict Liability, 1 CAN J. L. & JURISPRUDENCE 147, 169-70 (1988). To put it a<br />

different way: causation alone does not distinguish between the two parties to the case. So what<br />

then is the ground for liability offered by the judges in Ryl<strong>and</strong>s who differ with Judge Martin’s<br />

negligence st<strong>and</strong>ard?<br />

2. The reciprocity view. In discussing the defense of necessity in Vincent v. Lake Erie<br />

Transportation Co., above, we noted the argument advanced by torts jurists like George Fletcher<br />

that the real basis for the liability in torts is the imposition of a non-reciprocal risk. Fletcher<br />

contends that Ryl<strong>and</strong>s is precisely such a case: “The critical feature of [Ryl<strong>and</strong>s] is that the<br />

defendant created a risk of harm to the plaintiff that was of an order different from the risks that<br />

the plaintiff imposed on the defendant.” George Fletcher, Fairness <strong>and</strong> Utility in Tort Theory, 85<br />

HARV. L. REV. 537, 546 (1971). Does the reciprocity argument offer a sound basis for allocating<br />

the cost of the harm to the reservoir-building defendant in Ryl<strong>and</strong>s? Critics insist that the<br />

reciprocity argument is just as circular here in Ryl<strong>and</strong>s as it was in Vincent. It is circular because<br />

the relative risks of the activities turn on tort law’s underlying allocation of those risks. If the<br />

plaintiff coal miner has the right to compensation for the costs imposed by the defendant reservoir<br />

builder’s conduct, then the defendant has created a risk of harm for itself, not for the plaintiff.<br />

The risk to the coal mining plaintiff is only asymmetrical if we imagine a baseline of what<br />

belongs to whom in the situation. But that of course is precisely what the torts judge is supposed<br />

to do to resolve the dispute in the first place!<br />

3. First in time? What about a first-in-time principle? The coal mine operator was removing<br />

coal from the l<strong>and</strong> before the construction of the defendant’s large new reservoir <strong>and</strong> mill. Should<br />

this timing factor be enough to decide the case, or should temporal priority be disregarded? Does<br />

it matter that the defendant already operated a much smaller reservoir <strong>and</strong> mill nearby? Note, too,<br />

that the plaintiff <strong>and</strong> the defendant were linked in a web of contracts with a common l<strong>and</strong>lord. If<br />

the parties had contemplated risks like the one that came to fruition, what kind of a term would<br />

they have adopted in their respective leases to deal with it?<br />

4. Unusual behavior. Another possible justification for the Ryl<strong>and</strong>s outcome focuses on the<br />

kinds of conduct that are ordinary in the neighborhood. When actors engage in new or otherwise<br />

unusual activities, others may not be in a position to anticipate the risks that such conduct poses.<br />

Does this distinction offer a ground for explaining the Ryl<strong>and</strong>s case?<br />

123

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!