06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 2. Intentional Harms<br />

demonstrates the distinctiveness of the wrong of trespass to l<strong>and</strong>. Vincent, we<br />

believe, is a plain-vanilla trespass case. The ship owner intentionally occupied the<br />

defendant’s property (the dock) even after it was no longer permitted to do so. It<br />

therefore committed a trespass for which compensation was owed. Of course its<br />

decision to trespass was entirely reasonable. However—as we have emphasized all<br />

along—the wrong of trespass, at least in the first instance, has nothing to do with<br />

whether the defendant behaved reasonably. . . .<br />

Even though the reasonableness of the trespass in Vincent does not prevent it from<br />

being a trespass, it does have some significance on the outcome of the case. . . .<br />

[T]he same circumstances that explain why the captain’s decision to stay put was<br />

entirely reasonable also explain why the dock owner in Vincent, like the dock owner<br />

in Ploof, would have faced liability if it had forcibly ejected the Reynolds from the<br />

dock, thereby causing it or its crew to suffer harm. A property owner has a limited<br />

privilege to take measures to ward off trespassers [but] as we saw in Katko v. Briney,<br />

a property possessor cannot do just anything in response to trespasses. Ploof tells<br />

us that if a property owner expels trespassers under circumstances where the<br />

expulsion exposes them to a grave risk of death or bodily harm, the property owner<br />

will have abused his privilege to defend his property <strong>and</strong> therefore will be subject<br />

to liability for battery.<br />

JOHN C. P. GOLDBERG & BENJAMIN C. ZIPURSKY, THE OXFORD INTRODUCTIONS TO U.S. LAW:<br />

TORTS (2010). What, in Goldberg’s <strong>and</strong> Zipursky’s view, explains why the dockowner may not<br />

forcibly unmoor the shipowner? Do Goldberg <strong>and</strong> Zipursky have an account of this feature of the<br />

legal structure, or does their theory beg the question of whence the privilege comes?<br />

5. The economic view of Vincent. A very different set of accounts of tort law <strong>and</strong> of cases<br />

like Vincent emphasizes the economic logic of the case. In this view, the aim of the law should be<br />

to allocate liability to the party best positioned <strong>and</strong> incentivized to minimize the costs of<br />

accidents. Costs should be allocated, in other words, to the best cost avoider. See GUIDO<br />

CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS (1970).<br />

Note, however, that cases like Vincent pose two wrinkles. The first is that it can be very<br />

hard for an adjudicator to accurately gauge which party is better positioned to minimize accident<br />

costs. The second is that it is not always clear that adjudicators will in fact always be able to<br />

decide that question, at least as a prospective matter. Will shipowners in Minnesota bear the risk<br />

of Vincent-like damages in future Vincent-like situations? One might think so having just read the<br />

case. But if we allow shipowners <strong>and</strong> dockowners to trade the risks before those risks come to<br />

fruition, we should expect to see the risk freely traded, even if the common law tort rule allocates<br />

it to ship owners as an initial matter.<br />

This insight has made the Vincent decision a classic case for the discussion of what<br />

economists <strong>and</strong> lawyers call the Coase Theorem. In a famous article, Nobel Prize-winning<br />

economist Ronald Coase contended that absent transaction costs, rational parties will transact to<br />

allocate the entitlements to their highest value user regardless of the initial allocation of legal<br />

entitlements. Parties will do so in order to maximize the joint value of the entitlement in question.<br />

Coase gave the analogy of a then-recent British case brought by a physician against a neighboring<br />

baker whose noisy machinery interfered with his medical practice. The court had allocated the<br />

90

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!