25.06.2020 Views

epdf.pub_the-nuts-and-bolts-of-proofs-third-edition-an-intr

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Special Kinds of Theorems 53

As both d and m are positive numbers larger than or equal to 2 and

smaller than or equal to k, by inductive hypothesis they are either

primes or product of prime numbers.

If they are both prime numbers, the statement is proved.

If at least one of them is not prime, we can replace it with its prime

factors. So fc + 1 will be a product of prime factors in any case.

Therefore, by the second principle of mathematical induction, the statement

is true for all natural numbers n > 1. •

The adjectives "strong" and "weak" attached to the two statements of

the principle of mathematical induction are not always used in the same

way by different authors and they are misleading. When reading the

two statements, it is easy to see that the strong principle of mathematical

induction implies the principle of mathematical induction. Indeed, the

inductive hypothesis of the principle of mathematical induction assumes

that the given statement is true just for an arbitrary number n. The inductive

hypothesis of the strong principle of mathematical induction assumes that

the given statement is true for all the numbers between the one covered

by the base case and an arbitrary number n.

In reahty, these two principles are equivalent. The proof of this claim is not

easy; it consists of proving that both principles are equivalent to a third

principle, the well-ordering principle (see the material in the front of the

book). So, in turn, the strong principle of mathematical induction and the

principle of mathematical induction are equivalent to each other.

Then which one of the two principles should be used in a proof by

induction? The first answer is that really it does not make any difference, as

one could always use the strong principle of mathematical induction, in

general, when proving equalities, the principle of mathematical induction is

sufficient. For some mathematicians, it is a matter of elegance and beauty to

use as httle machinery as possible when constructing a proof; therefore, they

prefer to use the principle of mathematical induction whenever possible.

We will consider another example that requires the use of the strong

principle of mathematical induction.

EXAMPLE 4. A polynomial of degree n > 1 with real coefficients has at

most n real zeroes, not all necessarily distinct.

Proof:

1. Base case. The statement is true for the smallest number we can

consider, which is 1. Indeed a polynomial of degree 1 is of the form

P{x) = aiX-\-ao with a\ ^ 0. Its zero is the number x = -ao/ai. So, a

polynomial of degree 1 with real coefficients has one real zero.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!