25.06.2020 Views

epdf.pub_the-nuts-and-bolts-of-proofs-third-edition-an-intr

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Introduction and Basic Terminology 7

introduced. Indeed, all the results already established and all the definitions

already stated as parts of a context can be used in the construction of

the proofs of other results in that same context. As this book focuses more

on the "nuts and bolts" of proof design than on the development of a

mathematical theory, it does not include the construction of a mathematical

setting for the material presented. This approach is supposed to provide the

reader with the basic tools to use for the construction of proofs in a variety

of mathematical settings.

At this point we want to emphasize the difference between the vaHdity of

an argument and the truth or falsity of the results of an argument. An

argument is valid if its hypothesis suppHes sufficient and certain basis for the

conclusion to be reached. An argument can be vaHd and reach a false

conclusion, as in the following example, in which one of the hypotheses

is false.

All birds are able to fly.

Penguins are birds.

Therefore, penguins are able to fly.

An argument can be invahd and reach a true conclusion. Consider the

following argument:

Cows have four legs.

Giraffes have four legs.

Therefore, giraffes are taller than cows.

In the example just given, it is clear that the information we have (cows have

four legs; giraffes have four legs) does not imply that "giraffes are taller that

cows," which is nonetheless a true fact. The only conclusion we could

legitimately reach is that giraffes and cows have the same number of legs.

In other cases the possible flaws in the reasoning process are more subtle.

Consider the following argument.

// Joe wins the state lottery, he can afford a new car.

Joe did not win the state lottery.

Therefore, Joe cannot afford a new car.

The hypotheses for this argument are: If Joe wins the state lottery, he can

afford a new car. Joe did not win the state lottery. The conclusion reached is:

Joe cannot afford a new car.

This is an example of incorrect (nonvahd) reasoning. Indeed, Joe did not

win the state lottery, so he might not be able to afford a new car (the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!