02.03.2020 Views

Social Justice Activism

Social Justice Activism

Social Justice Activism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

FAMILIES IN SOCIETY • Volume 83, Number 4

During the twentieth century, the most popular approach

to the problem of distribution was based on utilitarian

arguments, whose calculus presupposes the rational

ordering of social goods to achieve what John Stuart Mill

(1971) termed the “greatest net balance of satisfaction” for

society. In the late twentieth century, this view was often

linked with the assumption that the prioritization of social

goals occurs through a process equally accessible to all

members of society in a manner that promotes generalized

benevolence. Yet, in his contemporary classic, A Theory of

Justice (1971, 1999), Rawls argues that as a philosophical

guide utilitarianism creates no imperative of social justice,

since it can be used to rationalize a concentration of goods

benefiting the privileged classes of society. Instead, the justice

of a system must be measured, he argued, based “on

how fundamental rights and duties are assigned and on the

economic opportunities and social conditions in the various

sectors of society” (p. 7; see also Rawls, 2001).

Rawls based his conception of distributive justice on the

premise that “all social values … are to be distributed equally

unless an unequal distribution of any, or all, of these values

is to everyone’s advantage” (p. 62). He derived what he

called his maximin theory from two fundamental principles:

• Each person has an equal right to the most extensive system

of personal liberty compatible with a system of total liberty

for all

• Social and economic inequality are to be arranged so that

they are both (a) to the greatest benefit to the least advantaged

in society and (b) attached to positions open to all

under conditions of fair equality of opportunity

From these principles of justice, Rawls articulated a

“principle of redress,” which established the philosophical

basis for social policies directed toward a more just distribution

of social goods. Other scholars have applied this

principle to support policies like affirmative action and

reparations for African Americans (Maguire, 1980; Robinson,

2000). As stated by Rawls, the principle seems particularly

well-suited to the social work profession’s goal of

eliminating racial, gender, and economic inequalities.

Undeserved inequalities call for redress; and since

inequalities of birth and natural endowment are

undeserved, these inequalities are to be somehow

compensated for. Thus, the principle holds that in

order to treat all persons equally, to provide genuine

equality of opportunity, society must give more attention

to those with fewer native assets and to those

born into the less favorable social positions. The idea

is to redress the bias of contingencies in the direction

of equality. (1971, p. 100)

This view of distributive justice found adherents in religious

circles as well. In their famous pastoral letter

(1986), the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops went

even further than Rawls. The bishops asserted that “distributive

justice requires that the allocation of income,

wealth, and power in society be evaluated in light of its effect

on persons whose basic needs are unmet” (paragraph

70). The document also stated that “social justice implies

that persons have an obligation to be active and productive

participants in the life of society and that society has a

duty to enable them to participate in this way.” Thus, the

concept of social justice “also includes a duty to organize

economic and social institutions so that people can contribute

to society in ways that respect their freedom and the dignity

of their labor” (paragraphs 71 & 72, emphases added).

Part of the appeal of Rawls’ theory and the Bishops’ letter

is in the synthesis they forged between two competing

meta-analyses—liberalism and socialism—whose conflicting

influences have been regarded as central to the development

of modern Western social welfare (George &

Wilding, 1994). Rawls’ “difference principle” and the duties

articulated by the pastoral letter seek to equalize life

chances for people across racial, gender, and class lines, but

never at the expense of the basic liberal freedoms protected

by the “equal liberty principle” (Tomasi, 2001; Gutman,

1989; Moon, 1988; Sandel, 1982; Ackerman, 1980).

This synthesis is particularly compelling for the social work

profession because of its historic emphasis on both the

preservation of individual human rights and dignity—best

expressed through the concept of self-determination—and

the redistribution of resources to promote the well-being

of disadvantaged populations (National Association of Social

Workers, 1996). It also offers social reformers a conceptual

escape from the trap laid by conservative opponents

of social welfare that have often obfuscated appeals for justice-centered

social policies by labeling them with antidemocratic

rhetoric, such as quotas (Hayek, 1976; Mead,

1986; Nozick, 1974; Sunstein, 1997).

Two fundamental problems are often overlooked, however,

in discussions of applying justice principles to contemporary

social policy debates. The first is the paradox of

attempting to develop principles of justice within a political,

economic, and social context based largely, if tacitly, on

the preservation of injustice. As Smith (1988) argues, “the

longstanding history of invidious discrimination in the

United States demonstrates that attention must always be

paid to the threats [it] poses to liberal values” (p. 247).

346

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!