08.04.2019 Views

ARISTOTLE AND THE EARLIER PERIPATETICS vol.I by Eduard Zeller, B.F.C.Costelloe 1897

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine) ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!! Strabo – “Geography” “There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.” (Strab. 7.fragments.9) ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine)

ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!!

Strabo – “Geography”
“There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.”
(Strab. 7.fragments.9)

ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

;<br />

;<br />

<strong>ARISTOTLE</strong>'S WRITINGS 113<br />

works a form of exposition which must make them unintelligible<br />

to any but his scholars ; ' while at the same<br />

time it is said that it was here only that he disclosed his<br />

views in their full logical connection. 2 On this theory<br />

the ' exoteric ' writings were broadly distinguished from<br />

the ' acroatic,' just <strong>by</strong> the fact that they were intended<br />

for a wider public, and that they were therefore put in<br />

a more popular form, did not cover the more difficult<br />

classes of inquiry, and substituted for a severe and<br />

scientific method of proof one more accommodated to<br />

general comprehension. 3<br />

1<br />

This idea is expressed in<br />

the answer of Aristotle to Alexander<br />

(see Gell. ibid.'), when he<br />

replies to the reproach of the<br />

latter with regard totheaKpoanKol<br />

\6yoi : XgQl oiv ainovs Kal iKtieBofievous<br />

Kal fify 4KSe5ofievovs ' l-vverol<br />

yap elffi fi6vots rots rifiav aKoiffaffiv.<br />

See also Themist. Or. xxvi. 319,<br />

A sq., where it is said that Aristotle<br />

did not find the same discourses<br />

suitable for the masses<br />

as for the philosophers, and therefore<br />

withdrew the highest secrets<br />

of his teaching (the re'Aea Upa,<br />

the fivvTitcbv) from the former <strong>by</strong><br />

using obscure language. Simpl.<br />

Phys. 2, b, referring to the letters<br />

just mentioned, says : ty toTs<br />

anpoafiaTMois iurdtpeiav ^reT^Sevtre,<br />

&c.<br />

For the same view see Categ.<br />

Schol. 27, a, 38, David, Categ.<br />

Schol. 22, a,, 20 ; 27, a, 18 sq. In<br />

the same sense Lucian, V. Auet.<br />

c. 26, calls Aristotle SittAoSj, aWos<br />

[lev d eKTOff&ev repiicd.<br />

' Kal yap 4v tKelvots TrAettrra<br />

Kal 7rcpl tSc tiSikHv Kal irepX tSiv<br />

(pvaiKwv eV5fJ|a»s \4yerat.' But the<br />

example of the Topics and the<br />

MAetoric shows that this only<br />

refers to the basis of the opinions<br />

laid down in these writings, the<br />

argument from the universally<br />

acknowledged (the ft/$o|oi/), and<br />

not to the teaching as such. The<br />

later writers, as a rule, express<br />

themselves in the same sense<br />

thus Simpl. Pkys. 164, a: lfo>-<br />

Tepuca Se ioTi ra xou/a Kal Si'<br />

4v56£av irepaiv6fi€Pa aAAa [xt] airo-<br />

SeiKTLKa fitjSh aKpoafmriicd. As to<br />

Ammon. and David, see following<br />

note ;<br />

and cf. Philop. Phys.<br />

p. 4. On the other hand David,<br />

Schol. in Ar. 24, b, 33, changes<br />

the statement of Alexander<br />

(which he quotes in order to refute<br />

it) into : 8ti iv fiiv roh ixpoafiariKois<br />

to BoKovyra a&T$ \eyei Kal<br />

ra oAtjOtj, iv Si toij SiaKoyucoh to<br />

aWois tioicovirra, to i^cuSt}.<br />

3<br />

Besides the testimony already<br />

adduced, the statements<br />

found in the Neoplatonic com-<br />

114 <strong>ARISTOTLE</strong><br />

The theory just mentioned can be traced as far back<br />

as Andronicus, perhaps even farther ; ' but this does<br />

not put its correctness beyond question.<br />

It is, however,<br />

confirmed in the main, even if it requires correction in<br />

one point or another, <strong>by</strong> the utterances of Aristotle<br />

himself as to the ' Exoteric Discourses.' It is true that<br />

in a general sense he may describe as ' exoteric ' any<br />

topic which does not belong to the inquiry immediately<br />

mentators go to establish this<br />

point. Thus the so-called Ammon.<br />

in Categ. 6, b sqq. (see also Stahr,<br />

AristoteMa, ii. 255 sqq.), who,<br />

after some other divisions of the<br />

the Aristotelian writings, among<br />

'<br />

syntagmatic ones distinguishes<br />

'<br />

aiiTOirp6ff(i)ira nal aKpoaparticb. and<br />

8ia\oyiKh kuI i |aiTfpiica. The former<br />

are written irpbs yvi\aiovs<br />

aKpoaras, the latter irpbs riiv tusv<br />

isoKKaiv ntyiXtiav; in the former<br />

Aristotle expresses his own<br />

opinion with a strictly scientific<br />

argument, in the latter rcfc So-<br />

Kovvra aoT6Taij/ l<br />

Kal oh olol re<br />

elo'tv ol iroWol iiraicoKovdeiv. Similarly,<br />

only at greater length,<br />

David, Schol. 24, a, 20 sqq., who<br />

likewise divides the trvprayp-aTindi<br />

into avTowpdo'ctnra or a/cpOajuccn/cct<br />

and SiaXoyuch, & koX ^atrepiKa Aeyovrtu<br />

and considers the former<br />

to have been written itpbs robs<br />

£iriT7]deiovs rf tptKotroQlq, the<br />

latter irpbs cLveiriTT)Seiovs irpbs l\offotpiav,<br />

and hence the former Si'<br />

avayicaffTLK&v \6ycov, the latter<br />

Sik iriBavav. Cf. p. 1 11, n. 4.<br />

1<br />

In proof of this statement<br />

we cannot attach so much importance<br />

to the passage just<br />

given from David as Heitz does<br />

(Verl. Selir. 25 sq.). The fact<br />

that David (24, b, 5) expressly<br />

appeals to Ammonius (n. epA"7"<br />

veias) and to the commentary on<br />

the Categories passing under Ammonius'<br />

name (which, although in<br />

its present form it does not<br />

come from Ammonius, yet seems<br />

to have originated in one written<br />

<strong>by</strong> him), indicates that Ammonius<br />

was David's proximate authority<br />

and though he (Ammonius) certainly<br />

made use of earlier writers<br />

(and principally Alexander, whom<br />

David at 24, b, 33 attacks, and<br />

from whom his quotation of the<br />

Aristotelian Evdemus is probably<br />

taken, like that in Philop. De<br />

An. 'E, 2 sq.; Ar. Fr. p. 3481,<br />

No. 41), still we do not know<br />

how much has been added to<br />

their testimony. On the other<br />

hand we must trace the statements<br />

in Cicero, Strabo, and<br />

Gellius(ra

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!