08.04.2019 Views

ARISTOTLE AND THE EARLIER PERIPATETICS vol.I by Eduard Zeller, B.F.C.Costelloe 1897

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine) ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!! Strabo – “Geography” “There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.” (Strab. 7.fragments.9) ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine)

ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!!

Strabo – “Geography”
“There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.”
(Strab. 7.fragments.9)

ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

;<br />

PHYSICS 473<br />

*<br />

most primitive and ancient bodies. Those, on the<br />

contrary, which exhibit a composite movement, must be<br />

formed <strong>by</strong> combination from them, and receive their<br />

particular bias from the constituent which preponderates<br />

in their composition. That which is natural is<br />

always earlier than that which is opposed to nature and<br />

violent. It follows that circular, and also rectilineal,<br />

movement must be naturally fitted for some body or<br />

other, the more so that rotation is the only unbroken and<br />

interminable movement, and nothing that is<br />

contrary<br />

to nature fulfils these conditions. Accordingly there<br />

must exist two sorts of simple bodies— the<br />

one originally<br />

destined for rectilineal, the other for circular, movement.<br />

1 Eectilineal movement has opposite directions :<br />

it is either upwards or downwards, passing from centre<br />

to circumference, or «ice versa. Consequent!}', the bodies<br />

which exhibit it<br />

must be of opposite natures, destined<br />

for the one or the other kind of motion :<br />

be either light or heavy.<br />

hand, exhibits no such contraries.<br />

towards any point in the circumference.<br />

that is, they must<br />

Circular motion, on the other<br />

It starts from any point<br />

So the body<br />

which is naturally qualified for it must likewise be without<br />

contrariety.<br />

It can neither be heavy nor light, since<br />

it does not rise or fall, and in fact it cannot exhibit any<br />

kind of rectilineal motion.<br />

It is even impossible to communicate<br />

either upward or downward motion to it <strong>by</strong> force,<br />

since if the one were unnatural to it the other must 2 be<br />

distinction between two realms already laid down (c. 2, 269, a,<br />

of being is obvious from his 10, 14) as the basis of the diswhole<br />

treatment of the subject, cussion (see p. 224, n. 3), %v hi<br />

Cf. also p. 366, n. 1. ivarriov, which, when thus uni-<br />

1<br />

Be Calo, i. 2, 268, b, 14 sqq. versally expressed, is certainly<br />

'<br />

According to the principle open to dispute.<br />

474 <strong>ARISTOTLE</strong><br />

its natural motion. 1<br />

motion is<br />

The body that is destined for circular<br />

also without beginning or ending, subject to<br />

neither increase nor diminution, neither impression nor<br />

change. 2<br />

comes into<br />

being springs from its opposite, and everything<br />

that<br />

His argument for this is that everything that<br />

perishes is resolved into the same<br />

3 all increase<br />

and decrease depend upon addition or subtraction<br />

of the matter out of which a thing has grown, and therefore<br />

that which, being without beginning, possesses no<br />

such matter, cannot increase or decrease ;<br />

all bodies,<br />

finally, which alter, either increase or decrease, and where<br />

there is no such process neither is there any alteration. 4<br />

1<br />

Ibid. c. 3, 269, b, 18-270, a,<br />

] 2 ; nor can the position $(a /j.iv<br />

yap ev84x*Tat ttjv &Wov ko! irepov<br />

I sc. Kti'rjtriif KivuixOai] (c. 2, 269, a,<br />

7) be accepted except provisionally<br />

as of universal validity.<br />

As is shown in the sequel, it is<br />

inapplicable to the SEther. The<br />

position upon which the latter<br />

conclusion rests, (viz. that movement<br />

in a circle has no opposite).<br />

Aristotle, indeed, endeavours<br />

(c. 4) further to establish <strong>by</strong><br />

special proofs. But he cannot<br />

prove that the motion may not<br />

be crooked or oblique ; for if we<br />

have two opposite motions on<br />

the same or on parallel lines<br />

which deviate in opposite directions,<br />

it does not make the<br />

slightest difference whether the<br />

lines are straight or circular.<br />

Moreover, the courses of the<br />

fixed stars and of the planets<br />

are actually in opposite directions<br />

; why may these bodies<br />

not, then, consist of different<br />

jetherial substance ? We are not<br />

warranted, however, with Meyer<br />

(Aristot. Thierhtnde, 393) in<br />

casting a doubt upon Aristotle's<br />

clearly expressed meaning, merely<br />

on the ground of the actual<br />

difficulties that beset the theory.<br />

2<br />

He says, De Orlo, i. 3, 270,<br />

a, 13, b, 1 : ayevTjTOf teal citpQaprov<br />

Kal avavl-es real ai/aKKoiayroi/, aiSioy<br />

teal out' avfy}aiv %x ov °^Te fpOlfTtv,<br />

d\A' ayhparov «al dvaXkoianov teal<br />

awaBis. Cf. Metaph. viii. 4, 1044,<br />

b, 7, xii. 1, 2, 1069, a, 30, b, 25.<br />

3<br />

On this point, cf. also p.<br />

341 sq.<br />

4<br />

Be Ccelo, i. 3, 270, a, 13-35.<br />

The immutability of the body<br />

which has no opposite might have<br />

been proved more simply and<br />

conclusively from the proposition<br />

(p. 341, and p. 353 sq. above)<br />

that all change means transition<br />

from one state into its opposite,<br />

and that a thing can only be<br />

operated upon <strong>by</strong> its opposite.<br />

Aristotle, however, does not here<br />

adopt this method, as his investigation<br />

into the conception of<br />

change and affection was not<br />

published until later—in his

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!