08.04.2019 Views

ARISTOTLE AND THE EARLIER PERIPATETICS vol.I by Eduard Zeller, B.F.C.Costelloe 1897

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine) ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!! Strabo – “Geography” “There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.” (Strab. 7.fragments.9) ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

MACEDONIA is GREECE and will always be GREECE- (if they are desperate to steal a name, Monkeydonkeys suits them just fine)

ΚΑΤΩ ΤΟ ΠΡΟΔΟΤΙΚΟ "ΣΥΝΤΑΓΜΑΤΙΚΟ ΤΟΞΟ"!!!

Strabo – “Geography”
“There remain of Europe, first, Macedonia and the parts of Thrace that are contiguous to it and extend as far as Byzantium; secondly, Greece; and thirdly, the islands that are close by. Macedonia, of course, is a part of Greece, yet now, since I am following the nature and shape of the places geographically, I have decided to classify it apart from the rest of Greece and to join it with that part of Thrace which borders on it and extends as far as the mouth of the Euxine and the Propontis. Then, a little further on, Strabo mentions Cypsela and the Hebrus River, and also describes a sort of parallelogram in which the whole of Macedonia lies.”
(Strab. 7.fragments.9)

ΚΚΕ, ΚΝΕ, ΟΝΝΕΔ, ΑΓΟΡΑ,ΕΚΚΛΗΣΙΑ,ΝΕΑ,ΦΩΝΗ,ΦΕΚ,ΝΟΜΟΣ,LIFO,MACEDONIA, ALEXANDER, GREECE,IKEA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

;<br />

:<br />

:<br />

merits '<br />

LOGIC 235<br />

Aristotle pays as little attention as to the Hypothetical<br />

and Disjunctive Syllogisms.<br />

himself admits {Anal. Pr. i. 3,<br />

25, a, 37; De Interpr. c. 13, 22,<br />

b, 29 ; of. Metapli. ix. 2 init. c. 5,<br />

1048, a, 4, c. 8, 1050, b, 30 sqq.)<br />

with regard to the forces of<br />

nature (Swi/jeis) which only act<br />

in one direction, that the necessary<br />

also may be called a possible<br />

(Swot!)!'), and that, allowing this,<br />

universal negative possible-propositions<br />

can be converted simply,<br />

and that we may conclude from<br />

necessity to possibility—but he<br />

also adds that this is not true as<br />

to Ms own concept of the possible.—Two<br />

further points of<br />

dispute, on which Alexander<br />

wrote a work (Alex. Anal. 40, b,<br />

83, a), arose between Aristotle<br />

and his pupils upon the question<br />

about the mood of conclusions in<br />

syllogisms, the premisses of<br />

which are in different moods.<br />

Aristotle says that where one<br />

premiss is a possible- and the<br />

other an actual-proposition, a<br />

perfect syllogism can only be had<br />

in the case where the major proposition<br />

is a possible-proposition<br />

if, however, it is the minor, we<br />

get, first of all, an imperfect<br />

syllogism, i.e. one in which the<br />

conclusion is only obtained <strong>by</strong><br />

a deduetio ad aiswdum and not<br />

immediately from the given premisses,<br />

and secondly, in the case<br />

of a negative syllogism (more<br />

correctly : in all cases), the possibility<br />

in the conclusion must be<br />

taken in the improper sense (i.e.<br />

not as confined to that which<br />

both can and cannot be) (Anal.<br />

Pr. i. 15). Theophrastus and<br />

Eudemus, on the contrary, were<br />

of opinion that even in this case<br />

Only in what he<br />

there was a perfect possiblesyllogism<br />

(Alex. loo. cit. 56, b).<br />

Both sides are right, according to<br />

their concepts of the possible.<br />

If we understand <strong>by</strong> ' possible '<br />

everything that can be, including<br />

also the necessary, the syllogisms<br />

are quite correct and simple<br />

'<br />

Every B is A, every C can be B,<br />

therefore every G can be A';<br />

'<br />

No B is A, every C can be B,<br />

therefore it is possible that no C<br />

is A,' If, on the other hand, we<br />

take possible ' ' to mean only that<br />

of which the contrary is likewise<br />

possible, we cannot make such<br />

syllogisms, because in this supposition<br />

the minor, ' every C can<br />

be B,' includes the negative proposition,<br />

every C can be not-B.'<br />

'<br />

And also, as Theophrastus and<br />

Budemns merely adhered to the<br />

principle that the modality of<br />

the conclusion is conformed to<br />

the weaker premiss (Alex, ibid.'),<br />

they asserted, on the same principle,<br />

that when one premiss<br />

is assertorial and the other<br />

apodeictic, \the conclusion is<br />

4ymliiilio (Alex. ibid. 40, a, 42, J<br />

b, and from him Philop. Schol.<br />

in Arist. 158, b, 18, 159, a, 6),<br />

whilst, according to Aristotle<br />

(Anal. Pr. i. 9 sqq.) it is apodeictic<br />

when the major is so. In<br />

this case also, according to the<br />

meaning which we attach to the<br />

modality of propositions, both<br />

assertions may be made. If the<br />

propositions 'B must be A,' B<br />

'<br />

cannot be A,' are supposed to<br />

express that between B and A<br />

there is (or is not) not a contingent,<br />

but a necessary connection,<br />

it follows that between every-<br />

L>36 <strong>ARISTOTLE</strong><br />

says of contradictory opposition ' do we find the kernel of<br />

the late doctrine of disjunctive judgments. On the<br />

other hand, he is copious in his treatment of the Conversion<br />

of Propositions, 2 laying down the well-known<br />

rules, 3 but he treats it solely in connection with his<br />

theory of the Syllogism.<br />

This theory of the Syllogism was expounded <strong>by</strong><br />

Aristotle at full length, and it may truly be called his<br />

most original discovery. 4 As he was the first to introduce<br />

the name of the Syllogism into the scientific<br />

vocabulary, 5 so he was also the first to remark that all<br />

connections and all advances in our thought depend<br />

upon the syllogistic combination of judgments. A<br />

'<br />

Syllogism ' is a chain of thoughts, in which, from certain<br />

matters assumed, and <strong>by</strong> virtue of these alone, there issues<br />

of necessity some further matter different from them. 6<br />

thing contained in B and A, <strong>by</strong><br />

the same necessity, there is,, or<br />

is not, a connection (if all living<br />

beings, <strong>by</strong> reason of a necessity<br />

of nature, are mortal, the same<br />

is also true of every kind of<br />

living beings, e.g. of men), as<br />

Aristotle, loo. tit. 30, a, 21 sqq.<br />

shows quite clearly. If, on the<br />

other hand, these propositions<br />

are meant to state that we are<br />

obliged to think A connected or<br />

not connected with B, the proposition,<br />

' C must (or cannot) be<br />

'<br />

A can only be deduced from<br />

the proposition B must ' (or<br />

cannot) be A,' when we are<br />

obliged to consider C implied in<br />

B. If, however, we only know<br />

as a fact (assertorially) that<br />

C is B, then we only know as a<br />

fact, likewise, that C is or is not<br />

that which we are obliged to<br />

think connected or not connected<br />

with B.<br />

1<br />

Vid. supr. p. 230.<br />

' Anal. Pr. i. 2, 3, cf. c. 13,<br />

32, a, 29 sqq. c. 17, 36, b, 15<br />

sqq. ii. 1, 53, a, 3 sqq.<br />

3<br />

Simple conversion of universal<br />

negative and particular<br />

affirmative judgments, particular<br />

conversion (later so-called conrersio<br />

per aecidens) of universal<br />

affirmative, and no conversion at<br />

all of particular negative judgments<br />

— for the nonversio per<br />

oontrapontionem was not as yet<br />

known to him.<br />

4<br />

As he himself says, Soph. M.<br />

c. 34, 183, b, 34, 184, b, 1.<br />

6 Cf. Pbantl, Gescli. d.<br />

Log. i. 264.<br />

6<br />

Anal. Pr. i. 24. b, 18<br />

o-vWoyi&fibs 8e eori \6yos iv §<br />

Ts84vTQ)V TLVWV fET€p6v Tl TUV KCl-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!