19.01.2018 Views

Judicial ReEngineering

Judicial ReEngineering

Judicial ReEngineering

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The e-Advocate<br />

Quarterly Magazine<br />

Exodus 18 | Deuteronomy 1 | Ezra 7<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>ReEngineering</strong><br />

Universal Legal Systems Analysis<br />

“Helping Individuals, Organizations & Communities<br />

Achieve Their Full Potential”<br />

Vol. IX, Issue XXXVII – Q-2 April | May | June 2023


The Advocacy Foundation, Inc.<br />

Helping Individuals, Organizations & Communities<br />

Achieve Their Full Potential<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>ReEngineering</strong><br />

Universal Legal Systems Analysis<br />

“Helping Individuals, Organizations & Communities<br />

Achieve Their Full Potential<br />

1735 Market Street, Suite 3750 | 100 Edgewood Avenue, Suite 1690<br />

Philadelphia, PA 19102 Atlanta, GA 30303<br />

John C Johnson III, Esq.<br />

Founder & CEO<br />

(878) 222-0450<br />

Voice | Fax | SMS<br />

www.TheAdvocacyFoundation.org<br />

Page 2 of 115


Page 3 of 115


Jethro Visits Moses<br />

Biblical Authority<br />

Exodus 18<br />

______<br />

1 Now Jethro, the priest of Midian and father-in-law of Moses, heard of everything God had done for Moses and for<br />

his people Israel, and how the LORD had brought Israel out of Egypt. 2 After Moses had sent away his wife Zipporah,<br />

his father-in-law Jethro received her 3 and her two sons. One son was named Gershom, for Moses said, "I have<br />

become an alien in a foreign land"; 4 and the other was named Eliezer, for he said, "My father's God was my helper;<br />

he saved me from the sword of Pharaoh." 5 Jethro, Moses' father-in-law, together with Moses' sons and wife, came to<br />

him in the desert, where he was camped near the mountain of God. 6 Jethro had sent word to him, "I, your father-inlaw<br />

Jethro, am coming to you with your wife and her two sons." 7 So Moses went out to meet his father-in-law and<br />

bowed down and kissed him. They<br />

greeted each other and then went into the<br />

tent. 8 Moses told his father-in-law<br />

about everything the LORD had done<br />

to Pharaoh and the Egyptians for<br />

Israel's sake and about all the<br />

hardships they had met along the<br />

way and how the LORD had saved<br />

them. 9 Jethro was delighted to<br />

hear about all the good things<br />

the LORD had done for Israel in<br />

rescuing them from the hand of<br />

the Egyptians. 10 He said,<br />

"Praise be to the LORD, who<br />

rescued you from the hand of the Egyptians and of<br />

Pharaoh, and who rescued<br />

the people from the hand of<br />

the Egyptians. 11 Now I know<br />

that the LORD is greater<br />

than all other gods, for he did<br />

this to those who had treated<br />

Israel arrogantly." 12 Then<br />

Jethro, Moses' father-in-law,<br />

brought a burnt offering and<br />

other sacrifices to God, and<br />

Aaron came with all the<br />

elders of Israel to eat bread<br />

with Moses' father-in-law in<br />

the presence of God. 13 The<br />

next day Moses took his seat<br />

to serve as judge for the<br />

people, and they stood around him from morning till<br />

evening. 14 When his father-<br />

in-law saw all that Moses<br />

was doing for the people, he<br />

said, "What is this you are<br />

doing for the people? Why do<br />

you alone sit as judge, while<br />

all these people stand around you from morning till<br />

evening?" 15 Moses answered<br />

him, "Because the people come<br />

to me to seek God's will. 16<br />

Whenever they have a dispute, it<br />

is brought to me, and I decide<br />

between the parties and inform<br />

them of God's decrees and laws." 17 Moses' father-in-law replied, "What you are doing is not good. 18 You and these<br />

people who come to you will only wear yourselves out. The work is too heavy for you; you cannot handle it alone. 19<br />

Listen now to me and I will give you some advice, and may God be with you. You must be the people's representative<br />

before God and bring their disputes to him. 20 Teach them the decrees and laws, and show them the way to live and<br />

the duties they are to perform. 21 But select capable men from all the people--men who fear God, trustworthy men<br />

who hate dishonest gain--and appoint them as officials over thousands, hundreds, fifties and tens. 22 Have them<br />

serve as judges for the people at all times, but have them bring every difficult case to you; the simple cases they can<br />

decide themselves. That will make your load lighter, because they will share it with you. 23 If you do this and God so<br />

commands, you will be able to stand the strain, and all these people will go home satisfied." 24 Moses listened to his<br />

father-in-law and did everything he said. 25 He chose capable men from all Israel and made them leaders of the<br />

people, officials over thousands, hundreds, fifties and tens. 26 They served as judges for the people at all times. The<br />

difficult cases they brought to Moses, but the simple ones they decided themselves. 27 Then Moses sent his fatherin-law<br />

on his way, and Jethro returned to his own country.<br />

Page 4 of 115


The Command to Leave Horeb<br />

Deuteronomy 1<br />

1 These are the words Moses spoke to all Israel in the desert east of the Jordan--that is, in the Arabah--opposite<br />

Suph, between Paran and Tophel, Laban, Hazeroth and Dizahab. 2 (It takes eleven days to go from Horeb to Kadesh<br />

Barnea by the Mount Seir road.) 3 In the fortieth year, on the first day of the eleventh month, Moses proclaimed to the<br />

Israelites all that the LORD had commanded him concerning them. 4 This was after he had defeated Sihon king of<br />

the Amorites, who reigned in Heshbon, and at Edrei had defeated Og king of Bashan, who reigned in Ashtaroth. 5<br />

East of the Jordan in the territory of Moab, Moses began to expound this law, saying: 6 The LORD our God said to us<br />

at Horeb, "You have stayed long enough at this mountain. 7 Break camp and advance into the hill country of the<br />

Amorites; go to all the neighboring peoples in the Arabah, in the mountains, in the western foothills, in the Negev and<br />

along the coast, to the land of the Canaanites and to Lebanon, as far as the great river, the Euphrates. 8 See, I have<br />

given you this land. Go in and take possession of the land that the LORD swore he would give to your fathers--to<br />

Abraham, Isaac and Jacob--and to their descendants after them."<br />

The Appointment of Leaders<br />

9 At that time I said to you, "You are too heavy a burden for me to carry alone. 10 The LORD your God has increased<br />

your numbers so that today you are as many as the stars in the sky. 11 May the LORD, the God of your fathers,<br />

increase you a thousand times and bless you as he has promised! 12 But how can I bear your problems and your<br />

burdens and your disputes all by myself ? 13 Choose some wise, understanding and respected men from each of<br />

your tribes, and I will set them over you." 14 You answered me, "What you propose to do is good." 15 So I took the<br />

leading men of your tribes, wise and respected men, and appointed them to have authority over you--as commanders<br />

of thousands, of hundreds, of fifties and of tens and as tribal officials. 16 And I charged your judges at that time: Hear<br />

the disputes between your brothers and judge fairly, whether the case is between brother Israelites or between one of<br />

them and an alien. 17 Do not show partiality in judging; hear both small and great alike. Do not be afraid of any man,<br />

for judgment belongs to God. Bring me any case too hard for you, and I will hear it. 18 And at that time I told you<br />

everything you were to do.<br />

Spies Sent Out<br />

19 Then, as the LORD our God commanded us, we set out from Horeb and went toward the hill country of the<br />

Amorites through all that vast and dreadful desert that you have seen, and so we reached Kadesh Barnea. 20 Then I<br />

said to you, "You have reached the hill country of the Amorites, which the LORD our God is giving us. 21 See, the<br />

LORD your God has given you the land. Go up and take possession of it as the LORD, the God of your fathers, told<br />

you. Do not be afraid; do not be discouraged." 22 Then all of you came to me and said, "Let us send men ahead to<br />

spy out the land for us and bring back a report about the route we are to take and the towns we will come to." 23 The<br />

idea seemed good to me; so I selected twelve of you, one man from each tribe. 24 They left and went up into the hill<br />

country, and came to the Valley of Eshcol and explored it. 25 Taking with them some of the fruit of the land, they<br />

brought it down to us and reported, "It is a good land that the LORD our God is giving us."<br />

Rebellion Against the LORD<br />

26 But you were unwilling to go up; you rebelled against the command of the LORD your God. 27 You grumbled in<br />

your tents and said, "The LORD hates us; so he brought us out of Egypt to deliver us into the hands of the Amorites<br />

to destroy us. 28 Where can we go? Our brothers have made us lose heart. They say, 'The people are stronger and<br />

taller than we are; the cities are large, with walls up to the sky. We even saw the Anakites there.' " 29 Then I said to<br />

you, "Do not be terrified; do not be afraid of them. 30 The LORD your God, who is going before you, will fight for you,<br />

as he did for you in Egypt, before your very eyes, 31 and in the desert. There you saw how the LORD your God<br />

carried you, as a father carries his son, all the way you went until you reached this place." 32 In spite of this, you did<br />

not trust in the LORD your God, 33 who went ahead of you on your journey, in fire by night and in a cloud by day, to<br />

search out places for you to camp and to show you the way you should go. 34 When the LORD heard what you said,<br />

he was angry and solemnly swore: 35 "Not a man of this evil generation shall see the good land I swore to give your<br />

Page 5 of 115


forefathers, 36 except Caleb son of Jephunneh. He will see it, and I will give him and his descendants the land he set<br />

his feet on, because he followed the LORD wholeheartedly." 37 Because of you the LORD became angry with me<br />

also and said, "You shall not enter it, either. 38 But your assistant, Joshua son of Nun, will enter it. Encourage him,<br />

because he will lead Israel to inherit it. 39 And the little ones that you said would be taken captive, your children who<br />

do not yet know good from bad--they will enter the land. I will give it to them and they will take possession of it. 40 But<br />

as for you, turn around and set out toward the desert along the route to the Red Sea." 41 Then you replied, "We have<br />

sinned against the LORD. We will go up and fight, as the LORD our God commanded us." So every one of you put on<br />

his weapons, thinking it easy to go up into the hill country. 42 But the LORD said to me, "Tell them, 'Do not go up and<br />

fight, because I will not be with you. You will be defeated by your enemies.' " 43 So I told you, but you would not<br />

listen. You rebelled against the LORD's command and in your arrogance you marched up into the hill country. 44 The<br />

Amorites who lived in those hills came out against you; they chased you like a swarm of bees and beat you down<br />

from Seir all the way to Hormah. 45 You came back and wept before the LORD, but he paid no attention to your<br />

weeping and turned a deaf ear to you. 46 And so you stayed in Kadesh many days--all the time you spent there.<br />

Ezra Comes to Jerusalem<br />

Ezra 7<br />

1 After these things, during the reign of Artaxerxes king of Persia, Ezra son of Seraiah, the son of Azariah, the son of<br />

Hilkiah, 2 the son of Shallum, the son of Zadok, the son of Ahitub, 3 the son of Amariah, the son of Azariah, the son<br />

of Meraioth, 4 the son of Zerahiah, the son of Uzzi, the son of Bukki, 5 the son of Abishua, the son of Phinehas, the<br />

son of Eleazar, the son of Aaron the chief priest-- 6 this Ezra came up from Babylon. He was a teacher well versed in<br />

the Law of Moses, which the LORD, the God of Israel, had given. The king had granted him everything he asked, for<br />

the hand of the LORD his God was on him. 7 Some of the Israelites, including priests, Levites, singers, gatekeepers<br />

and temple servants, also came up to Jerusalem in the seventh year of King Artaxerxes. 8 Ezra arrived in Jerusalem<br />

in the fifth month of the seventh year of the king. 9 He had begun his journey from Babylon on the first day of the first<br />

month, and he arrived in Jerusalem on the first day of the fifth month, for the gracious hand of his God was on him.<br />

10 For Ezra had devoted himself to the study and observance of the Law of the LORD, and to teaching its decrees<br />

and laws in Israel.<br />

King Artaxerxes' Letter to Ezra<br />

11 This is a copy of the letter King Artaxerxes had given to Ezra the priest and teacher, a man learned in matters<br />

concerning the commands and decrees of the LORD for Israel: 12 Artaxerxes, king of kings, To Ezra the priest, a<br />

teacher of the Law of the God of heaven: Greetings. 13 Now I decree that any of the Israelites in my kingdom,<br />

including priests and Levites, who wish to go to Jerusalem with you, may go. 14 You are sent by the king and his<br />

seven advisers to inquire about Judah and Jerusalem with regard to the Law of your God, which is in your hand. 15<br />

Moreover, you are to take with you the silver and gold that the king and his advisers have freely given to the God of<br />

Israel, whose dwelling is in Jerusalem, 16 together with all the silver and gold you may obtain from the province of<br />

Babylon, as well as the freewill offerings of the people and priests for the temple of their God in Jerusalem. 17 With<br />

this money be sure to buy bulls, rams and male lambs, together with their grain offerings and drink offerings, and<br />

sacrifice them on the altar of the temple of your God in Jerusalem. 18 You and your brother Jews may then do<br />

whatever seems best with the rest of the silver and gold, in accordance with the will of your God. 19 Deliver to the<br />

God of Jerusalem all the articles entrusted to you for worship in the temple of your God. 20 And anything else needed<br />

for the temple of your God that you may have occasion to supply, you may provide from the royal treasury. 21 Now I,<br />

King Artaxerxes, order all the treasurers of Trans-Euphrates to provide with diligence whatever Ezra the priest, a<br />

teacher of the Law of the God of heaven, may ask of you-- 22 up to a hundred talents of silver, a hundred cors of<br />

wheat, a hundred baths of wine, a hundred baths of olive oil, and salt without limit. 23 Whatever the God of heaven<br />

has prescribed, let it be done with diligence for the temple of the God of heaven. Why should there be wrath against<br />

the realm of the king and of his sons? 24 You are also to know that you have no authority to impose taxes, tribute or<br />

duty on any of the priests, Levites, singers, gatekeepers, temple servants or other workers at this house of God. 25<br />

And you, Ezra, in accordance with the wisdom of your God, which you possess, appoint magistrates and judges to<br />

administer justice to all the people of Trans-Euphrates--all who know the laws of your God. And you are to teach any<br />

who do not know them. 26 Whoever does not obey the law of your God and the law of the king must surely be<br />

punished by death, banishment, confiscation of property, or imprisonment. 27 Praise be to the LORD, the God of our<br />

fathers, who has put it into the king's heart to bring honor to the house of the LORD in Jerusalem in this way 28 and<br />

who has extended his good favor to me before the king and his advisers and all the king's powerful officials. Because<br />

the hand of the LORD my God was on me, I took courage and gathered leading men from Israel to go up with me.<br />

Page 6 of 115


Page 7 of 115


Table of Contents<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>ReEngineering</strong> – Universal Legal Systems Analysis<br />

Biblical Authority<br />

I. Introduction<br />

II.<br />

III.<br />

IV.<br />

The Judiciary<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Independence<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review<br />

V. Rule of Law<br />

VI. Rule of Higher Law<br />

VII. Political Corruption of the Judiciary<br />

VIII. Conflicts of Interest<br />

IX.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

Attachments<br />

A. The Role of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

B. Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

C. Proper <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

Copyright © 2015 The Advocacy Foundation, Inc. All Rights Reserved.<br />

Page 8 of 115


Page 9 of 115


Introduction<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Reform is the complete or partial political reform of a country's judiciary. <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

reform is often done as a part of wider reform of the country's political system or a legal reform.<br />

Areas of the judicial reform often include; codification of law instead of common law, moving<br />

from an inquisitorial system to an adversarial system, establishing stronger judicial independence<br />

with judicial councils or changes to appointment procedure, establishing mandatory retirement<br />

age for judges or enhancing independence of prosecution.<br />

The Judiciary (also known as the <strong>Judicial</strong> System or Court<br />

System) is the system of courts that interprets and applies the<br />

law in the name of the state. The judiciary also provides a<br />

mechanism for the resolution of disputes. Under the doctrine of<br />

the separation of powers, the judiciary generally does not make<br />

law (that is, in a plenary fashion, which is the responsibility of<br />

the legislature) or enforce law (which is the responsibility of the<br />

executive), but rather interprets law and applies it to the facts of<br />

each case. This branch of the state is often tasked with ensuring<br />

equal justice under law. It usually consists of a court of final<br />

appeal (called the "Supreme court" or "Constitutional court"),<br />

together with lower courts.<br />

In many jurisdictions the judicial branch has the power to<br />

change laws through the process of judicial review. Courts with<br />

judicial review power may annul the laws and rules of the state<br />

when it finds them incompatible with a higher norm, such as<br />

primary legislation, the provisions of the constitution or international law. Judges constitute a<br />

critical force for interpretation and implementation of a constitution, thus de facto in common<br />

law countries creating the body of constitutional law.<br />

In the US during recent decades the judiciary became active in economic issues related with<br />

economic rights established by constitution because "economics may provide insight into<br />

questions that bear on the proper legal interpretation". Since many countries with transitional<br />

political and economic systems continue treating their constitutions as abstract legal documents<br />

disengaged from the economic policy of the state, practice of judicial review of economic acts of<br />

executive and legislative branches have begun to grow.<br />

In the 1980s, the Supreme Court of India for almost a decade had been encouraging public<br />

interest litigation on behalf of the poor and oppressed by using a very broad interpretation of<br />

several articles of the Indian Constitution.<br />

Budget of the judiciary in many transitional and developing countries is almost completely<br />

controlled by the executive. The latter undermines the separation of powers, as it creates a<br />

Page 10 of 115


critical financial dependence of the judiciary. The proper national wealth distribution including<br />

the government spending on the judiciary is subject of the constitutional economics. It is<br />

important to distinguish between the two methods of corruption of the judiciary: the state<br />

(through budget planning and various privileges), and the private.<br />

The term "judiciary" is also used to refer collectively to the personnel, such as judges,<br />

magistrates and other adjudicators, who form the core of a judiciary (sometimes referred to as a<br />

"bench"), as well as the staffs who keep the system running smoothly.<br />

After The Revolution<br />

After the French Revolution, lawmakers stopped interpretation of law by judges, and the<br />

legislature was the only body permitted to interpret the law; this prohibition was later overturned<br />

by the Code Napoléon.<br />

In civil law jurisdictions at present, judges interpret the law to about the same extent as in<br />

common law jurisdictions – however it is different from the common law tradition which directly<br />

recognizes the limited power to make law. For instance, in France, the jurisprudence constante<br />

of the Court of Cassation or the Council of State is equivalent in practice with case law.<br />

However, the Louisiana Supreme Court notes the principal difference between the two legal<br />

doctrines: a single court decision can provide sufficient foundation for the common law doctrine<br />

of stare decisis, however, "a series of adjudicated cases, all in accord, form the basis for<br />

jurisprudence constante." Moreover, the Louisiana Court of Appeals has explicitly noted that<br />

jurisprudence constante is merely a secondary source of law, which cannot be authoritative and<br />

does not rise to the level of stare decisis.<br />

Page 11 of 115


Page 12 of 115


The Judiciary<br />

In common law jurisdictions, courts interpret law,<br />

including constitutions, statutes, and regulations. They<br />

also make law (but in a limited sense, limited to the facts<br />

of particular cases) based upon prior case law in areas<br />

where the legislature has not made law. For instance, the<br />

tort of negligence is not derived from statute law in most<br />

common law jurisdictions. The term common law refers<br />

to this kind of law.<br />

In civil law jurisdictions, courts interpret the law, but are<br />

prohibited from creating law, and thus do not issue<br />

rulings more general than the actual case to be judged.<br />

Jurisprudence plays a similar role to case law.<br />

In the United States court system, the Supreme Court is<br />

the final authority on the interpretation of the federal<br />

Constitution and all statutes and regulations created<br />

pursuant to it, as well as the constitutionality of the<br />

various state laws; in the US federal court system, federal<br />

cases are tried in trial courts, known as the US district courts, followed by appellate courts and<br />

then the Supreme Court. State courts, which try 98% of litigation, may have different names and<br />

organization; trial courts may be called "courts of common plea", appellate courts "superior<br />

courts" or "commonwealth courts". The judicial system, whether state or federal, begins with a<br />

court of first instance, is appealed to an appellate court, and then ends at the court of last resort.<br />

In France, the final authority on the interpretation of the law is the Council of State for<br />

administrative cases, and the Court of Cassation for civil and criminal cases.<br />

In the People's Republic of China, the final authority on the interpretation of the law is the<br />

National People's Congress.<br />

Other countries such as Argentina have mixed systems that include lower courts, appeals courts,<br />

a cassation court (for criminal law) and a Supreme Court. In this system the Supreme Court is<br />

always the final authority, but criminal cases have four stages, one more than civil law does. On<br />

the court sits a total of nine justices. This number has been changed several times.<br />

Other Countries<br />

Japan’s process for selecting Judges is longer and more stringent than the process in the United<br />

States and in Mexico. Assistant judges are appointed from those who have completed their<br />

training at the "Legal Training and Research Institute" located in Wako City. Once appointeid,<br />

assistant judges still may not qualify to sit alone until they have served for five years, and have<br />

been appointed by the Supreme Court. Judges require ten years of experience in practical affairs,<br />

Page 13 of 115


public prosecutor, or practicing attorney. In the Japanese <strong>Judicial</strong> Branch there is the Supreme<br />

Court located in Japan, eight high courts, fifty district courts, fifty family courts, and 438<br />

summary courts. In difference, Mexican Supreme Court Justices are appointed by the president,<br />

and then are approved by the Senate to serve for a life term. Other justices are appointed by the<br />

Supreme Court and serve for six years. Federal courts consist of the Supreme Court with 21<br />

magistrates, 32 circuit tribunals and 98 district courts. The Supreme Court of Mexico is located<br />

in "Mexico City. Supreme Court Judges must be of ages 35 to 65 and hold a law degree during<br />

the five years preceding their nomination. In the United States Supreme Court, justices are<br />

appointed by the president and approved by the Senate. As in Mexico, justices serve for a life<br />

term or until retirement. The Supreme Court of the United States is located in "Washington<br />

D.C". The Federal court system consists of 94 federal judicial districts. The 94 districts are then<br />

divided into twelve regional circuits. The United States consist of five different types of courts<br />

that are considered subordinate to the Supreme Court, U.S bankruptcy courts, U.S Courts of<br />

Appeal for the federal circuit, U.S Court of International Trade, U.S Courts of Appeal, and U.S<br />

District Courts.<br />

The Supreme Court<br />

[The] supreme court is the highest court within the hierarchy of many legal jurisdictions. Other<br />

descriptions for such courts include court of last resort, instance court, judgment court, apex<br />

court, and highest court of appeal. Broadly speaking, the decisions of a supreme court are not<br />

subject to further review by any other court. Supreme courts typically function primarily as<br />

appellate courts, hearing appeals from decisions of lower trial courts, or from intermediate-level<br />

appellate courts.<br />

However, not all highest courts are named as such. Civil law states do not tend to have singular<br />

highest courts. Additionally, the highest court in some jurisdictions is not named the "Supreme<br />

Court", for example, the High Court of Australia; this is because decisions by the High Court<br />

could formerly be appealed to the Privy Council. In a few places, the court named the "Supreme<br />

Court" is not in fact the highest court; examples include the New York Supreme Court, which is<br />

superseded by the New York Court of Appeals, and the former Supreme Court of Judicature of<br />

England and Wales.<br />

Some countries have multiple "supreme courts" whose respective jurisdictions have different<br />

geographical extents, or which are restricted to particular areas of law. In particular, countries<br />

with a federal system of government typically have both a federal supreme court (such as the<br />

Supreme Court of the United States), and supreme courts for each member state (such as the<br />

Supreme Court of Nevada), with the former having jurisdiction over the latter only to the extent<br />

that the federal constitution extends federal law over state law. Jurisdictions with a civil law<br />

system often have a hierarchy of administrative courts separate from the ordinary courts, headed<br />

by a supreme administrative court as it the case in the Netherlands. A number of jurisdictions<br />

also follow the "Austrian" model of a separate constitutional court (first developed in the<br />

Czechoslovak Constitution of 1920).<br />

Within the British Empire, the highest court within a colony was often called the "Supreme<br />

Court", even though appeals could be made from that court to the United Kingdom's Privy<br />

Page 14 of 115


Council (based in London). A number of Commonwealth jurisdictions retain this system, but<br />

many others have reconstituted their own highest court as a court of last resort, with the right of<br />

appeal to the Privy Council being abolished.<br />

In jurisdictions using a common law system, the doctrine of stare decisis applies, whereby the<br />

principles applied by the supreme court in its decisions are binding upon all lower courts; this is<br />

intended to apply a uniform interpretation and implementation of the law. In civil law<br />

jurisdictions the doctrine of stare decisis is not generally considered to apply, so the decisions of<br />

the supreme court are not necessarily binding beyond the immediate case before it; however, in<br />

practice the decisions of the supreme court usually provide a very strong precedent, or<br />

jurisprudence constante, for both itself and all lower courts.<br />

In the United States<br />

The Supreme Court of the United States, established in 1789, is the highest Federal<br />

court in the United States, with powers of judicial review first asserted in Calder v.<br />

Bull (1798) in Justice Iredell's dissenting opinion. The power was<br />

later given binding authority by Justice Marshall in Marbury v.<br />

Madison (1803). There are currently nine seats on the US<br />

Supreme Court.<br />

Each U.S. state has a state supreme<br />

court, which is the highest authority<br />

interpreting that state's law and administering that state's judiciary.<br />

Two states, Oklahoma and<br />

Texas, each have two separate<br />

highest courts that respectively<br />

specialize in criminal cases and<br />

civil cases. Although Delaware has a<br />

specialized court, the Court of<br />

Chancery, to hear<br />

cases in equity, it is<br />

not a supreme court because the<br />

Delaware Supreme Court<br />

has appellate jurisdiction over<br />

it.<br />

The titles of<br />

state supreme<br />

court vary, which can<br />

cause confusion between<br />

jurisdictions because one state may use a name for its highest court that another uses<br />

for a lower court. In New York, Maryland, and the District of Columbia the highest<br />

court is called the<br />

Court of Appeals,<br />

a name used by many states for<br />

their intermediate appellate courts. Further, trial courts of general jurisdiction in New York are<br />

called the Supreme Court, and the intermediate appellate court is called the Supreme Court,<br />

Appellate Division. In West Virginia, the highest court of the state is the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeals. In Maine and Massachusetts the highest court is styled the "Supreme <strong>Judicial</strong> Court";<br />

the last is the oldest appellate court of continuous operation in the Western Hemisphere.<br />

Page 15 of 115


Common Law Countries<br />

Australia<br />

In Australia, the High Court of Australia became the court of last resort with the passing of the<br />

Australia Act in 1986. This act abolished the last rights of appeal to the Privy Council. Each state<br />

and territory has its own Supreme Court, which is the highest court in that state/territory. This<br />

leads to some confusion among those from other jurisdictions as the term "supreme court" seems<br />

to refer to the court of last resort. The reason that the High Court of Australia is not named the<br />

"supreme court" is purely historical. Before the federation of the Australian colonies as states of<br />

Australia (in 1901), each colony had its own independent judicial system with a supreme court as<br />

the highest court physically within the colony (with a right of appeal to the Privy Council). On<br />

federation, the constitution provided for the establishment of a federal "supreme court", to be<br />

named the "High Court" which could hear appeals from the state Supreme Courts. With the<br />

exception of the Australian Capital Territory, each state's Supreme Court is divided into two<br />

divisions: the Trial Division and the Court of Appeal. Appeals from the ACT Supreme Court are<br />

heard in the High Court of Australia. The current Chief Justice of the High Court is Robert<br />

French.<br />

Bangladesh<br />

The Supreme Court of Bangladesh is created by the provisions of the Constitution of<br />

Bangladesh, 1972. There are two Divisions of the Supreme Court, i.e. (a) Appellate Division and<br />

(b) High Court Division. Appellate Division is the highest Court of Appeal and usually does not<br />

exercise the powers of a court of first instance. Whereas, the High Court Division is a Court of<br />

first instance in company and admiralty matters. The Supreme Court of Bangladesh is the<br />

protector and guardian of Bangladesh Constitution.<br />

The judgements of Appellate Division of Bangladesh Supreme Court are accessible in the<br />

Chancery Law Chronicles.<br />

Canada<br />

In Canada, the Supreme Court of Canada was established in 1875 but only became the highest<br />

court in the country in 1949 when the right of appeal to the <strong>Judicial</strong> Committee of the Privy<br />

Council was abolished. This court hears appeals of decisions made by courts of appeal from the<br />

provinces and territories and appeals of decisions made by the Federal Court of Appeal. The<br />

court's decisions are final and binding on the federal courts and the courts from all provinces and<br />

territories. The title "Supreme" can be confusing because, for example, The Supreme Court of<br />

British Columbia does not have the final say and controversial cases heard there often get<br />

appealed in higher courts - it is in fact one of the lower courts in such a process.<br />

Page 16 of 115


Hong Kong<br />

In Hong Kong, the Supreme Court of Hong Kong (now known as the High Court of Hong Kong)<br />

was the final court of appeal during its colonial times which ended with transfer of sovereignty in<br />

1997. The final adjudication power, as in any other British Colonies, rested with the <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Committee of the Privy Council (JCPC) in London, United Kingdom. Now the power of final<br />

adjudication is vested in the Court of Final Appeal created in 1997. Under the Basic Law, its<br />

constitution, the territory remains a common law jurisdiction. Consequently, judges from other<br />

common law jurisdictions (including England and Wales) can be recruited and continue to serve<br />

in the judiciary according to Article 92 of the Basic Law. On the other hand, the power of<br />

interpretation of the Basic Law itself is vested in the Standing Committee of the National<br />

People's Congress (NPCSC) in Beijing (without retroactive effect), and the courts are authorised<br />

to interpret the Basic Law when trying cases, in accordance with Article 158 of the Basic Law.<br />

This arrangement became controversial in light of the right of abode issue in 1999, raising<br />

concerns for judicial independence.<br />

India<br />

In India, the Supreme Court of India was created on January 28, 1950 after the adoption of the<br />

Constitution. Article 141 of the Constitution of India states that the law declared by Supreme<br />

Court is to be binding on all Courts within the territory of India. It is the highest court in India<br />

and has ultimate judicial authority within India to interpret the Constitution and decide questions<br />

of national law (including local bylaws). The Supreme Court is vested with the power of judicial<br />

review to ensure the application of the rule of law. Besides, unlike most other countries, Indian<br />

Constitution places the supreme court (judiciary) co-equal with the legislative and the executive<br />

wings. Therefore the judiciary is neither superior nor inferior to the legislative or the executive.<br />

With reference to the State of Jammu and Kashmir (J&K) it would be relevant to note that, J&K<br />

has for various historical reasons a special status vis-a-vis the other states of India. Article 370 of<br />

the Constitution of India carves out certain exceptions for J&K. The Constitution of India is not<br />

fully applicable to the state of J&K. This is the effect of Article 370. The Constitution of India is<br />

applicable to the state of J&K with various modifications and exceptions. These are provided for<br />

in the Constitution (Application to Jammu and Kashmir) Order, 1954. Also, Jammu and<br />

Kashmir, unlike the other Indian states, also has its own Constitution. Although the Constitution<br />

of India is applicable to Jammu and Kashmir with numerous modifications, the Constitution<br />

(Application to Jammu and Kashmir) Order, 1954 makes Article 141 applicable to the state of<br />

J&K and hence law declared by Supreme Court is equally applicable to all courts of J&K<br />

including the High Court.<br />

Ireland<br />

The Supreme Court is the highest court in Ireland. It has authority to interpret the constitution,<br />

and strike down laws and activities of the state that it finds to be unconstitutional. It is also the<br />

highest authority in the interpretation of the law. Constitutionally it must have authority to<br />

interpret the constitution but its further appellate jurisdiction from lower courts is defined by law.<br />

The Irish Supreme Court consists of its presiding member, the Chief Justice, and seven other<br />

Page 17 of 115


judges. Judges of the Supreme Court are appointed by the President in accordance with the<br />

binding advice of the Government. The Supreme Court sits in the Four Courts in Dublin.<br />

Israel<br />

Israel's Supreme Court is at the head of the court system in the State of Israel. It is the highest<br />

judicial instance. The Supreme Court sits in Jerusalem. The area of its jurisdiction is the entire<br />

State. A ruling of the Supreme Court is binding upon every court, other than the Supreme Court<br />

itself. The Israeli supreme court is both an appellate court and the high court of justice. As an<br />

appellate court, the Supreme Court considers cases on appeal (both criminal and civil) on<br />

judgments and other decisions of the District Courts. It also considers appeals on judicial and<br />

quasi-judicial decisions of various kinds, such as matters relating to the legality of Knesset<br />

elections and disciplinary rulings of the Bar Association. As the High Court of Justice (Hebrew:<br />

Beit Mishpat Gavoha Le'Zedek הובג טפשמ תיב ‏;קדצל also known by its initials as Bagatz ‏,(ץ"גב the<br />

Supreme Court rules as a court of first instance, primarily in matters regarding the legality of<br />

decisions of State authorities: Government decisions, those of local authorities and other bodies<br />

and persons performing public functions under the law, and direct challenges to the<br />

constitutionality of laws enacted by the Knesset. The court has broad discretionary authority to<br />

rule on matters in which it considers it necessary to grant relief in the interests of justice, and<br />

which are not within the jurisdiction of another court or tribunal. The High Court of Justice<br />

grants relief through orders such as injunction, mandamus and Habeas Corpus, as well as through<br />

declaratory judgments. The Supreme Court can also sit at a further hearing on its own judgment.<br />

In a matter on which the Supreme Court has ruled - whether as a court of appeals or as the High<br />

Court of Justice - with a panel of three or more justices, it may rule at a further hearing with a<br />

panel of a larger number of justices. A further hearing may be held if the Supreme Court makes a<br />

ruling inconsistent with a previous ruling or if the Court deems that the importance, difficulty or<br />

novelty of a ruling of the Court justifies such hearing. The Supreme Court also holds the unique<br />

power of being able to order "trial de novo" (a retrial).<br />

Nauru<br />

In Nauru, there is no single highest court for all types of cases. The Supreme Court has final<br />

jurisdiction on constitutional matters, but any other case may be appealed further to the<br />

Appellate Court. In addition, an agreement between Nauru and Australia in 1976 provides for<br />

appeals from the Supreme Court of Nauru to the High Court of Australia in both criminal and<br />

civil cases, with the notable exception of constitutional cases.<br />

New Zealand<br />

In New Zealand, the right of appeal to the Privy Council was abolished following the passing of<br />

the Supreme Court Act (2003). The new Supreme Court of New Zealand was officially<br />

established at the beginning of 2004, although it did not come into operation until July. The High<br />

Court of New Zealand was until 1980 known as the Supreme Court.<br />

Page 18 of 115


Pakistan<br />

The Supreme Court has been the apex court for Pakistan since the declaration of the republic in<br />

1956 (previously the Privy Council had that function). The Supreme Court has the final say on<br />

matters of constitutional law, federal law or on matters of mixed federal and provincial<br />

competence. It can hear appeals on matters of provincial competence only if a matter of a<br />

constitutional nature is raised.<br />

With respect to Pakistan's territories (i.e. FATA, Azad Kashmir, Northern Areas and Islamabad<br />

Capital Territory (ICT)) the Supreme Court's jurisdiction is rather limited and varies from<br />

territory to territory; it can hear appeals only of a constitutional nature from FATA and Northern<br />

Areas, while ICT generally functions the same as provinces. Azad Kashmir has its own courts<br />

system and the constitution of Pakistan does not apply to it as such; appeals from Azad Kashmir<br />

relate to its relationship with Pakistan.<br />

The provinces have their own courts system, with the High Court as the apex court, except<br />

insofar as where an appeal can go to the Supreme Court as mentioned above.<br />

United Kingdom<br />

The Supreme Court of the United Kingdom was established by the Constitutional Reform Act<br />

2005 with effect from 1 October 2009 and assumed the judicial functions of the House of Lords,<br />

which include final appellate jurisdiction in civil cases throughout the UK, and in criminal cases<br />

in Northern Ireland, England and Wales. In the United Kingdom, there are separate legislatures<br />

with limited devolved powers over Wales, Northern Ireland and Scotland: devolution issues<br />

under the Scotland Act 1998, Government of Wales Act and Northern Ireland Act were<br />

transferred from the <strong>Judicial</strong> Committee of the Privy Council to the new Supreme Court by the<br />

Constitutional Reform Act.<br />

In respect of Community Law the Supreme Court is subject to the decisions of the European<br />

Court of Justice. Since there can be no appeal from the Supreme Court, there is an interlocutory<br />

procedure by which the Supreme Court may refer to the European Court questions of European<br />

law which arise in cases before it, and obtain a definitive ruling before the Supreme Court gives<br />

its judgment.<br />

The Supreme Court shares its members and accommodation at the Middlesex Guildhall with the<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Committee of the Privy Council which hears final appeals from certain smaller<br />

Commonwealth countries, admiralty cases, and certain appeals from the ecclesiastical courts and<br />

statutory private jurisdictions, such as professional and academic bodies.<br />

(The Constitutional Reform Act renamed the rarely cited Supreme Court of Judicature for<br />

England and Wales as the Senior Courts of England and Wales).<br />

Page 19 of 115


Civil Law Countries<br />

The Roman law and the Corpus Juris Civilis are generally held to be the historical model for<br />

civil law. From the late 18th century onwards, civil law jurisdictions began to codify their laws,<br />

most of all in civil codes.<br />

Austria<br />

In Austria, the Austrian Constitution of 1920 (based on a draft by Hans Kelsen) introduced<br />

judicial review of legislative acts for their constitutionality. This function is performed by the<br />

Constitutional Court (Verfassungsgerichtshof), which is also charged with the review of<br />

administrative acts on whether they violate constitutionally guaranteed rights. Other than that,<br />

administrative acts are reviewed by the Administrative Court (Verwaltungsgerichtshof). The<br />

Supreme Court (Oberste Gerichtshof (OGH)), stands at the top of Austria's system of "ordinary<br />

courts" (ordentliche Gerichte) as the final instance in issues of private law and criminal law.<br />

Brazil<br />

In Brazil, the Supreme Federal Tribunal is the highest court. It is both the constitutional court<br />

and the court of last resort in Brazilian law. It only reviews cases that may be unconstitutional or<br />

final habeas corpus pleads for criminal cases. It also judges, in original jurisdiction, cases<br />

involving members of congress, senators, ministers of state, members of the high courts and the<br />

President and Vice-President of the Republic. The Superior Court of Justice reviews State and<br />

Federal Circuit courts decisions for civil law and criminal law cases, when dealing with federal<br />

law or conflicting rulings. The Superior Labour Tribunal reviews cases involving labour law.<br />

The Superior Electoral Tribunal is the court of last resort of electoral law, and also oversees<br />

general elections. The Superior Military Tribunal is the highest court in matters of federal<br />

military law.<br />

Republic of China<br />

In the Republic of China, there are three different courts of last resort:<br />

Supreme Court of the Republic of China ( 中 華 民 國 最 高 法 院 ): civil and criminal cases.<br />

Supreme Administrative Court of the Republic of China ( 中 華 民 國 最 高 行 政 法 院 ):<br />

executive cases.<br />

Council of Grand Justices ( 大 法 官 會 議 ): interpretation of the Constitution, interpretation<br />

of laws and regulations, dissolution of political parties in violation of the Constitution,<br />

trial of impeachments against the President or Vice President.<br />

The Council of Grand Justices, consisting of 15 justices and mainly dealing with constitutional<br />

issues, is the counterpart of constitutional courts in some countries.<br />

All three courts are directly under the <strong>Judicial</strong> Yuan, whose president also serves as Chief Justice<br />

in the Council of Grand Justices.<br />

Page 20 of 115


Croatia<br />

In Croatia, the supreme jurisdiction is given to the Supreme Court, which secures a uniform<br />

application of laws. The Constitutional Court exists to verify constitutionality of laws and<br />

regulations, as well as decide on individual complaints on decisions on governmental bodies. It<br />

also decides on jurisdictional disputes between the legislative, executive and judicial branches.<br />

Denmark<br />

In Denmark, all ordinary courts have original jurisdiction to hear all types of cases, including<br />

cases of a constitutional or administrative nature. As a result, there exists no special<br />

constitutional court, and therefore final jurisdiction is vested with the Danish Supreme Court<br />

(Højesteret) which was established 14 February 1661 by king Frederik III.<br />

France<br />

In France, supreme appellate jurisdiction is divided among three judicial bodies:<br />

for judicial cases, i.e., civil or criminal matters: Court of Cassation (Cour de cassation)<br />

for administrative cases: Council of State (Conseil d'État)<br />

constitutional challenges of statutory laws: Constitutional Council (Conseil<br />

constitutionnel)<br />

When there is jurisdictional dispute between judicial and administrative courts: the Court of<br />

Arbitration (Tribunal des conflits), which is empanelled half from the Court of Cassation and<br />

half from the Council of State and presided over by the Minister of Justice, is called together to<br />

settle the dispute or hand down a final decision.<br />

The High Court (Haute Cour) exists only to impeach the President of the French Republic in<br />

case of "breach of his duties patently incompatible with his continuing in office". Since a<br />

constitutional amendment of 2007, the French Constitution states that the High Court is<br />

composed of all members of both Houses of Parliament. As of 2012, it has never been convened.<br />

Germany<br />

In Germany, there is no single supreme court.<br />

Final interpretation of the German Constitution, the Grundgesetz, is the task of the<br />

Bundesverfassungsgericht (Federal Constitutional Court), which is the de facto highest German<br />

court as it can declare federal and state legislation immediately ineffective, and has the power to<br />

overrule decisions of all other federal courts despite not being a regular court of appeals in the<br />

German court system.<br />

In civil and criminal cases, the Bundesgerichtshof is at the top of the hierarchy of courts. The<br />

other branches of the German judicial system each have their own appellate systems, each<br />

topped by a supreme court; these are the Bundessozialgericht for social security, the<br />

Page 21 of 115


Bundesarbeitsgericht for employment and labour, the Bundesfinanzhof for taxation, and the<br />

Bundesverwaltungsgericht for administrative law. The so-called Gemeinsamer Senat der<br />

Obersten Gerichtshöfe (Joint Senate of the Supreme Courts), is not a supreme court in itself, but<br />

an ad-hoc body that is convened only in when one supreme court intends to diverge from another<br />

supreme court's legal opinion. As the courts have well-defined areas of responsibility, this<br />

situation rarely arises, and so the Joint Senate only gathers rather rarely, and only to consider<br />

matters which are mostly definitory.<br />

The Netherlands<br />

In the Netherlands, the Supreme Court of the Netherlands is the highest. Its decisions, known as<br />

"arresten", are absolutely final. The court is banned from testing legislation against the<br />

constitution, pursuant to the principle of the sovereignty of the States-General; the court can,<br />

however, test legislation against treaties. Also, the ordinary courts in the Netherlands, including<br />

the Hoge Raad, do not deal with administrative law, which is dealt with in separate<br />

administrative courts, the highest of which is the Council of State (Raad van State)<br />

Iceland<br />

The Supreme Court of Iceland (Icelandic: Hæstiréttur Íslands, lit. Highest Court of Iceland) was<br />

founded under Act No. 22/1919 and held its first session on 16 February 1920. The Court holds<br />

the highest judicial power in Iceland, where the court system has two levels.<br />

Italy<br />

Italy follows the French system of different supreme courts.<br />

The Italian court of last resort for most disputes is the Corte Suprema di Cassazione. There is<br />

also a separate constitutional court, the Corte costituzionale, which has a duty of judicial review,<br />

and which can strike down legislation as being in conflict with the Constitution.<br />

Japan<br />

In Japan, the Supreme Court of Japan is called 最 高 裁 判 所 (Saikō-Saibansho; called 最 高 裁<br />

Saikō-Sai for short), located in Chiyoda, Tokyo, and is the highest court in Japan. It has ultimate<br />

judicial authority within Japan to interpret the Constitution and decide questions of national law<br />

(including local by-laws). It has the power of judicial review (i.e., it can declare Acts of Diet and<br />

Local Assembly, and administrative actions, unconstitutional).<br />

Luxembourg<br />

In Luxembourg, challenges on the conformity of the law to the Constitution are brought before<br />

the Cour Constitutionnelle (Constitutional Court). — The most used and common procedure to<br />

present these challenges is by way of the "question préjudicielle" (prejudicial question).<br />

The Court of last resort for civil and criminal proceedings is the "Cour de Cassation".<br />

Page 22 of 115


For administrative proceedings the highest court is the "Cour Administrative" (Administrative<br />

Court).<br />

Macau<br />

The supreme court of Macau is the Court of Final Appeal (Portuguese: Tribunal de Última<br />

Instância; Chinese: 澳 門 終 審 法 院 ).<br />

Philippines<br />

While the Philippines is generally considered a civil law nation, its Supreme Court is heavily<br />

modelled after the American Supreme Court. This can be attributed to the fact that the<br />

Philippines was colonized by both Spain and the United States, and the system of laws of both<br />

nations strongly influenced the development of Philippine laws and jurisprudence. Even as the<br />

body of Philippine laws remain mostly codified, the Philippine Civil Code expressly recognizes<br />

that decisions of the Supreme Court "form part of the law of the land", belonging to the same<br />

class as statutes. The 1987 Philippine Constitution also explicitly grants to the Supreme Court<br />

the power of judicial review over laws and executive actions. The Supreme Court is composed of<br />

1 Chief Justice and 14 Associate Justices. The court sits either en banc or in divisions, depending<br />

on the nature of the case to be decided.<br />

Portugal<br />

In Portugal, there are several supreme courts, each with a specific jurisdition:<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

The Supreme Court of Justice (Supremo Tribunal de Justiça) - for judicial (civil and<br />

criminal) matters;<br />

The Constitutional Court (Tribunal Constitucional) - for the constitutional matters;<br />

The Supreme Administrative Court (Supremo Tribunal Administrativo) - for<br />

administrative and fiscal matters;<br />

The Court of Auditors (Tribunal de Contas) - for auditing the public expenditure.<br />

Scotland<br />

Founded by papal bull in 1532, the Court of Session is the supreme civil court of Scotland, and<br />

the High Court of Justiciary is the supreme criminal court. However, the absolute highest court<br />

(excluding criminal matters) is the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom.<br />

Spain<br />

Spanish Supreme Court is the highest court for all cases in Spain (both private and public). Only<br />

those cases related to human rights can be appealed at the Constitutional Court (which also<br />

decides about acts accordance with Spanish Constitution).<br />

Page 23 of 115


In Spain, high courts cannot create binding precedents; however, lower rank courts usually<br />

observe Supreme Court interpretations. In most private law cases, two Supreme Court<br />

judgements supporting a claim are needed to appeal at the Supreme Court.<br />

Five sections form the Spanish Supreme court:<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

Section one judges private law cases (including commercial law).<br />

Section two decides about criminal appeals.<br />

Section three judges administrative cases and controls government normative powers.<br />

Section four is dedicated to labour law.<br />

Section five is dedicated to military justice.<br />

Sweden<br />

In Sweden, the Supreme Court and the Supreme Administrative Court respectively function as<br />

the highest courts of the land. The Supreme Administrative Court considers cases concerning<br />

disputes between individuals and administrative organs, as well as disputes among administrative<br />

organs, while the Supreme Court considers all other cases. The judges are appointed by the<br />

Government. In most cases, the Supreme Courts will only grant leave to appeal a case<br />

(prövningstillstånd) if the case involves setting a precedent in the interpretation of the law.<br />

Exceptions are issues where the Supreme Court is the court of first instance. Such cases include<br />

an application for a retrial of a criminal case in the light of new evidence, and prosecutions made<br />

against an incumbent minister of the Government for severe neglect of duty. If a lower court has<br />

to try a case which involves a question where there is no settled interpretation of the law, it can<br />

also refer the question to the relevant Supreme Court for an answer.<br />

Switzerland<br />

In Switzerland, the Federal Supreme Court of Switzerland is the final court of appeals. Due to<br />

Switzerland's system of direct democracy, it has no authority to review the constitutionality of<br />

federal statutes, but the people can strike down a proposed law by referendum. According to<br />

settled case law, however, the Court is authorised to review the compliance of all Swiss law with<br />

certain categories of international law, especially the European Convention of Human Rights.<br />

Sri Lanka<br />

In Sri Lanka, the Supreme Court of Sri Lanka was created in 1972 after the adoption of a new<br />

Constitution. The Supreme Court is the highest and final superior court of record and is<br />

empowered to exercise its powers, subject to the provisions of the Constitution. The court rulings<br />

take precedence over all lower Courts. The Sri Lanka judicial system is complex blend of both<br />

common-law and civil-law. In some cases such as capital punishment, the decision may be<br />

passed on to the President of the Republic for clemency petitions. However, when there is 2/3<br />

majority in the parliament in favour of president (as with present), the supreme court and its<br />

judges' powers become nullified as they could be fired from their positions according to the<br />

Constitution, if the president wants. Therefore, in such situations, Civil law empowerment<br />

vanishes.<br />

Page 24 of 115


South Africa<br />

In South Africa, the Supreme Court of Appeal (SCA) was created in 1994 and replaced the<br />

Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of South Africa as the highest court of appeal in nonconstitutional<br />

matters. The SAC is subordinate to the Constitutional Court, which is the highest<br />

court in matters involving the interpretation of the Constitution.<br />

In the Soviet Union<br />

In most nations with constitutions modelled after the Soviet Union, the legislature was given the<br />

power of being the court of last resort. In the People's Republic of China, the final power to<br />

interpret the law is vested in the Standing Committee of the National People's Congress<br />

(NPCSC). This power includes the power to interpret the basic laws of Hong Kong and Macau,<br />

the constitutional documents of the two special administrative regions which are common law<br />

and Portuguese-based legal system jurisdictions respectively. This power is a legislative power<br />

and not a judicial one in that an interpretation by the NPCSC does not affect cases which have<br />

already been decided.<br />

International Standards for <strong>Judicial</strong> Appointments<br />

Japan’s process for selecting Judges is longer and more stringent than the process in the United<br />

States and in Mexico. Assistant judges are appointed from those who have completed their<br />

training at the "Legal Training and Research Institute" located in Wako City. Once appointeid,<br />

assistant judges still<br />

may not qualify to<br />

sit alone until they<br />

have served for five<br />

years, and have been appointed by<br />

the Supreme Court.<br />

Judges require ten<br />

years of experience<br />

in practical affairs,<br />

public prosecutor, or practicing<br />

attorney. In the Japanese <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Branch there is the Supreme Court<br />

located in Japan,<br />

eight high courts,<br />

fifty district courts,<br />

fifty family courts,<br />

and 438 summary<br />

courts. In difference,<br />

Mexican Supreme Court Justices are<br />

appointed by the<br />

president, and then<br />

are approved by the<br />

Senate to serve for a<br />

life term. Other justices are appointed by the Supreme Court and serve for six years. Federal<br />

courts consist of the Supreme Court with 21 magistrates, 32 circuit tribunals and 98 district<br />

courts. The Supreme Court of Mexico is located in "Mexico City. Supreme Court Judges must be<br />

of ages 35 to 65 and hold a law degree during the five years preceding their nomination. In the<br />

United States Supreme Court, justices are appointed by the president and approved by the<br />

Senate. As in Mexico, justices serve for a life term or until retirement. The Supreme Court of the<br />

United States is located in "Washington D.C". The Federal court system consists of 94 federal<br />

judicial districts. The 94 districts are then divided into twelve regional circuits. The United States<br />

consist of five different types of courts that are considered subordinate to the Supreme Court,<br />

Page 25 of 115


U.S bankruptcy courts, U.S Courts of Appeal for the federal circuit, U.S Court of International<br />

Trade, U.S Courts of Appeal, and U.S District Courts.<br />

Page 26 of 115


Page 27 of 115


<strong>Judicial</strong> Independence<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Independence is the concept that the<br />

judiciary needs to be kept away from the other<br />

branches of government. That is, courts should<br />

not be subject to improper influence from the<br />

other branches of government, or from private or<br />

partisan interests. <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence is vital<br />

and important to the idea of separation of<br />

powers.<br />

Different countries deal with the idea of judicial<br />

independence through different means of<br />

judicial selection, or choosing judges. One way<br />

to promote judicial independence is by granting<br />

life tenure or long tenure for judges, which<br />

ideally frees them to decide cases and make<br />

rulings according to the rule of law and judicial<br />

discretion, even if those decisions are politically unpopular or opposed by powerful interests.<br />

This concept can be traced back to 18th century England.<br />

In some countries, the ability of the judiciary to check the legislature is enhanced by the power of<br />

judicial review. This power can be used, for example, by mandating certain action when the<br />

judiciary perceives that a branch of government is refusing to perform a constitutional duty, or<br />

by declaring laws passed by the legislature unconstitutional.<br />

Constitutional economics studies issues such as the proper distribution of national wealth<br />

including government spending on the judiciary. In transitional and developing countries,<br />

spending on the judiciary may be controlled by the executive. This undermines the principle of<br />

judicial independence because it creates a financial dependence of the judiciary on the executive.<br />

It is important to distinguish between two methods of corruption of the judiciary: the state<br />

(through budget planning and privileges) being the most dangerous, and private. State corruption<br />

of the judiciary can impede the ability of businesses to optimally facilitate the growth and<br />

development of a market economy.<br />

National and International Developments<br />

The development judicial independence has been argued to involve a cycle of national law<br />

impacting international law, and international law subsequently impacting national law. [2] This is<br />

said to occur in three phases: the first phase is characterized by the domestic development of the<br />

concept of judicial independence, the second by the seeping of this concept into the international<br />

scene, and the third by the re-domestication of newly reformulated international principles of<br />

judicial independence, which may have significant and dramatic results.<br />

Page 28 of 115


A notable illustration of this cycle of impacting and reimpacting is that of the United Kingdom.<br />

The first phase occurred in England with the original conception of judicial independence in the<br />

Act of Settlement in 1701. [3] The second phase was evident when England’s concepts regarding<br />

judicial independence first entered the international scene, and from there moved into the<br />

domestic arenas of other countries; for instance, England served as the theoretical model for<br />

Montesquieu’s separation of powers doctrine [4] and the Founding Fathers of the US Constitution<br />

used England as their dominant model in formulating the Constitution’s Article III, which is the<br />

foundation of American judicial independence. [5] Other common law countries, including<br />

Canada, Australia, and India, also adopted the British model of judicial independence. [6]<br />

In recent decades the third phase of judicial independence has come to play in the UK, [7] as it has<br />

been significantly influenced by judicial independence principles developed by international<br />

human rights constitutional documents. The European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) has had<br />

a significant impact on the conceptual analysis of judicial independence in England and<br />

Scotland. This process began in the 1990s with the ECtHR hearing UK cases, and later this<br />

process found its dramatic expression in the application of the ECtHR in the British Human<br />

Rights Act, which came into force in 2000. [8]<br />

Where British national law had previously impacted the international development of judicial<br />

independence, the British Constitutional Reform Act of 2005 [9] signaled a shift, with<br />

international law now impacting British domestic law. The Constitutional Reform Act<br />

dramatically reformed government control over the administration of justice in England and<br />

Wales; importantly, it discontinued the aberrant position of the Lord Chancellor, one of the<br />

country’s oldest constitutional offices, who was entrusted with a combination of legislative,<br />

executive, and judicial capacities. [10] The Lord Chancellor served as speaker of the Upper House<br />

of Parliament, the House of Lords; as a member of the executive branch and member of the<br />

senior cabinet; and as the head of the judiciary. Historically, the appellate function had a<br />

connection with the executive branch due to the types of cases typically heard – impeachment<br />

and the hearing of felony charges against peers. [11] The Constitutional Reform Act established<br />

new lines of demarcation between the Lord Chancellor and the judiciary, transferring all the<br />

judicial functions to the judiciary and entrusting the Lord Chancellor only with what are<br />

considered administrative and executive matters. In addition, the Constitutional Reform Act<br />

replaced the Lord Chancellor by the Lord Chief Justice as head of the judiciary, separated the<br />

judicial Appellate Committee of the House of Lords from the legislative parliament, reforming it<br />

as the Supreme Court, and creating a <strong>Judicial</strong> Appointments Commission. [12] The creation of the<br />

Supreme Court was important, for it finally separated the highest court of appeal from the House<br />

of Lords. [13]<br />

Thus, the United Kingdom, where the first phase of judicial independence began over three<br />

hundred years ago, illustrates vividly the mutual impacts of national and international law and<br />

jurisprudence in the area of judicial independence. It demonstrates a cycle of mutual normative<br />

impacts and cross-conceptual fertilizations. In this process, concepts and ideas have become<br />

enriched as they have been implemented in successive judicial and political systems, as each<br />

system has enhanced and deepened the concepts and ideas it actualized. In addition to the UK,<br />

similar developments of conceptual cross-fertilization can be seen internationally, for example in<br />

Page 29 of 115


EU law, [14] in civil law countries such as Austria, and in other common law jurisdictions<br />

including Canada. [15]<br />

International standards<br />

The International Association of <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence and World Peace produced the Mt.<br />

Scopus International Standards of <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence between 2007 and 2012. These built on<br />

the same association's New Delhi Minimum Standards on <strong>Judicial</strong> independence adopted in 1982<br />

and their Montréal Universal Declaration on the Independence of Justice in 1983. Other<br />

influences they cite for the standards include the UN Basic Principles of <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence<br />

from 1985, the Burgh House Principles of <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence in International Law (for the<br />

international judiciary), Tokyo Law Asia Principles, Council of Europe Statements on judicial<br />

independence (particularly the Recommendation of the Committee of Ministers to Member<br />

States on the independence, efficiency and role of judges), the Bangalore Principles of <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Conduct 2002, and the American Bar Association's revision of its ethical standards for judges. [16]<br />

The Justice System<br />

In recent years, the principle of <strong>Judicial</strong> Independence has been described as one of the core<br />

values of the justice system.<br />

Contemporary Usage<br />

Under the uncodified British Constitution, there are two important conventions which help to<br />

preserve judicial independence. The first is that the Parliament of the United Kingdom does not<br />

comment on the cases which are before the court. The second is the principle of parliamentary<br />

privilege: that Members of Parliament are protected from prosecution in certain circumstances by<br />

the courts.<br />

Furthermore, the independence of the judiciary is guaranteed by the Constitutional Reform Act<br />

2005. [23] In order to try to promote the independence of the judiciary, the selection process is<br />

designed to minimize political interference. The process focuses on senior members of the<br />

judiciary rather than on politicians. Part 2 of the Tribunals, Courts and Enforcement Act 2007<br />

aims to increase diversity among the judiciary.<br />

The pay of judges is determined by an independent pay review body. It will make<br />

recommendations to the government having taken evidence from a variety of sources. The<br />

government accepts these recommendations and will traditionally implement them fully. As long<br />

as judges hold their positions in "good order," they remain in post until they wish to retire or<br />

until they reach the mandatory retirement age of 70.<br />

As of March 2008, the legal profession is self-regulating; it is responsible for implementing and<br />

enforcing its own professional standards and disciplining its own members. In this case, the<br />

bodies are the Bar Council and the Law Society. However, this self-regulation will come to an<br />

end when those bodies themselves come under the regulation of the Legal Standards Board,<br />

composed of non-lawyers, under the Legal Services Act 2007.<br />

Page 30 of 115


In The United States<br />

Federal Courts<br />

Article III of the United States Constitution establishes the federal courts as part of the federal<br />

government.<br />

The Constitution provides that federal judges, including judges of the Supreme Court of the<br />

United States, are appointed by the President "by and with the advice and consent of the Senate."<br />

Once appointed, federal judges:<br />

...both of the supreme and inferior Courts, shall hold their Offices during good Behavior, and<br />

shall, at stated Times, receive for their Services a Compensation which shall not be diminished<br />

during their Continuance in Office.<br />

Federal judges vacate office only upon death, resignation, or impeachment and removal from<br />

office by Congress; only 13 federal judges have ever been impeached. The phrase "during good<br />

behavior" predates the Declaration of Independence. John Adams equated it with quamdiu se<br />

bene gesserint in a letter to the Boston Gazette published on 11 January 1773, [24] a phrase that<br />

first appeared in section 3 of the Act of Settlement 1701 in England.<br />

The President is free to appoint any person to the federal bench, yet typically he consults with the<br />

American Bar Association,whose Standing Committee on the Federal Judiciary rates each<br />

nominee "Well Qualified," "Qualified" or "Not Qualified."<br />

State Courts<br />

State courts deal with independence of the judiciary in many ways, and several forms of judicial<br />

selection are used for both trial courts and appellate courts (including state supreme courts),<br />

varying between states and sometimes within states. In some states, judges are elected (sometime<br />

on a partisan ballot, other times on a nonpartisan one), while in others they are appointed by the<br />

governor or state legislature.<br />

The 2000 case of Bush v. Gore, in which a majority of the Supreme Court, including some<br />

appointees of President George H. W. Bush, overruled challenges to the election of the George<br />

W. Bush then pending in the Florida Supreme Court, whose members had all been appointed by<br />

Democratic governors, is seen by many as reinforcing the need for judicial independence, both<br />

with regard to the Florida Supreme Court and the US Supreme Court. This case has focused<br />

increased attention on judicial outcomes as opposed to the traditional focus on judicial<br />

qualifications.<br />

In The Soviet Union<br />

The Judiciary of Russia interprets and applies the law of Russia. It is defined under the<br />

Constitution and law with a hierarchical structure with the Constitutional Court, Supreme Court,<br />

Page 31 of 115


and Supreme Court of Arbitration at the apex. The district courts are the primary criminal trial<br />

courts, and the regional courts are the primary appellate courts. The judiciary is governed by the<br />

All-Russian Congress of Judges and its Council of Judges, and its management is aided by the<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Department of the Supreme Court, the <strong>Judicial</strong> Qualification Collegia, the Ministry of<br />

Justice, and the various courts' chairpersons. And although there are many officers of the court,<br />

including jurors, the Prosecutor General remains the most powerful component of the Russian<br />

judicial system.<br />

The judiciary faces many problems and a widespread lack of confidence but has also made much<br />

progress in recent times. There have been serious violations of the accepted separation of powers<br />

doctrine, systematic attempts to undermine jury trials, problems with access to justice, problems<br />

with court infrastructure and financial support, and corruption. But the judiciary has also seen a<br />

fairer and more efficient administration, a strengthening of the rule of law, moves towards a<br />

more adversarial system, and increased utilization of the justice system under Putin.<br />

Russia has a trifurcated court system, with constitutional, ordinary, and commercial courts. The<br />

Constitutional Court of Russia is considered a separate, independent court. The district courts are<br />

the primary criminal trial courts, and the regional courts are the primary appellate courts.<br />

The ordinary courts have a four-tiered hierarchy and are responsible for civil and criminal cases:<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

the Supreme Court of Russia,<br />

regional courts,<br />

district courts, and<br />

magistrate courts.<br />

In 1995, the courts sentenced about 1 million people for criminal offenses, and considered 3<br />

million administrative offenses and 2.5 million civil cases.<br />

Constitutional Court<br />

The Constitutional Court of Russia (Конституционный суд<br />

Российской Федерации) is responsible for cases<br />

concerning conformity with the Constitution, judicial<br />

disputes between 2 or more federal bodies, between a federal<br />

body and a member of the Federation, and between members<br />

of the Federation. [2] As such, it practices "constitutional<br />

review" (as differentiated from judicial review) and decides<br />

whether federal laws, presidential decrees and directives,<br />

and local constitutions, charters, and laws comply with the<br />

federal constitution, as well as treaties between the national government and a regional<br />

governments and between regional governments.<br />

It is composed of 19 judges, and may sit in plenary sessions but is otherwise divided into 2<br />

chambers. [2] The Constitutional Court consists of two chambers with 10 and 9 judges<br />

Page 32 of 115


espectively. The Chairman presides over one of the chambers, the Deputy Chairman presides<br />

over the other chamber.<br />

Constitutionality of laws, disputes concerning competence of governmental agencies,<br />

impeachment of the President of Russia, and Constitutional Court's proposals of legislation must<br />

be dealt with by the plenary session. The Constitutional Court may also submit to the plenary<br />

session any other issue at its discretion.<br />

In general, the court hears cases referred by the President, the Federation Council, the State<br />

Duma, one-fifth of the members of either chamber of the Federal Assembly, the Government, the<br />

Supreme Court, or other bodies of legislative or executive authority. [2] It also hears complains by<br />

citizens of allegations of constitutional rights violations. [2]<br />

Supreme Court<br />

The Supreme Court of Russia (Верховный суд Российской<br />

Федерации) is the highest court, and supervises inferior<br />

courts of general jurisdiction. It occasionally sits as a court<br />

of first instance in cases where important interests of state<br />

are at issue; in this case it normally consists of a judge and a<br />

jury, but occasionally consists of three judges.<br />

There are 115 members of the Supreme Court. At plenary<br />

sessions the Supreme Court studies the judicial decisions of<br />

lower courts on various topics and adopts resolutions, which<br />

establish recommendations on the interpretation of particular<br />

provisions of law for lower courts for uniform application.<br />

The Presidium of the Russian Supreme Court (Президиум<br />

Верховного Суда Российской Федерации) represents<br />

Russia's final court of appeal. The Presidium consists of<br />

thirteen judges: the Chairman of the Supreme Court, its first<br />

deputy chairman, its six deputy chairmen and five other<br />

Supreme Court judges. Only the Prosecutor General has the right to appeal to the Presidium, and<br />

as a result, very few criminal cases reviewed by the three-judge panels of the Supreme Court<br />

make it to the Presidium. Only 0.4% of criminal cases in 1998 ended with an acquittal in the<br />

Presidium.<br />

The court is divided into several chambers or collegia (коллегия), and each chamber normally<br />

sits with three judges:<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

civil (коллегии по гражданским);<br />

criminal (коллегии по уголовным);<br />

military (Военной коллегии);<br />

administrative (коллегии по административным); and<br />

Page 33 of 115


appeals (Апелляционная коллегия; formerly the cassation panel or Кассационная<br />

коллегия), which can review decisions of the other chambers.<br />

There are several entities attached to the Supreme Court. The Academic Consultative Council<br />

(Научно-консультативный совет при Верховном Суде Российской Федерации) assists the<br />

court in various legal and academic matters and comprises members of the Supreme Court itself,<br />

academics, practicing lawyers, and law enforcement officers. The members of the Academic<br />

Consultative Council are elected at plenary sessions of the Supreme Court. The <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Department is responsible for administration of the courts.<br />

Regional Courts<br />

Regional courts (also called kray courts and city courts) are the courts at the regional level,<br />

though are not all named as such. This includes the supreme courts of the Republics of Russia,<br />

courts of the krais (territories; краевой суд or kray courts), courts of the oblasts (regions;<br />

областной суд), city courts of the federal cities of Russia (Moscow and Saint Petersburg), courts<br />

of the autonomous oblasts, and courts of the autonomous okrugs.<br />

The courts sit as both courts of first instance and appellate courts. As courts of first instance, they<br />

hear more complex civil cases and serious criminal cases. A judge and a jury, or alternatively 3<br />

judges, hear these cases. As appellate courts, they hear decisions of district courts that have not<br />

yet entered into force, and consist of 3 judges.<br />

District Courts<br />

District courts (районный суд or городской суд; also called<br />

rayon or raion courts), which were called People's Courts<br />

until 1996, are primarily courts of first instance but<br />

sometimes hear appeals from magistrate courts. [7] They are<br />

formed in areas (районах or rayons), urban areas (районах<br />

в городах), and cities (городах). Decisions of the court are<br />

appealed to the regional court.<br />

As courts of first instance, they handle criminal cases where imprisonment is for more than 3<br />

years, and consist of 1 judge and a jury where required. As courts of appeal from decisions of the<br />

magistrate courts consisting of 1 justice of the peace, they consist of 1 judge and retry the case.<br />

Arbitration Courts<br />

Arbitration courts (арбитражный суд; also called arbitrazh or commercial courts) hear cases<br />

dealing with a wide matter of contractual issues, such as rights of ownership, contract changes,<br />

performance of obligations, loans, bank accounts, and bankruptcy. They operate independently<br />

of the other courts. The Supreme Court of Arbitration of Russia (also called the Supreme<br />

Commercial Court, the Supreme Arbitrazh Court, or the Supreme Arbitration Court) is the<br />

highest such court, and consists of 1 chairman and 4 deputy chairmen.<br />

Page 34 of 115


Magistrate Courts<br />

Magistrate courts (мировой суд; also called Justices of the Peace Courts) handle criminal cases<br />

where imprisonment is for less than three years such as petty hooliganism, public drunkenness,<br />

and serious traffic violations of a non-criminal nature, minor civil cases such as simple divorces,<br />

some property cases, disputes over land, and some labor cases, as well as some federal<br />

administrative law cases. The magistrate courts were expected to hear two-thirds of all civil<br />

cases and close to 100,000 criminal cases. It consists of one magistrate or justice of the peace.<br />

Pursuant to the 2002 Federal Law on Organs of the <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Community, which is the legal basis for the judicial organs<br />

of self-government, the All-Russian Congress of Judges is<br />

the supreme body of the judiciary. [10] The Congress elects<br />

the members of the Council of Judges, the self-government<br />

body of the judiciary.<br />

The <strong>Judicial</strong> Department of the Supreme Court of Russia is<br />

responsible for administration of the courts, such as selection and training of judicial candidates,<br />

working with law institutes, and qualifications of judges and other court officers. It is expected to<br />

enhance the independence of the judicial branch. It also supports the Council of Judges and the<br />

Supreme Qualifying Collegium.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Qualification Collegia are bodies of judicial self-regulation that were established at the<br />

regional (<strong>Judicial</strong> Qualification Collegia) and national (Supreme Qualification Collegium) levels.<br />

They play a key role in the appointment, promotion and dismissal of judges.<br />

Some judges serve as a court chairperson. The court chairperson is solely responsible for the<br />

allocation of cases to judges, has considerable powers in the matters of appointment, and makes<br />

the initial recommendation for disciplinary measures, in particular dismissal.<br />

Court Officers<br />

Judges are appointed by the Federation Council, and serve for life. Candidates are recommended<br />

by the Qualification Collegia / Supreme Qualification Collegium to the President, who in turn<br />

recommends candidates to the Federation Council.<br />

The judges of the Constitutional Court are nominated by the President and appointed by the<br />

Federation Council for 12 years, and the judges must be at least 40 years old and must retire at<br />

70 years old. The also must have served as a lawyer for at least 15 years and have a "recognized<br />

high qualification" (quotation from Constitutional Court Act) in law.<br />

The Russian Minister of Justice is responsible for appointing judges to regional and city courts;<br />

however, in practice, many appointments below the national level still are made by the chief<br />

executives of subnational jurisdictions.<br />

Page 35 of 115


Judges of the district courts are appointed by the President. A candidate must be at least 25 years<br />

old, is expected to have received a higher legal education (commonly a specialist degree), have<br />

at least 5 years of experience in the legal profession, and pass an examination from the Ministry<br />

of Justice.<br />

Justices of the peace are usually appointed by the regional legislature, but may also be elected.<br />

Justices of the peace require most of the same qualifications.<br />

Prosecutors<br />

The Prosecutor General of Russia is the highest prosecutor in Russia, and both he and his office<br />

are independent from the executive, legislative and judicial branches of power. The Prosecutor<br />

General remains the most powerful component of the Russian judicial system.<br />

The Prosecutor General is entrusted with:<br />

1. prosecution in court on behalf of the State;<br />

2. representation of the interests of a citizen or of the State in court in cases determined by<br />

law;<br />

3. supervision of the observance of laws by bodies that conduct detective and search<br />

activity, inquiry and pre-trial investigation;<br />

4. supervision of the observance of laws in the execution of judicial decisions in criminal<br />

cases, and also in the application of other measures of coercion related to the restraint of<br />

personal liberty of citizens.<br />

The Investigative Committee of Russia, sometimes described as the "Russian FBI", is the main<br />

federal investigating authority in Russia, formed in place of the Investigative Committee of the<br />

Prosecutor General in 2011.<br />

The Prosecutor General is nominated by the President of Russia and appointed by the majority of<br />

Federation Council for a term of five years. If the nomination fails, the President must nominate<br />

another candidate within 30 days. The resignation of the Prosecutor General before the end of his<br />

term should be approved by both a majority of Federation Council and the President.<br />

Advocates<br />

The Russian legal profession is unregulated, but there have been moves towards unification and<br />

regulation recently. Anyone with a legal education can practice law, but only a member of the<br />

Advokatura (Адвокатура) may practice before a criminal court. Legal education has traditionally<br />

begun with the specialist degree in law (специалист по правоведению). An "advocate" is an<br />

attorney who has demonstrated qualification and belongs to an organizational structure of<br />

advocates specified by law, known as being "called to the bar" in commonwealth countries.<br />

An examination is administered by the qualifications commission of a court for admission to its<br />

Advokatura. To sit for the exam, one must have a higher legal education (commonly a specialist<br />

degree) and either two years of experience in legal work or a training program in a law firm. The<br />

Page 36 of 115


exam is both written and oral, but the main test is oral. The qualifications commission is<br />

composed of seven advocates, two judges, two representatives of the regional legislature, and<br />

two representatives of the Ministry of Justice.<br />

In 1988 there were 25,000 lawyers, [19] and in 2002 there were 47,000 defense lawyers in all of<br />

Russia.<br />

Jurors<br />

A juror must be 25 years old, legally competent, and without a criminal record.<br />

Regulation of Russian Law<br />

The judiciary is primarily regulated by the Constitution of Russia, the Code of Criminal<br />

Procedure, and the 1996 Federal Constitutional Law on the <strong>Judicial</strong> System of the Russian<br />

Federation. The Constitution states that the judicial branch is independent of the legislative and<br />

executive branches, but there have been serious violations of the accepted separation of powers<br />

doctrine.<br />

There is no usage of precedent, as used in common law legal systems. As such, the law on appeal<br />

may depend on the composition of the chamber deciding the appeal. A chamber normally<br />

consists of 3 judges, out of the dozens of judges within the court (19 in the Constitutional Court,<br />

115 in the Supreme Court). Without the legal principle of stare decisis, for each case a chamber<br />

may come to a different, even contradictory, conclusion, even compared to chambers within the<br />

same session. If they come to relatively consistent decisions, those in civil law legal systems call<br />

this jurisprudence constante.<br />

Criminal Procedure<br />

Everyone has the right of legal assistance. The accused have the right to a defense lawyer from<br />

the time they are detained, put in custody, charged, or declared a suspect. According to the 2001<br />

Code of Criminal Procedure, defense lawyers can participate in investigations with the consent<br />

of the prosecutor, meet privately with a client, collect evidence independently of the prosecutor,<br />

identify defense witnesses, present expert witnesses, be present for all court procedures, access to<br />

the prosecutions evidence after the investigation, and to file appeals regarding court procedures.<br />

For serious and specific crimes, the accused have the option of a jury trial consisting of 12<br />

jurors. [8] The crimes that may be tried by a jury are murder, kidnapping, rape with aggravating<br />

circumstances, child trafficking, gangsterism, large-scale bribery, treason, terrorism, public calls<br />

for violent change in the constitutional system or for the seizure of power, and select other<br />

crimes against the state. The Constitution of Russia stipulates that, until the abolition of the death<br />

penalty, all defendants in a case that may result in a death sentence are entitled to a jury trial.<br />

Jurors are selected by the prosecution and defense from a list of 30-40 eligible candidates. They<br />

are similar to common law juries, and unlike lay judges, in that they sit separately from the<br />

judges and decide questions of fact alone while the judge determines questions of law. They<br />

Page 37 of 115


must return unanimous verdicts during the first 3 hours of deliberation, but may return majority<br />

verdicts after that, with 6 jurors being enough to acquit. They may also request that the judge<br />

show leniency in sentencing.<br />

Main Criticism<br />

The arbitrazh courts have been singled out as particularly effective in dealing with business<br />

issues. [9] Also, the number of people seeking assistance of the judicial system has increased from<br />

1 million under Yeltsin to 6 million under Putin.<br />

However, Transparency International found that 78% of respondents reported they did not expect<br />

to find justice in the courts. Both public perception and comments from senior judges point to<br />

bribery as prevalent at the trial court level.<br />

There have been serious violations of the accepted separation of powers doctrine. Constitutional<br />

Court Judge and Council of Judges member Vladimir Yaroslavtsev, in a 2009 interview with the<br />

Spanish newspaper El País, claimed that the presidential executive office and security services<br />

had undermined judicial independence in Russia. Constitutional Court Judge Anatoly Kononov,<br />

who had frequently dissented from decisions taken by the majority of the court, in his interview<br />

to Sobesednik supported Yaroslavtsev, claiming that there was no independent judiciary in<br />

Russia.<br />

There have been accusations of systematic attempts to undermine jury trials, including juror<br />

intimidation and bribery, and systematic trial delays. The number of jury trials remains small, at<br />

about 600 per year, out of about 1 million trials. Lawmakers are continuously chipping away at<br />

what types of criminal offenses merit a jury trial. Juries have granted acquittals in 15-20% of<br />

cases, compared with less than 1% in cases decided by judges. Juries may be dismissed and<br />

skeptical juries have been dismissed on the verge of verdicts, and acquittals are frequently<br />

overturned by higher courts.<br />

Compared to other industrialized nations, Russia has historically had a small number of lawyers<br />

in relation to its population. In 2002 there were 47,000 defense lawyers in all of Russia, while the<br />

courts sentenced about 1 million people for criminal offenses and considered 3 million<br />

administrative offenses and 2.5 million civil cases, and the Russian Census of 2002 put the<br />

resident population at more than 145 million people. For a comparison to the United States, the<br />

number of active lawyers practicing before the judiciary of California as of December 2012 was<br />

more than 179,000, while the 2010 United States Census put the California population at more<br />

than 37 million people.<br />

The court chairperson has sole discretion for allocation of court cases, and there is no systematic<br />

procedure for allocation based on objective criteria. There have been reports where the<br />

chairperson always assigns sensitive cases to particular judges or transfers cases to another judge<br />

during an ongoing trial.<br />

There have been allegations of corruption concerning the oral exam required for admission to the<br />

Advokatura, known as being "called to the bar" in commonwealth countries.<br />

Page 38 of 115


Page 39 of 115


<strong>Judicial</strong> Review<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review is the doctrine under which legislative and executive actions are subject to<br />

review by the judiciary. A court with judicial review power may invalidate laws and decisions<br />

that are incompatible with a higher authority, such as the terms of a written<br />

constitution.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review is one of the checks and balances in the separation of<br />

powers: the<br />

power of the judiciary to supervise the legislative<br />

and executive branches. The<br />

doctrine varies between<br />

jurisdictions, so the procedure<br />

and scope of judicial review<br />

may differ between and within<br />

countries.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review can be understood in the context of two distinct—but parallel—legal systems,<br />

civil law and common law, and also by two distinct theories of democracy regarding the manner<br />

in which government should be organized with respect to the principles and doctrines of<br />

legislative supremacy and the separation of powers.<br />

First, two distinct legal systems, civil law and common law, have different views about judicial<br />

review. Common-law judges are seen as sources of law, capable of creating new legal principles,<br />

and also capable of rejecting legal principles that are no longer valid. In the civil-law tradition,<br />

judges are seen as those who apply the law, with no power to create (or destroy) legal principles.<br />

Secondly, the idea of separation of powers is another theory about how a democratic society's<br />

government should be organized. In contrast to legislative supremacy, the idea of separation of<br />

powers was first introduced by Montesquieu; it was later institutionalized in the United States by<br />

the Supreme Court ruling in Marbury v. Madison under the court of John Marshall. Separation of<br />

powers is based on the idea that no branch of government should be able to exert power over any<br />

other branch without due process of law; each branch of government should have a check on the<br />

powers of the other branches of government, thus creating a regulative balance among all<br />

branches of government. The key to this idea is checks and balances. In the United States,<br />

judicial review is considered a key check on the powers of the other two branches of government<br />

by the judiciary, although the power itself is not granted by the Constitution.<br />

Differences in organizing "democratic" societies led to different views regarding judicial review,<br />

with societies based on common law and those stressing a separation of powers being the most<br />

likely to utilize judicial review. Nevertheless, many countries whose legal systems are based on<br />

the idea of legislative supremacy have learned the possible dangers and limitations of entrusting<br />

power exclusively to the legislative branch of government. Many countries with civil-law<br />

systems have adopted a form of judicial review to stem the tyranny of the majority.<br />

Another reason why judicial review should be understood in the context of both the development<br />

of two distinct legal systems (civil law and common law) and two theories of democracy<br />

Page 40 of 115


(legislative supremacy and separation of powers) is that some countries with common-law<br />

systems do not have judicial review of primary legislation. Though a common-law system is<br />

present in the United Kingdom, the country still has a strong attachment to the idea of legislative<br />

supremacy; consequently, judges in the United Kingdom do not have the power to strike down<br />

primary legislation. However, since the United Kingdom became a member of the European<br />

Union there has been tension between its tendency toward legislative supremacy and the EU's<br />

legal system, which specifically gives the Court of Justice of the European Union the power of<br />

judicial review.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review of Administrative Acts<br />

Most modern legal systems allow the courts to review administrative acts (individual decisions<br />

of a public body, such as a decision to grant a subsidy or to withdraw a residence permit). In<br />

most systems, this also includes review of secondary legislation (legally-enforceable rules of<br />

general applicability adopted by administrative bodies). Some countries (notably France and<br />

Germany) have implemented a system of administrative courts which are charged with resolving<br />

disputes between members of the public and the administration. In other countries (including the<br />

United States, Scotland and the Netherlands), judicial review is carried out by regular civil courts<br />

although it may be delegated to specialized panels within these courts (such as the<br />

Administrative Court within the High Court of England and Wales). The United States employs<br />

a mixed system in which some administrative decisions are reviewed by the United States district<br />

courts (which are the general trial courts), some are reviewed directly by the United States courts<br />

of appeals and others are reviewed by specialized tribunals such as the United States Court of<br />

Appeals for Veterans Claims (which, despite its name, is not technically part of the federal<br />

judicial branch). It is quite common that before a request for judicial review of an administrative<br />

act is filed with a court, certain preliminary conditions (such as a complaint to the authority<br />

itself) must be fulfilled. In most countries, the courts apply special procedures in administrative<br />

cases.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review of Primary Legislation<br />

There are three broad approaches to judicial review of the constitutionality of primary<br />

legislation—that is, laws passed directly by an elected legislature. Some countries do not permit<br />

a review of the validity of primary legislation. In the United Kingdom, statutes cannot be set<br />

aside under the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. Another example is the Netherlands,<br />

where the constitution expressly forbids the courts to rule on the question of constitutionality of<br />

primary legislation.<br />

Review by General Courts<br />

In the United States, federal and state courts (at all levels, both appellate and trial) are able to<br />

review and declare the "constitutionality", or agreement with the Constitution (or lack thereof) of<br />

legislation that is relevant to any case properly within their jurisdiction. In American legal<br />

language, "judicial review" refers primarily to the adjudication of constitutionality of statutes,<br />

especially by the Supreme Court of the United States. This is commonly held to have been<br />

Page 41 of 115


established in the case of Marbury v. Madison, which was argued before the Supreme Court in<br />

1803. A similar system was also adopted in Australia.<br />

Review by A Specialized Court<br />

In 1920, Czechoslovakia adopted a system of judicial review by a specialized court, the<br />

Constitutional Court as written by Hans Kelsen, a leading jurist of the time. This system was<br />

later adopted by Austria and became known as the Austrian System, also under the primary<br />

authorship of Hans Kelsen, being emulated by a number of other countries. In these systems,<br />

other courts are not competent to question the constitutionality of primary legislation; they often<br />

may, however, initiate the process of review by the Constitutional Court.<br />

Russia adopts a mixed model since (as in the US) courts at all levels, both federal and state, are<br />

empowered to review primary legislation and declare its constitutionality; as in the Czech<br />

Republic, there is a constitutional court in charge of reviewing the constitutionality of primary<br />

legislation. The difference is that in the first case, the decision about the laws adequacy to the<br />

Russian Constitution only binds the parties to the lawsuit; in the second, the Court's decision<br />

must be followed by judges and government officials at all levels.<br />

Legal Reformation<br />

Law Reform or Legal Reform is the process of examining existing laws, and advocating and<br />

implementing changes in a legal system, usually with the aim of enhancing justice or efficiency.<br />

Intimately related are law reform bodies or law commissions, which are organizations set up to<br />

facilitate law reform. Law reform bodies carry out research and recommend ways to simplify and<br />

modernize the law. Many law reform bodies are statutory corporations set up by governments,<br />

although they are usually independent from government control, providing intellectual<br />

independence to accurately reflect and report on how the law should progress.<br />

Law reform activities can include preparation and presentation of cases in court in order to<br />

change the common law; lobbying of government officials in order to change legislation; and<br />

research or writing that helps to establish an empirical basis for other law reform activities.<br />

The four main methods in reforming law are repeal (get rid of a law), creation of new law,<br />

consolidation (change existing law) and codification.<br />

The expression "law reform" is used in a number of senses and some of these are close to being<br />

wholly incompatible with each other.<br />

In the Law Reform Commission Act 1975, the expression "reform" includes, in relation to the<br />

law or a branch of the law, its development, its codification (including in particular its<br />

simplification and modernisation) and the revision and consolidation of statute law, and kindred<br />

words must be construed accordingly.<br />

Page 42 of 115


Correlation with <strong>Judicial</strong> Reform<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> reform is the complete or partial political reform of a country's judiciary. <strong>Judicial</strong> reform<br />

is often done as a part of wider reform of the country's political system or a legal reform. The<br />

President of the Constitutional Court of the Russian Federation, Valery Zorkin, gives in his<br />

article, "Twelve Theseses on Legal Reform in Russia", first published in Russian magazine<br />

«Legislation and Economics», N. 2, 2004 an explained correlation between legal and judicial<br />

reform: "Complete legal reform should normally include not only judicial reform, but also<br />

reform of various aspects of the structural system and content of legislation, legal education,<br />

legal awareness by the population, and also the corporate consciousness of the whole legal<br />

community. <strong>Judicial</strong> reform usually aims to improve such things as law courts, procuracies,<br />

advocacy (bar), inquest, executory processes, and record keeping.".<br />

Economic Considerations<br />

Legal reform can be the ―driver‖ for all other reforms, including reform of the economy. A true<br />

market economy cannot be created without ensuring both full guarantees of private property and<br />

transparent predictability for entrepreneurial activity, on the one hand; and sufficiently<br />

reasonable legal control over economic processes, on the other hand. Legal reform should be an<br />

integral part of any on-going reform process. Legal reform is a tool for implementing necessary<br />

reforms, to balance competing interests, create a dynamic and sustainable economy, and build a<br />

sustainable civil society. During last decades the judiciary became active in economic issues<br />

related with economic rights established by constitution because "economics may provide insight<br />

into questions that bear on the proper legal interpretation". [4] Since many a country with a<br />

transitional political and economic system continues treating its constitution as an abstract legal<br />

document disengaged from the economic policy of the state, practice of judicial review of<br />

economic acts of executive and legislative branches became to grow.<br />

The budget of the judiciary in many transitional and developing countries is completely<br />

controlled by the executive. The latter undermines the separation of powers, as it creates a<br />

critical financial dependence of the judiciary. The proper national wealth distribution including<br />

the government spending on the judiciary is subject of the constitutional economics. It is<br />

important to distinguish between the two methods of corruption of the judiciary: the state<br />

(through budget planning and various privileges), and the private.<br />

The US Model<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review within the United States is the<br />

ability of a court to examine and decide if a<br />

statute, treaty or administrative regulation<br />

contradicts or violates the provisions of existing<br />

law, a State Constitution, or ultimately the United<br />

States Constitution. While the U.S. Constitution<br />

does not explicitly define a "power" of judicial<br />

review, the authority for judicial review in the<br />

United States has been inferred from the<br />

Page 43 of 115


structure, provisions, and history of the Constitution.<br />

Two landmark decisions by the U.S. Supreme Court served to confirm the inferred constitutional<br />

authority for judicial review in the United States: In 1796, Hylton v. United States was the first<br />

case decided by the Supreme Court involving a direct challenge to the constitutionality of an act<br />

of Congress, the Carriage Act of 1794 which imposed a "carriage tax". The Court engaged in the<br />

process of judicial review by examining the plaintiff's claim that the carriage tax was<br />

unconstitutional. After review, the Supreme Court decided the Carriage Act was not<br />

unconstitutional. In 1803, Marbury v. Madison was the first Supreme Court case where the Court<br />

asserted its authority for judicial review to strike down a law as unconstitutional. At the end of<br />

his opinion in this decision, Chief Justice John Marshall maintained that the Supreme Court's<br />

responsibility to overturn unconstitutional legislation was a necessary consequence of their<br />

sworn oath of office to uphold the Constitution as instructed in Article Six of the Constitution.<br />

As of 2014, the United States Supreme Court has held 176 Acts of the U.S. Congress<br />

unconstitutional.<br />

Constitutional Authorization<br />

The Constitution does not expressly provide that the federal judiciary has the power of judicial<br />

review. Rather, the power to declare laws unconstitutional has been deemed an implied power,<br />

derived from Article III and Article VI.<br />

The provisions relating to the federal judicial power in Article III state:<br />

“<br />

The<br />

judicial power of the United States, shall be vested in one<br />

Supreme Court, and in such inferior courts as the Congress may from<br />

time to time ordain and establish. . . . The judicial power shall extend<br />

to all cases, in law and equity, arising under this Constitution, the<br />

laws of the United States, and treaties made, or which shall be made,<br />

under their authority. . . . In all cases affecting ambassadors, other<br />

public ministers and consuls, and those in which a state shall be party,<br />

the Supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction. In all the other<br />

cases before mentioned, the Supreme Court shall have appellate<br />

jurisdiction, both as to law and fact, with such exceptions, and under<br />

such regulations as the Congress shall make.<br />

”<br />

Page 44 of 115


The Supremacy Clause of Article VI states:<br />

“<br />

This<br />

Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be<br />

made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be<br />

made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme<br />

Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound<br />

thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the<br />

Contrary notwithstanding. . . . [A]ll executive and judicial Officers,<br />

both of the United States and of the several States, shall be bound by<br />

Oath or Affirmation, to support this Constitution.<br />

”<br />

The power of judicial review has been implied from these provisions based on the following<br />

reasoning. It is the inherent duty of the courts to determine the applicable law in any given case.<br />

The Supremacy Clause says "[t]his Constitution" is the "supreme law of the land." The<br />

Constitution therefore is the fundamental law of the United States. Federal statutes are the law of<br />

the land only when they are "made in pursuance" of the Constitution. State constitutions and<br />

statutes are valid only if they are consistent with the Constitution. Any law contrary to the<br />

Constitution is void. The federal judicial power extends to all cases "arising under this<br />

Constitution." As part of their inherent duty to determine the law, the federal courts have the<br />

duty to interpret and apply the Constitution and to decide whether a federal or state statute<br />

conflicts with the Constitution. All judges are bound to follow the Constitution. If there is a<br />

conflict, the federal courts have a duty to follow the Constitution and to treat the conflicting<br />

statute as unenforceable. The Supreme Court has final appellate jurisdiction in all cases arising<br />

under the Constitution, so the Supreme Court has the ultimate authority to decide whether<br />

statutes are consistent with the Constitution.<br />

The Constitutional Convention<br />

During the debates at the Constitutional Convention, the Founding Fathers made a number of<br />

references to the concept of judicial review. The greatest number of these references occurred<br />

during the discussion of the proposal known as the Virginia Plan. The Virginia Plan included a<br />

"council of revision" that would have examined proposed new federal laws and would have<br />

accepted or rejected them, similar to today's presidential veto. The "council of revision" would<br />

have included the President along with some federal judges. Several delegates objected to the<br />

inclusion of federal judges on the council of revision. They argued the federal judiciary, through<br />

its power to declare laws unconstitutional, already had the opportunity to protect against<br />

legislative encroachment, and the judiciary did not need a second way to negate laws by<br />

participating in the council of revision. For example, Elbridge Gerry said federal judges "would<br />

have a sufficient check against encroachments on their own department by their exposition of the<br />

laws, which involved a power of deciding on their constitutionality. In some states the judges<br />

had actually set aside laws, as being against the constitution. This was done too with general<br />

approbation." Luther Martin said: "[A]s to the constitutionality of laws, that point will come<br />

before the judges in their official character. In this character they have a negative on the laws.<br />

Join them with the executive in the revision, and they will have a double negative." These and<br />

Page 45 of 115


other similar comments by the delegates indicated that the federal courts would have the power<br />

of judicial review.<br />

Other delegates argued that if federal judges were involved in the law-making process through<br />

participation on the council of revision, their objectivity as judges in later deciding on the<br />

constitutionality of those laws could be impaired. These comments indicated a belief that the<br />

federal courts would have the power to declare laws unconstitutional.<br />

At several other points in the debates at the Constitutional Convention, delegates made<br />

comments indicating their belief that under the Constitution, federal judges would have the<br />

power of judicial review. For example, George Mason said that federal judges "could declare an<br />

unconstitutional law void." James Madison said: "A law violating a constitution established by<br />

the people themselves, would be considered by the Judges as null & void."<br />

In all, fifteen delegates from nine states made comments regarding the power of the federal<br />

courts to review the constitutionality of laws. All but two of them supported the idea that the<br />

federal courts would have the power of judicial review. Some delegates to the Constitutional<br />

Convention did not speak about judicial review during the Convention, but did speak about it<br />

before or after the Convention. Including these additional comments by Convention delegates,<br />

scholars have found that twenty-five or twenty-six of the Convention delegates made comments<br />

indicating support for judicial review, while three to six delegates opposed judicial review. One<br />

review of the debates and voting records of the convention counted as many as forty delegates<br />

who supported judicial review, with four or five opposed.<br />

In their comments relating to judicial review, the framers indicated that the power of judges to<br />

declare laws unconstitutional was part of the system of separation of powers. The framers stated<br />

that the courts' power to declare laws unconstitutional would provide a check on the legislature,<br />

protecting against excessive exercise of legislative power.<br />

The State Ratification Debates<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review was discussed in at least seven of the thirteen state ratifying conventions, and<br />

was mentioned by almost two dozen delegates. In each of these conventions, delegates asserted<br />

that the proposed Constitution would allow the courts to exercise judicial review. There is no<br />

record of any delegate to a state ratifying convention who indicated that the federal courts would<br />

not have the power of judicial review.<br />

For example, James Wilson asserted in the Pennsylvania ratifying convention that federal judges<br />

would exercise judicial review: "If a law should be made inconsistent with those powers vested<br />

by this instrument in Congress, the judges, as a consequence of their independence, and the<br />

particular powers of government being defined, will declare such law to be null and void. For the<br />

power of the Constitution predominates. Anything, therefore, that shall be enacted by Congress<br />

contrary thereto will not have the force of law."<br />

In the Connecticut ratifying convention, Oliver Ellsworth likewise described judicial review as a<br />

feature of the Constitution: "This Constitution defines the extent of the powers of the general<br />

Page 46 of 115


government. If the general legislature should at any time overleap their limits, the judicial<br />

department is a constitutional check. If the United States go beyond their powers, if they make a<br />

law which the Constitution does not authorize, it is void; and the judicial power, the national<br />

judges, who, to secure their impartiality, are to be made independent, will declare it to be void."<br />

During the ratification process, supporters and opponents of ratification published pamphlets,<br />

essays, and speeches debating various aspects of the Constitution. Publications by over a dozen<br />

authors in at least twelve of the thirteen states asserted that under the Constitution, the federal<br />

courts would have the power of judicial review. There is no record of any opponent to the<br />

Constitution who claimed that the Constitution did not involve a power of judicial review.<br />

After reviewing the statements made by the founders, one scholar concluded: "The evidence<br />

from the Constitutional Convention and from the state ratification conventions is overwhelming<br />

that the original public meaning of the term 'judicial power' [in Article III] included the power to<br />

nullify unconstitutional laws."<br />

The Federalist Papers<br />

The Federalist Papers, which were published in 1787–1788 to promote ratification of the<br />

Constitution, made several references to the power of judicial review. The most extensive<br />

discussion of judicial review was in Federalist No. 78, written by Alexander Hamilton, which<br />

clearly explained that the federal courts would have the power of judicial review. Hamilton<br />

stated that under the Constitution, the federal judiciary would have the power to declare laws<br />

unconstitutional. Hamilton asserted that this was appropriate because it would protect the people<br />

against abuse of power by Congress:<br />

“<br />

[T]he<br />

courts were designed to be an intermediate body between the<br />

people and the legislature, in order, among other things, to keep the<br />

latter within the limits assigned to their authority. The interpretation<br />

of the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts. A<br />

constitution is, in fact, and must be regarded by the judges, as a<br />

fundamental law. It therefore belongs to them to ascertain its<br />

meaning, as well as the meaning of any particular act proceeding<br />

from the legislative body. If there should happen to be an<br />

irreconcilable variance between the two, that which has the superior<br />

obligation and validity ought, of course, to be preferred; or, in other<br />

words, the Constitution ought to be preferred to the statute, the<br />

intention of the people to the intention of their agents.<br />

Nor does this conclusion by any means suppose a superiority of the<br />

judicial to the legislative power. It only supposes that the power of<br />

the people is superior to both; and that where the will of the<br />

legislature, declared in its statutes, stands in opposition to that of the<br />

people, declared in the Constitution, the judges ought to be governed<br />

”<br />

Page 47 of 115


y the latter rather than the former. They ought to regulate their<br />

decisions by the fundamental laws, rather than by those which are not<br />

fundamental....<br />

[A]ccordingly, whenever a particular statute contravenes the<br />

Constitution, it will be the duty of the <strong>Judicial</strong> tribunals to adhere to<br />

the latter and disregard the former....<br />

[T]he courts of justice are to be considered as the bulwarks of a<br />

limited Constitution against legislative encroachments.<br />

In Federalist No. 80, Hamilton rejected the idea that the power to decide the constitutionality of<br />

an act of Congress should lie with each of the states: "The mere necessity of uniformity in the<br />

interpretation of the national laws, decides the question. Thirteen independent courts of final<br />

jurisdiction over the same causes, arising upon the same laws, is a hydra in government, from<br />

which nothing but contradiction and confusion can proceed." Consistent with the need for<br />

uniformity in interpretation of the Constitution, Hamilton explained in Federalist No. 82 that the<br />

Supreme Court has authority to hear appeals from the state courts in cases relating to the<br />

Constitution.<br />

The arguments against ratification by the Anti-Federalists agreed that the federal courts would<br />

have the power of judicial review, though the Anti-Federalists viewed this negatively. Robert<br />

Yates, writing under the pseudonym "Brutus", stated:<br />

“<br />

[T]he<br />

judges under this constitution will control the legislature, for the supreme<br />

court are authorised in the last resort, to determine what is the extent of the powers<br />

of the Congress. They are to give the constitution an explanation, and there is no<br />

power above them to set aside their judgment. . . . The supreme court then have a<br />

right, independent of the legislature, to give a construction to the constitution and<br />

every part of it, and there is no power provided in this system to correct their<br />

construction or do it away. If, therefore, the legislature pass any laws, inconsistent<br />

with the sense the judges put upon the constitution, they will declare it void.<br />

The Judiciary Act of 1789<br />

The first Congress passed the Judiciary Act of 1789, establishing the lower federal courts and<br />

specifying the details of federal court jurisdiction. Section 25 of the Judiciary Act provided for<br />

the Supreme Court to hear appeals from state courts when the state court decided that a federal<br />

statute was invalid, or when the state court upheld a state statute against a claim that the state<br />

statute was repugnant to the Constitution. This provision gave the Supreme Court the power to<br />

Page 48 of 115


eview state court decisions involving the constitutionality of both federal statutes and state<br />

statutes. The Judiciary Act thereby incorporated the concept of judicial review.<br />

Court Decisions from 1788 to 1803<br />

Between the ratification of the Constitution in 1788 and the decision in<br />

Marbury<br />

v. Madison in 1803, judicial review was employed in both<br />

the<br />

federal and state courts. A detailed analysis has identified<br />

thirty-<br />

one state or federal cases during this time in which<br />

statutes were struck down as unconstitutional, and seven<br />

additional cases in which statutes were upheld but at<br />

least one judge concluded the statute was<br />

unconstitutional. The author of this analysis,<br />

Professor William Treanor, concluded: "The sheer<br />

number of these decisions not only belies the<br />

notion that the institution of judicial review was<br />

created by Chief Justice Marshall in Marbury, it<br />

also reflects widespread acceptance and<br />

application of the doctrine."<br />

Several other cases involving judicial review issues reached the Supreme Court before the issue<br />

was definitively decided in Marbury in 1803.<br />

In Hayburn's Case, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 408 (1792), federal circuit courts held an act of Congress<br />

unconstitutional for the first time. Three federal circuit courts found that Congress had violated<br />

the Constitution by passing an act requiring circuit court judges to decide pension applications,<br />

subject to the review of the Secretary of War. These circuit courts found that this was not a<br />

proper judicial function under Article III. These three decisions were appealed to the Supreme<br />

Court, but the appeals became moot when Congress repealed the statute while the appeals were<br />

pending.<br />

In an unreported Supreme Court decision in 1794, United States v. Yale Todd, the Supreme Court<br />

reversed a pension that was awarded under the same pension act that had been at issue in<br />

Hayburn's Case. The Court apparently decided that the act designating judges to decide pensions<br />

was not constitutional because this was not a proper judicial function. This apparently was the<br />

first Supreme Court case to find an act of Congress unconstitutional. However, there was not an<br />

official report of the case and it was not used as a precedent.<br />

Hylton v. United States, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 171 (1796), was the first case decided by the Supreme<br />

Court that involved a challenge to the constitutionality of an act of Congress. It was argued that a<br />

federal tax on carriages violated the constitutional provision regarding "direct" taxes. The<br />

Supreme Court upheld the tax, finding it was constitutional. Although the Supreme Court did not<br />

strike down the act in question, the Court engaged in the process of judicial review by<br />

considering the constitutionality of the tax. The case was widely publicized at the time, and<br />

observers understood that the Court was testing the constitutionality of an act of Congress.<br />

Page 49 of 115


Because it found the statute valid, the Court did not have to assert that it had the power to declare<br />

a statute unconstitutional.<br />

In Ware v. Hylton, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 199 (1796), the Supreme Court for the first time struck down<br />

a state statute. The Court reviewed a Virginia statute regarding pre-Revolutionary war debts and<br />

found that it was inconsistent with the peace treaty between the United States and Great Britain.<br />

Relying on the Supremacy Clause, the Court found the Virginia statute invalid.<br />

In Hollingsworth v. Virginia, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 378 (1798), the Supreme Court found that it did not<br />

have jurisdiction to hear the case because of the jurisdiction limitations of the Eleventh<br />

Amendment. This holding could be viewed as an implicit finding that the Judiciary Act of 1789,<br />

which would have allowed the Court jurisdiction, was unconstitutional in part. However, the<br />

Court did not provide any reasoning for its conclusion and did not say that it was finding the<br />

statute unconstitutional.<br />

In Cooper v. Telfair, 4 U.S. (4 Dall.) 14 (1800), Justice Chase stated: "It is indeed a general<br />

opinion—it is expressly admitted by all this bar and some of the judges have, individually in the<br />

circuits decided, that the Supreme Court can declare an act of Congress to be unconstitutional,<br />

and therefore invalid, but there is no adjudication of the Supreme Court itself upon the point."<br />

Responses to the Kentucky and Virginia Resolutions<br />

In 1798, the Kentucky and Virginia legislatures passed a series of resolutions asserting that the<br />

states have the power to determine whether acts of Congress are constitutional. In response, ten<br />

states passed their own resolutions disapproving the Kentucky and Virginia resolutions. Six of<br />

these states took the position that the power to declare acts of Congress unconstitutional lies in<br />

the federal courts, not in the state legislatures. For example, Vermont's resolution stated: "It<br />

belongs not to state legislatures to decide on the constitutionality of laws made by the general<br />

government; this power being exclusively vested in the judiciary courts of the Union."<br />

Thus, five years before Marbury v. Madison, a number of state legislatures stated their<br />

understanding that under the Constitution, the federal courts possess the power of judicial<br />

review.<br />

Marbury v. Madison<br />

The Supreme Court's landmark decision regarding judicial review is Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S.<br />

(1 Cranch) 137 (1803). Marbury was the first Supreme Court decision to strike down an act of<br />

Congress as unconstitutional. Chief Justice John Marshall wrote the opinion for a unanimous<br />

Court.<br />

The case arose when William Marbury filed a lawsuit seeking an order (a "writ of mandamus")<br />

requiring the Secretary of State, James Madison, to deliver to Marbury a commission appointing<br />

him as a justice of the peace. Marbury filed his case directly in the Supreme Court, invoking the<br />

Court's "original jurisdiction", rather than filing in a lower court.<br />

Page 50 of 115


The constitutional issue involved the question of whether the Supreme Court had jurisdiction to<br />

hear the case. The Judiciary Act of 1789 gave the Supreme Court original jurisdiction in cases<br />

involving writs of mandamus. So, under the Judiciary Act, the Supreme Court would have had<br />

jurisdiction to hear Marbury's case. However, the Constitution describes the cases in which the<br />

Supreme Court has original jurisdiction, and does not include mandamus cases. The Judiciary<br />

Act therefore attempted to give the Supreme Court jurisdiction that was not "warranted by the<br />

Constitution."<br />

Marshall's opinion stated that in the Constitution, the people established a government of limited<br />

powers: "The powers of the Legislature are defined and limited; and that those limits may not be<br />

mistaken or forgotten, the Constitution is written." The limits established in the Constitution<br />

would be meaningless "if these limits may at any time be passed by those intended to be<br />

restrained." Marshall observed that the Constitution is "the fundamental and paramount law of<br />

the nation", and that it cannot be altered by an ordinary act of the legislature. Therefore, "an act<br />

of the Legislature repugnant to the Constitution is void."<br />

Marshall then discussed the role of the courts, which is at the heart of the doctrine of judicial<br />

review. It would be an "absurdity", said Marshall, to require the courts to apply a law that is<br />

void. Rather, it is the inherent duty of the courts to interpret and apply the Constitution, and to<br />

determine whether there is a conflict between a statute and the Constitution:<br />

“<br />

It<br />

is emphatically the province and duty of the <strong>Judicial</strong> Department to<br />

say what the law is. Those who apply the rule to particular cases<br />

must, of necessity, expound and interpret that rule. If two laws<br />

conflict with each other, the Courts must decide on the operation of<br />

each.<br />

So, if a law be in opposition to the Constitution, if both the law and<br />

the Constitution apply to a particular case, so that the Court must<br />

either decide that case conformably to the law, disregarding the<br />

Constitution, or conformably to the Constitution, disregarding the<br />

law, the Court must determine which of these conflicting rules<br />

governs the case. This is of the very essence of judicial duty.<br />

If, then, the Courts are to regard the Constitution, and the<br />

Constitution is superior to any ordinary act of the Legislature, the<br />

Constitution, and not such ordinary act, must govern the case to<br />

which they both apply....<br />

”<br />

Marshall stated that the courts are authorized by the provisions of the Constitution itself to "look<br />

into" the Constitution, that is, to interpret and apply it, and that they have the duty to refuse to<br />

enforce any laws that are contrary to the Constitution. Specifically, Article III provides that the<br />

federal judicial power "is extended to all cases arising under the Constitution." Article VI<br />

requires judges to take an oath "to support this Constitution." Article VI also states that only laws<br />

Page 51 of 115


"made in pursuance of the Constitution" are the law of the land. Marshall concluded: "Thus, the<br />

particular phraseology of the Constitution of the United States confirms and strengthens the<br />

principle, supposed to be essential to all written Constitutions, that a law repugnant to the<br />

Constitution is void, and that courts, as well as other departments, are bound by that instrument."<br />

Marbury long has been regarded as the seminal case with respect to the doctrine of judicial<br />

review. Some scholars have suggested that Marshall's opinion in Marbury essentially created<br />

judicial review. In his book The Least Dangerous Branch, Professor Alexander Bickel wrote:<br />

“<br />

[T]he<br />

institution of the judiciary needed to be summoned up out of<br />

the constitutional vapors, shaped, and maintained. And the Great<br />

Chief Justice, John Marshall—not single-handed, but first and<br />

foremost—was there to do it and did. If any social process can be said<br />

to have been 'done' at a given time, and by a given act, it is Marshall's<br />

achievement. The time was 1803; the act was the decision in the case<br />

of Marbury v. Madison.<br />

”<br />

Other scholars view this as an overstatement, and argue that Marbury was decided in a context in<br />

which judicial review already was a familiar concept. These scholars point to the facts showing<br />

that judicial review was acknowledged by the Constitution's framers, was explained in the<br />

Federalist Papers and in the ratification debates, and was used by both state and federal courts for<br />

more than twenty years before Marbury, including the Supreme Court in Hylton v. United States.<br />

One scholar concluded: "[B]efore Marbury, judicial review had gained wide support."<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review Post Marbury<br />

After the Court exercised its power of judicial review in Marbury, it avoided striking down a<br />

federal statute during the next fifty years. The court would not do so again until Dred Scott v.<br />

Sandford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393 (1857).<br />

However, the Supreme Court did exercise judicial review in other contexts. In particular, the<br />

Court struck down a number of state statutes that were contrary to the Constitution. The first case<br />

in which the Supreme Court struck down a state statute as unconstitutional was Fletcher v. Peck,<br />

10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87 (1810).<br />

In a few cases, state courts took the position that their judgments were final and were not subject<br />

to review by the Supreme Court. They argued that the Constitution did not give the Supreme<br />

Court the authority to review state court decisions. They asserted that the Judiciary Act of 1789,<br />

which provided that the Supreme Court could hear certain appeals from state courts, was<br />

unconstitutional. In effect, these state courts were asserting that the principle of judicial review<br />

did not extend to allow federal review of state court decisions. This would have left the states<br />

free to adopt their own interpretations of the Constitution.<br />

Page 52 of 115


The Supreme Court rejected this argument. In Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304<br />

(1816), the Court held that under Article III, the federal courts have jurisdiction to hear all cases<br />

arising under the Constitution and laws of the United States, and that the Supreme Court has<br />

appellate jurisdiction in all such cases, whether those cases are filed in state or federal courts.<br />

The Court issued another decision to the same effect in the context of a criminal case, Cohens v.<br />

Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264 (1821). It is now well established that the Supreme Court may<br />

review decisions of state courts that involve federal law.<br />

The Supreme Court also has reviewed actions of the federal executive branch to determine<br />

whether those actions were authorized by acts of Congress or were beyond the authority granted<br />

by Congress.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review is now well established as a cornerstone of constitutional law. As of 2014, the<br />

United States Supreme Court had held unconstitutional some 176 Acts of the U.S. Congress.<br />

Although judicial review has now become an established part of constitutional law in the United<br />

States, there are some who disagree with the doctrine.<br />

At the Constitutional Convention, neither proponents nor opponents of judicial review disputed<br />

that any government based on a written constitution requires some mechanism to prevent laws<br />

that violate that constitution from being made and enforced. Otherwise, the document would be<br />

meaningless, and the legislature, with the power to enact any laws whatsoever, would be the<br />

supreme arm of government (the British doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty). The delegates at<br />

the Convention differed with respect to the question of whether Congress or the judiciary should<br />

make determinations regarding constitutionality of statutes. Hamilton addressed this in Federalist<br />

No. 78, in which he explained the reasons that the federal judiciary has the role of reviewing the<br />

constitutionality of statutes:<br />

“<br />

If<br />

it be said that the legislative body are themselves the constitutional<br />

judges of their own powers, and that the construction they put upon<br />

them is conclusive upon the other departments, it may be answered,<br />

that this cannot be the natural presumption, where it is not to be<br />

collected from any particular provisions in the Constitution. It is not<br />

otherwise to be supposed, that the Constitution could intend to enable<br />

the representatives of the people to substitute their will to that of their<br />

constituents. It is far more rational to suppose, that the courts were<br />

designed to be an intermediate body between the people and the<br />

legislature, in order, among other things, to keep the latter within the<br />

limits assigned to their authority.<br />

”<br />

Since the adoption of the Constitution, some have argued that the power of judicial review gives<br />

the courts the ability to impose their own views of the law, without an adequate check from any<br />

other branch of government. Robert Yates, a delegate to the Constitutional Convention from<br />

New York, argued during the ratification process in the Anti-Federalist Papers that the courts<br />

Page 53 of 115


would use the power of judicial review loosely to impose their views about the "spirit" of the<br />

Constitution:<br />

“<br />

[I]n<br />

their decisions they will not confine themselves to any fixed or<br />

established rules, but will determine, according to what appears to<br />

them, the reason and spirit of the constitution. The opinions of the<br />

supreme court, whatever they may be, will have the force of law;<br />

because there is no power provided in the constitution, that can<br />

correct their errors, or controul their adjudications. From this court<br />

there is no appeal.<br />

”<br />

In 1820, Thomas Jefferson expressed his opposition to the doctrine of judicial review:<br />

“<br />

You<br />

seem ... to consider the judges as the ultimate arbiters of all<br />

constitutional questions; a very dangerous doctrine indeed, and one<br />

which would place us under the despotism of an oligarchy. Our<br />

judges are as honest as other men, and not more so. They have, with<br />

others, the same passions for party, for power, and the privilege of<br />

their corps.... Their power [is] the more dangerous as they are in<br />

office for life, and not responsible, as the other functionaries are, to<br />

the elective control. The Constitution has erected no such single<br />

tribunal, knowing that to whatever hands confided, with the<br />

corruptions of time and party, its members would become despots. It<br />

has more wisely made all the departments co-equal and co-sovereign<br />

within themselves.<br />

”<br />

In 1861, Abraham Lincoln touched upon the same subject, during his first inaugural address:<br />

“<br />

[T]he<br />

candid citizen must confess that if the policy of the<br />

Government upon vital questions affecting the whole people is to be<br />

irrevocably fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court, the instant they<br />

are made in ordinary litigation between parties in personal actions the<br />

people will have ceased to be their own rulers, having to that extent<br />

practically resigned their Government into the hands of that eminent<br />

tribunal. Nor is there in this view any assault upon the court or the<br />

judges. It is a duty from which they may not shrink to decide cases<br />

properly brought before them, and it is no fault of theirs if others seek<br />

to turn their decisions to political purposes.<br />

”<br />

Page 54 of 115


Lincoln was alluding here to the case of Dred Scott v. Sandford, in which the Court had struck<br />

down a federal statute for the first time since Marbury v. Madison.<br />

It has been argued that the judiciary is not the only branch of government that may interpret the<br />

meaning of the Constitution. Article VI requires federal and state officeholders to be bound "by<br />

Oath or Affirmation, to support this Constitution." It has been argued that such officials may<br />

follow their own interpretations of the Constitution, at least until those interpretations have been<br />

tested in court.<br />

Some have argued that judicial review is unconstitutional. See W.W. Crosskey, Politics and the<br />

Constitution in the History of the United States (Chicago: 1953), chs. 27-29, with which compare<br />

Hart, Book Review, 67 Harv. L. Rev. 1456 (1954). A brief review of the debate on the subject is<br />

Westin, Introduction: Charles Beard and American Debate over <strong>Judicial</strong> Review, 1790-1961, in<br />

C. Beard, The Supreme Court and the Constitution (Englewood Cliffs: 1962 reissue of 1938 ed.),<br />

1-34, and bibliography at 133-149. See more at:<br />

http://constitution.findlaw.com/article3/annotation13.html#f576<br />

This theory is generally based on two arguments. First, the power of judicial review is not<br />

expressly delegated to the courts in the Constitution. The Tenth Amendment reserves to the<br />

states (or to the people) those powers not delegated to the federal government. The second<br />

argument is that the states alone have the power to ratify changes to the "supreme law" (the U.S.<br />

Constitution), and that the states should play some role in interpreting its meaning. Under this<br />

theory, allowing only federal courts to definitively conduct judicial review of federal law allows<br />

the national government to interpret its own restrictions as it sees fit, with no meaningful input<br />

from the ratifying power.<br />

The Contemporary Standard<br />

In the United States, unconstitutionality is the only ground for a federal court to strike down a<br />

federal statute. Justice Washington, speaking for the Marshall Court, put it this way in an 1829<br />

case:<br />

“<br />

We<br />

intend to decide no more than that the statute objected to in this<br />

case is not repugnant to the Constitution of the United States, and that<br />

unless it be so, this Court has no authority, under the 25th section of<br />

the judiciary act, to re-examine and to reverse the judgement of the<br />

supreme court of Pennsylvania in the present case.<br />

”<br />

If a state statute conflicts with a valid federal statute, then courts may strike down the state<br />

statute as an unstatutable violation of the Supremacy Clause. But a federal court may not strike<br />

down a statute absent a violation of federal law or of the federal Constitution.<br />

Page 55 of 115


Moreover, a suspicion or possibility of unconstitutionality is not enough for American<br />

courts to strike down a statute. Alexander Hamilton explained in Federalist<br />

78 that the standard of review should be "irreconcilable variance" with the<br />

Constitution. Anti-federalists agreed that courts would be unable to strike<br />

down federal statutes absent a conflict<br />

with the Constitution.<br />

For example, Robert Yates, writing under the<br />

pseudonym "Brutus", asserted that<br />

"the courts of the<br />

general government [will] be<br />

under obligation<br />

to observe the laws made by the<br />

general<br />

legislature not repugnant to<br />

the<br />

constitution."<br />

These<br />

principles—that<br />

federal statutes can only be<br />

struck down for<br />

unconstitutionality<br />

and that the unconstitutionality<br />

must be clear—<br />

were very common<br />

views at the time of<br />

the framing of the<br />

Constitution. For example, George Mason<br />

explained during the constitutional convention<br />

that judges "could declare<br />

an unconstitutional law void.<br />

But with regard to every law, however unjust, oppressive or<br />

pernicious, which did not come plainly under this description, they would be under the necessity<br />

as Judges to give it a free course."<br />

For a number of years, the courts were relatively deferential to Congress. Justice Washington put<br />

it this way, in an 1827 case: "It is but a decent respect to the wisdom, integrity, and patriotism of<br />

the legislative body, by which any law is passed, to presume in favor of its validity, until its<br />

violation of the Constitution is proved beyond a reasonable doubt."<br />

Although judges usually adhered to this principle that a statute could only be deemed<br />

unconstitutional in case of a clear contradiction until the twentieth century, this presumption of<br />

constitutionality weakened somewhat during the twentieth century, as exemplified by the<br />

Supreme Court's famous footnote four in United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144<br />

(1938), which suggested that statutes may be subjected to closer scrutiny in certain types of<br />

cases. Nevertheless, the federal courts have not departed from the principle that courts may only<br />

strike down statutes for unconstitutionality.<br />

Page 56 of 115


Of course, the practical implication of this principle is that a court cannot strike down a statute,<br />

even if it recognizes that the statute is obviously poorly drafted, irrational, or arises from<br />

legislators' corrupt motives, unless the flaw in the statute rises to the level of a clear<br />

constitutional violation. In 2008, Justice John Paul Stevens reaffirmed this point in a concurring<br />

opinion: "[A]s I recall my esteemed former colleague, Thurgood Marshall, remarking on<br />

numerous occasions: 'The Constitution does not prohibit legislatures from enacting stupid laws.'"<br />

In the federal system, courts may only decide actual cases or controversies; it is not possible to<br />

request the federal courts to review a law without at least one party having legal standing to<br />

engage in a lawsuit. This principle means that courts sometimes do not exercise their power of<br />

review, even when a law is seemingly unconstitutional, for want of jurisdiction. In some state<br />

courts, such as the Massachusetts Supreme <strong>Judicial</strong> Court, legislation may be referred in certain<br />

circumstances by the legislature or by the executive for an advisory ruling on its constitutionality<br />

prior to its enactment (or enforcement).<br />

The U.S. Supreme Court seeks to avoid reviewing the Constitutionality of an act where the case<br />

before it could be decided on other grounds. Justice Brandeis framed it thus (citations omitted):<br />

“<br />

The<br />

Court developed, for its own governance in the cases within its jurisdiction, a<br />

series of rules under which it has avoided passing upon a large part of all the<br />

constitutional questions pressed upon it for decision. They are:<br />

1. The Court will not pass upon the constitutionality of legislation in a<br />

friendly, non-adversary, proceeding, declining because to decide such<br />

questions is legitimate only in the last resort, and as a necessity in the<br />

determination of real, earnest, and vital controversy between individuals. It<br />

never was the thought that, by means of a friendly suit, a party beaten in the<br />

legislature could transfer to the courts an inquiry as to the constitutionality<br />

of the legislative act.<br />

2. The Court will not anticipate a question of constitutional law in advance of<br />

the necessity of deciding it. It is not the habit of the court to decide<br />

questions of a constitutional nature unless absolutely necessary to a<br />

decision of the case.<br />

3. The Court will not formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than<br />

required by the precise facts it applies to.<br />

4. The Court will not pass upon a constitutional question although properly<br />

presented by the record, if there is also present some other ground upon<br />

which the case may be disposed of… If a case can be decided on either of<br />

two grounds, one involving a constitutional question, the other a question of<br />

statutory construction or general law, the Court will decide only the latter.<br />

5. The Court will not pass upon the validity of a statute upon complaint of one<br />

who fails to show that he is injured by its operation.<br />

6. The Court will not pass upon the constitutionality of a statute at the instance<br />

of one who has availed himself of its benefits.<br />

Page 57 of 115


7. When the validity of an act of the Congress is drawn in question, and even<br />

if a serious doubt of constitutionality is raised, it is a cardinal principle that<br />

this Court will first ascertain whether a construction of the statute is fairly<br />

possible by which the question may be avoided.<br />

Statutory Limitations<br />

Although the Supreme Court continues to review the constitutionality of statutes, Congress and<br />

the states retain some power to influence what cases come before the Court. For example, the<br />

Constitution at Article III, Section 2, gives Congress power to make exceptions to the Supreme<br />

Court's appellate jurisdiction. The Supreme Court has historically acknowledged that its<br />

appellate jurisdiction is defined by Congress, and thus Congress may have power to make some<br />

legislative or executive actions unreviewable. This is known as jurisdiction stripping.<br />

Another way for Congress to limit judicial review was tried in January 1868, when a bill was<br />

proposed requiring a two-thirds majority of the Court in order to deem any Act of Congress<br />

unconstitutional. The bill was approved by the House, 116 to 39. [67] That measure died in the<br />

Senate, partly because the bill was unclear about how the bill's own constitutionality would be<br />

decided. [68]<br />

Many other bills have been proposed in Congress that would require a supermajority in order for<br />

the justices to exercise judicial review. [69] During the early years of the United States, a twothirds<br />

majority was necessary for the Supreme Court to exercise judicial review; because the<br />

Court then consisted of six members, a simple majority and a two-thirds majority both required<br />

four votes. [70] Currently, the constitutions of two states require a supermajority of supreme court<br />

justices in order to exercise judicial review: Nebraska (five out of seven justices) and North<br />

Dakota (four out of five justices).<br />

In The Soviet Union<br />

In modern Russia, aspects and directions of development of judicial reform were formulated in<br />

the «<strong>Judicial</strong> Reform Concept», enacted by the Russian Parliament on October 24, 1991. This<br />

document still remains legally valid and applicable.<br />

Valery Zorkin stressed that "the «separation of powers» principle, also proclaimed in the<br />

Constitution of the Russian Federation, requires observance of judicial independence. And such<br />

independence requires proper funding of the courts and their activities. It is well known that<br />

Russian courts remain under-funded. However, the cumulative economic costs suffered by both<br />

state and private enterprises as the result of under-performance by various judicial institutions,<br />

especially by the courts of general jurisdiction and the arbitration courts, is at least twice the<br />

order of magnitude as the financial burden carried by the state and society in financing such<br />

judicial institutions. The elimination of under-funding of the courts would definitely improve the<br />

efficiency of their work and be worthwhile.<br />

Page 58 of 115


Taking into account the specifics of historical developments in Russia, one may assert that<br />

without undertaking a large-scale legal reform it would be extremely difficult to succeed<br />

concurrently with judicial reform. It is necessary now to start unfolding a full-scale legal reform,<br />

which has to be completed by the year 2020. The official public presentation and implementation<br />

of such legal reform should become the prime responsibility of executive and legislative<br />

authorities. The program of legal reform needs to be adopted in the form of a legislative act.<br />

Page 59 of 115


Page 60 of 115


Rule of Law<br />

The Rule of Law (also known as Nomocracy) is the legal<br />

principle that law should govern a nation, as opposed to<br />

arbitrary decisions by individual government officials. It<br />

primarily refers to the influence and authority of law within<br />

society, particularly as a constraint upon behavior, including<br />

behavior of government officials. The phrase can be traced<br />

back to 16th century England, and it was popularized in the<br />

19th century by British jurist A. V. Dicey. The concept was<br />

familiar to ancient philosophers such as Aristotle, who wrote<br />

"Law should govern".<br />

Rule of law implies that every citizen is subject to the law,<br />

including law makers themselves. In this sense, it stands in<br />

contrast to an autocracy, collective leadership, dictatorship,<br />

or oligarchy where the rulers are held above the law (which<br />

is not necessary by definition but which is typical). Lack of<br />

the rule of law can be found in democracies and dictatorships, and can happen because of neglect<br />

or ignorance of the law, corruption, or lack of corrective mechanisms for administrative abuse,<br />

such as an independent judiciary with a rule-of-law culture, a practical right to petition for<br />

redress of grievances, or elections.<br />

Although credit for popularizing the expression "the rule of law" in modern times is usually<br />

given to A. V. Dicey, development of the legal concept can be traced through history to many<br />

ancient civilizations, including ancient Greece, China, Mesopotamia, India and Rome.<br />

Antiquity<br />

In the West, the ancient Greeks initially regarded the best form of government as rule by the best<br />

men. Plato advocated a benevolent monarchy ruled by an idealized philosopher king, who was<br />

above the law. Plato nevertheless hoped that the best men would be good at respecting<br />

established laws, explaining that "Where the law is subject to some other authority and has none<br />

of its own, the collapse of the state, in my view, is not far off; but if law is the master of the<br />

government and the government is its slave, then the situation is full of promise and men enjoy<br />

all the blessings that the gods shower on a state." More than Plato attempted to do, Aristotle<br />

flatly opposed letting the highest officials wield power beyond guarding and serving the laws. In<br />

other words, Aristotle advocated the rule of law:<br />

It is more proper that law should govern than any one of the citizens: upon the same principle, if<br />

it is advantageous to place the supreme power in some particular persons, they should be<br />

appointed to be only guardians, and the servants of the laws.<br />

Page 61 of 115


According to the Roman statesman Cicero, "We are all servants of the laws in order that we may<br />

be free." During the Roman Republic, controversial magistrates might be put on trial when their<br />

terms of office expired. Under the Roman Empire, the sovereign was personally immune<br />

(legibus solutus), but those with grievances could sue the treasury.<br />

In China, members of the school of legalism during the 3rd century BC argued for using law as a<br />

tool of governance, but they promoted "rule by law" as opposed to "rule of law", meaning that<br />

they placed the aristocrats and emperor above the law. In contrast, the Huang-Lao school of<br />

Daoism rejected legal positivism in favor of a natural law that even the ruler would be subject to.<br />

There has recently been an effort to reevaluate the influence of the Bible on Western<br />

constitutional law. In the Old Testament, there was some language in Deuteronomy imposing<br />

restrictions on the Jewish king, regarding such things as how many wives he could have, and<br />

how many horses he could own for his personal use. According to Professor Bernard M.<br />

Levinson, "This legislation was so utopian in its own time that it seems never to have been<br />

implemented...." The Deuteronomic social vision may have influenced opponents of the divine<br />

right of kings, including Bishop John Ponet in sixteenth-century England.<br />

Middle Ages<br />

In Islamic jurisprudence rule of law was formulated in the seventh century, so that no official<br />

could claim to be above the law, not even the caliph. However, this was not a reference to<br />

secular law, but to Islamic religious law in the form of Sharia law.<br />

In 1215, Archbishop Stephen Langton gathered the Barons in England and forced King John and<br />

future sovereigns and magistrates back under the rule of law, preserving ancient liberties by the<br />

Magna Carta in return for exacting taxes. This foundation for constitution was carried into the<br />

Constitution of the United States.<br />

Early Modern Period<br />

The first known use of this English phrase occurred around 1500 A.D. Another early example of<br />

the phrase "rule of law" is found in a petition to James I of England in 1610, from the House of<br />

Commons:<br />

Amongst many other points of happiness and freedom which your majesty's subjects of this<br />

kingdom have enjoyed under your royal progenitors, kings and queens of this realm, there is<br />

none which they have accounted more dear and precious than this, to be guided and governed by<br />

the certain rule of the law which giveth both to the head and members that which of right<br />

belongeth to them, and not by any uncertain or arbitrary form of government....<br />

Page 62 of 115


In 1607, English Chief Justice<br />

Sir Edward Coke said in the<br />

Case of Prohibitions (according<br />

to his own report) "that the law<br />

was the golden met-wand and<br />

measure to try the causes of the<br />

subjects; and which protected<br />

His Majesty in safety and peace:<br />

with which the King was greatly<br />

offended, and said, that then he<br />

should be under the law, which<br />

was treason to affirm, as he said;<br />

to which I said, that Bracton<br />

saith, quod Rex non debed esse<br />

sub homine, sed sub Deo et lege<br />

(That the King ought not to be<br />

under any man but under God<br />

and the law.)."<br />

Among the first modern authors<br />

to give the principle theoretical<br />

foundations was Samuel<br />

Rutherford in Lex, Rex (1644). The title, Latin for "the law is king", subverts the traditional<br />

formulation rex lex ("the king is law"). John Locke also discussed this issue in his Second<br />

Treatise of Government (1690). The principle was also discussed by Montesquieu in The Spirit<br />

of the Laws (1748). The phrase "rule of law" appears in Samuel Johnson's Dictionary (1755).<br />

In 1776, the notion that no one is above the law was popular during the founding of the United<br />

States. For example, Thomas Paine wrote in his pamphlet Common Sense that "in America, the<br />

law is king. For as in absolute governments the King is law, so in free countries the law ought to<br />

be king; and there ought to be no other." In 1780, John Adams enshrined this principle in the<br />

Massachusetts Constitution by seeking to establish "a government of laws and not of men."<br />

Categorization<br />

The Oxford English Dictionary has defined "rule of law" this way:<br />

“The authority and influence of law in society, esp. when viewed as a constraint on individual and<br />

institutional behaviour; (hence) the principle whereby all members of a society (including those in<br />

government) are considered equally subject to publicly disclosed legal codes and processes.”<br />

Rule of law implies that every citizen is subject to the law. It stands in contrast to the idea that<br />

the ruler is above the law, for example by divine right.<br />

Despite wide use by politicians, judges and academics, the rule of law has been described as "an<br />

exceedingly elusive notion" According to political theorist Judith N. Shklar, "the phrase 'the Rule<br />

Page 63 of 115


of Law' has become meaningless thanks to ideological abuse and general over-use", but<br />

nevertheless this phrase has in the past had specific and important meanings.<br />

Among modern legal theorists, one finds that at least two principal conceptions of the rule of law<br />

can be identified: a formalist or "thin" definition, and a substantive or "thick" definition; one<br />

occasionally encounters a third "functional" conception. Formalist definitions of the rule of law<br />

do not make a judgment about the "justness" of law itself, but define specific procedural<br />

attributes that a legal framework must have in order to be in compliance with the rule of law.<br />

Substantive conceptions of the rule of law go beyond this and include certain substantive rights<br />

that are said to be based on, or derived from, the rule of law.<br />

Most legal theorists believe that the rule of law has purely formal characteristics, meaning that<br />

the law must be publicly declared, with prospective application, and possess the characteristics<br />

of generality, equality, and certainty, but there are no requirements with regard to the content of<br />

the law. Others, including a few legal theorists, believe that the rule of law necessarily entails<br />

protection of individual rights. Within legal theory, these two approaches to the rule of law are<br />

seen as the two basic alternatives, respectively labelled the formal and substantive approaches.<br />

Still, there are other views as well. Some believe that democracy is part of the rule of law.<br />

The "formal" interpretation is more widespread than the "substantive" interpretation. Formalists<br />

hold that the law must be prospective, well-known, and have characteristics of generality,<br />

equality, and certainty. Other than that, the formal view contains no requirements as to the<br />

content of the law. This formal approach allows laws that protect democracy and individual<br />

rights, but recognizes the existence of "rule of law" in countries that do not necessarily have such<br />

laws protecting democracy or individual rights.<br />

The substantive interpretation holds that the rule of law intrinsically protects some or all<br />

individual rights.<br />

The functional interpretation of the term "rule of law", consistent with the traditional English<br />

meaning, contrasts the "rule of law" with the "rule of man." According to the functional view, a<br />

society in which government officers have a great deal of discretion has a low degree of "rule of<br />

law", whereas a society in which government officers have little discretion has a high degree of<br />

"rule of law". Upholding the rule of law can sometimes require the punishment of those who<br />

commit offenses that are justifiable under natural law but not statutory law. The rule of law is<br />

thus somewhat at odds with flexibility, even when flexibility may be preferable.<br />

The ancient concept of rule of law can be distinguished from rule by law, according to political<br />

science professor Li Shuguang: "The difference....is that, under the rule of law, the law is<br />

preeminent and can serve as a check against the abuse of power. Under rule by law, the law is a<br />

mere tool for a government, that suppresses in a legalistic fashion."<br />

Variations<br />

The rule of law has been considered as one of the key dimensions that determine the quality and<br />

good governance of a country. Research, like the Worldwide Governance Indicators, defines the<br />

Page 64 of 115


ule of law as: "the extent to which agents have confidence and abide by the rules of society, and<br />

in particular the quality of contract enforcement, the police and the courts, as well as the<br />

likelihood of crime or violence." Based on this definition the Worldwide Governance Indicators<br />

project has developed aggregate measurements for the rule of law in more than 200 countries, as<br />

seen in the map below. A government based on the rule of law can be called a "nomocracy",<br />

from the Greek nomos (law) and kratos (power or rule).<br />

Europe<br />

Rule of law in the United Kingdom is a core principle of the way the country is governed. In the<br />

19th century, A. V. Dicey, a constitutional scholar and lawyer, wrote of the twin pillars of the<br />

British constitution in his classic work Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution<br />

(1885). These pillars are the principle of Parliamentary sovereignty and the rule of law.<br />

In Finland, the constitution explicitly requires rule of law by stipulating that "the exercise of<br />

public powers shall be based on an Act. In all public activity, the law shall be strictly observed."<br />

United States<br />

All government officers of the United States,<br />

including the President, the Justices of the<br />

Supreme Court, state judges and legislators,<br />

and all members of Congress, pledge first and<br />

foremost to uphold the Constitution. These<br />

oaths affirm that the rule of law is superior to<br />

the rule of any human leader. At the same time,<br />

the federal government has considerable<br />

discretion: the legislative branch is free to<br />

decide what statutes it will write, as long as it<br />

stays within its enumerated powers and<br />

respects the constitutionally protected rights of<br />

individuals. Likewise, the judicial branch has a<br />

degree of judicial discretion, and the executive<br />

branch also has various discretionary powers<br />

including prosecutorial discretion.<br />

Scholars continue to debate whether the U.S. Constitution adopted a particular interpretation of<br />

the "rule of law," and if so, which one. For example, Law Professor John Harrison asserts that<br />

the word "law" in the Constitution is simply defined as that which is legally binding, rather than<br />

being "defined by formal or substantive criteria," and therefore judges do not have discretion to<br />

decide that laws fail to satisfy such unwritten and vague criteria. Law Professor Frederick Mark<br />

Gedicks disagrees, writing that Cicero, Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and the framers of the U.S.<br />

Constitution believed that an unjust law was not really a law at all.<br />

Some modern scholars contend that the rule of law has been corroded during the past century by<br />

the instrumental view of law promoted by legal realists such as Oliver Wendell Holmes and<br />

Page 65 of 115


Roscoe Pound. For example, Professor Brian Tamanaha asserts: "The rule of law is a centuriesold<br />

ideal, but the notion that law is a means to an end became entrenched only in the course of<br />

the nineteenth and twentieth centuries."<br />

Others argue that the rule of law has survived but was transformed to allow for the exercise of<br />

discretion by administrators. For much of American history, the dominant notion of the rule of<br />

law, in this setting, has been some version of A. V. Dicey's: ―no man is punishable or can be<br />

lawfully made to suffer in body or goods except for a distinct breach of law established in the<br />

ordinary legal manner before the ordinary Courts of the land.‖ That is, individuals should be able<br />

to challenge an administrative order by bringing suit in a court of general jurisdiction. As the<br />

dockets of worker compensation commissions, public utility commissions and other agencies<br />

burgeoned, it soon became apparent that letting judges decide for themselves all the facts in a<br />

dispute (such as the extent of an injury in a worker's compensation case) would overwhelm the<br />

courts and destroy the advantages of specialization that led to the creation of administrative<br />

agencies in the first place. Even Charles Evans Hughes, a Chief Justice of the United States,<br />

believed ―you must have administration, and you must have administration by administrative<br />

officers.‖ By 1941, a compromise had emerged. If administrators adopted procedures that moreor-less<br />

tracked "the ordinary legal manner" of the courts, further review of the facts by "the<br />

ordinary Courts of the land" was unnecessary. That is, if you had your "day in commission," the<br />

rule of law did not require a further "day in court." Thus Dicey's rule of law was recast into a<br />

purely procedural form.<br />

James Wilson said during the Philadelphia Convention in 1787 that, "Laws may be unjust, may<br />

be unwise, may be dangerous, may be destructive; and yet not be so unconstitutional as to justify<br />

the Judges in refusing to give them effect." George Mason agreed that judges "could declare an<br />

unconstitutional law void. But with regard to every law, however unjust, oppressive or<br />

pernicious, which did not come plainly under this description, they would be under the necessity<br />

as judges to give it a free course." Chief Justice John Marshall (joined by Justice Joseph Story)<br />

took a similar position in 1827: "When its existence as law is denied, that existence cannot be<br />

proved by showing what are the qualities of a law."<br />

Asia<br />

East Asian cultures are influenced by two schools of thought, Confucianism, which advocated<br />

good governance as rule by leaders who are benevolent and virtuous, and Legalism, which<br />

advocated strict adherence to law. The influence of one school of thought over the other has<br />

varied throughout the centuries. One study indicates that throughout East Asia, only South<br />

Korea, Singapore, Japan, Taiwan and Hong Kong have societies that are robustly committed to a<br />

law-bound state. According to Awzar Thi, a member of the Asian Human Rights Commission,<br />

the rule of law in Thailand, Cambodia, and most of Asia is weak or nonexistent:<br />

Apart from a number of states and territories, across the continent there is a huge gulf between<br />

the rule of law rhetoric and reality. In Thailand, the police force is an organized crime gang. In<br />

Cambodia, judges are proxies for the ruling political party ... That a judge may harbor political<br />

prejudice or apply the law unevenly are the smallest worries for an ordinary criminal defendant<br />

in Asia. More likely ones are: Will the police fabricate the evidence? Will the prosecutor bother<br />

Page 66 of 115


to show up? Will the judge fall asleep? Will I be poisoned in prison? Will my case be completed<br />

within a decade?<br />

In countries such as China and Vietnam, the transition to a market economy has been a major<br />

factor in a move toward the rule of law, because a rule of law is important to foreign investors<br />

and to economic development. It remains unclear whether the rule of law in countries like China<br />

and Vietnam will be limited to commercial matters or will spill into other areas as well, and if so<br />

whether that spillover will enhance prospects for related values such as democracy and human<br />

rights. The rule of law in China has been widely discussed and debated by both legal scholars<br />

and politicians in China.<br />

In Thailand, a kingdom that has had a constitution since the initial attempt to overthrow the<br />

absolute monarchy system in 1932, the rule of law has been more of a principle than actual<br />

practice. Ancient prejudices and political bias have been present in the three branches of<br />

government with each of their foundings, and justice has been processed formally according to<br />

the law but in fact more closely aligned with royalist principles that are still advocated in the 21st<br />

century. In November 2013, Thailand faced still further threats to the rule of law when the<br />

executive branch rejected a supreme court decision over how to select senators.<br />

In India, the longest constitutional text in the history of the world has governed that country<br />

since 1950. Although the Constitution of India may have been intended to provide details that<br />

would limit the opportunity for judicial discretion, the more text there is in a constitution the<br />

greater opportunity the judiciary may have to exercise judicial review. According to Indian<br />

journalist Harish Khare, "The rule of law or rather the Constitution [is] in danger of being<br />

supplanted by the rule of judges."<br />

Japan had centuries of tradition prior to World War II, during which there were laws, but they<br />

did not provide a central organizing principle for society, and they did not constrain the powers<br />

of government (Boadi, 2001). As the 21st century began, the percentage of people who were<br />

lawyers and judges in Japan remained very low relative to western Europe and the United States,<br />

and legislation in Japan tended to be terse and general, leaving much discretion in the hands of<br />

bureaucrats.<br />

Worldwide Organizational Promotion<br />

Various organizations are involved in promoting the rule of law.<br />

International Commission of Jurists<br />

In 1959, an international gathering of over 185 judges, lawyers, and law professors from 53<br />

countries, meeting in New Delhi and speaking as the International Commission of Jurists, made a<br />

declaration as to the fundamental principle of the rule of law. This was the Declaration of Delhi.<br />

They declared that the rule of law implies certain rights and freedoms, that it implies an<br />

independent judiciary, and that it implies social, economic and cultural conditions conducive to<br />

human dignity. The Declaration of Delhi did not, however, suggest that the rule of law requires<br />

legislative power to be subject to judicial review.<br />

Page 67 of 115


United Nations<br />

The Secretary-General of the United Nations defines the rule of law as:<br />

a principle of governance in which all persons, institutions and entities, public and private,<br />

including the State itself, are accountable to laws that are publicly promulgated, equally enforced<br />

and independently adjudicated, and which are consistent with international human rights norms<br />

and standards. It requires, as well, measures to ensure adherence to the principles of supremacy<br />

of law, equality before the law, accountability to the law, fairness in the application of the law,<br />

separation of powers, participation in decision-making, legal certainty, avoidance of arbitrariness<br />

and procedural and legal transparency.<br />

The General Assembly has considered rule of law as an agenda item since 1992, with renewed<br />

interest since 2006 and has adopted resolutions at its last three sessions. The Security Council<br />

has held a number of thematic debates on the rule of law, and adopted resolutions emphasizing<br />

the importance of these issues in the context of women, peace and security, children in armed<br />

conflict, and the protection of civilians in armed conflict. The Peacebuilding Commission has<br />

also regularly addressed rule of law issues with respect to countries on its agenda. The Vienna<br />

Declaration and Programme of Action also requires the rule of law be included in human rights<br />

education.<br />

Page 68 of 115


International Bar Association<br />

The Council of the International Bar Association passed a resolution in 2009 endorsing a<br />

substantive or "thick" definition of the rule of law:<br />

An independent, impartial judiciary; the presumption of innocence; the right to a fair and public<br />

trial without undue delay; a rational and proportionate approach to punishment; a strong and<br />

independent legal profession; strict protection of confidential communications between lawyer<br />

and client; equality of all before the law; these are all fundamental principles of the Rule of Law.<br />

Accordingly, arbitrary arrests; secret trials; indefinite detention without trial; cruel or degrading<br />

treatment or punishment; intimidation or corruption in the electoral process, are all unacceptable.<br />

The Rule of Law is the foundation of a civilised society. It establishes a transparent process<br />

accessible and equal to all. It ensures adherence to principles that both liberate and protect. The<br />

IBA calls upon all countries to respect these fundamental principles. It also calls upon its<br />

members to speak out in support of the Rule of Law within their respective communities.<br />

World Justice Project<br />

As used by the World Justice Project, a non-profit organization committed to advancing the rule<br />

of law around the world, the rule of law refers to a rules-based system in which the following<br />

four universal principles are upheld:<br />

1. The government and its officials and agents are accountable under the law;<br />

2. The laws are clear, publicized, stable, fair, and protect fundamental rights, including the<br />

security of persons and property;<br />

3. The process by which the laws are enacted, administered, and enforced is accessible, fair, and<br />

efficient;<br />

4. Access to justice is provided by competent, independent, and ethical adjudicators, attorneys or<br />

representatives, and judicial officers who are of sufficient number, have adequate resources, and<br />

reflect the makeup of the communities they serve.<br />

The World Justice Project has developed an Index to measure the extent to which countries<br />

adhere to the rule of law in practice. The WJP Rule of Law Index is composed of 9 factors and<br />

52 sub-factors, and covers a variety of dimensions of the rule of law —such as whether<br />

government officials are accountable under the law, and whether legal institutions protect<br />

fundamental rights and allow ordinary people access to justice.<br />

Economic Impacts<br />

One important aspect of the rule-of-law initiatives is the study and analysis of the rule of law’s<br />

impact on economic development. The rule-of-law movement cannot be fully successful in<br />

transitional and developing countries without an answer to the question: does the rule of law<br />

matter for economic development or not? Constitutional economics is the study of the<br />

Page 69 of 115


compatibility of economic and financial decisions within existing constitutional law frameworks,<br />

and such a framework includes government spending on the judiciary, which, in many<br />

transitional and developing countries, is completely controlled by the executive. It is useful to<br />

distinguish between the two methods of corruption of the judiciary: corruption by the executive<br />

branch, in contrast to corruption by private actors.<br />

The standards of constitutional economics can be used during annual budget process, and if that<br />

budget planning is transparent then the rule of law may benefit. The availability of an effective<br />

court system, to be used by the civil society in situations of unfair government spending and<br />

executive impoundment of previously authorized appropriations, is a key element for the success<br />

of the rule-of-law endeavor.<br />

The Rule of Law is especially important as an influence on the economic development in<br />

developing and transitional countries. To date, the term ―rule of law‖ has been used primarily in<br />

the English-speaking countries, and it is not yet fully clarified even with regard to such wellestablished<br />

democracies as, for instance, Sweden, Denmark, France, Germany, or Japan. A<br />

common language between lawyers of common law and civil law countries as well as between<br />

legal communities of developed and developing countries is critically important for research of<br />

links between the rule of law and real economy.<br />

The modern economist F. A. Hayek analyzed how the Rule of Law might be beneficial to the<br />

free market. Hayek proposed that under the Rule of Law individuals would be able to make wise<br />

investments and future plans with some confidence in a successful return on investment when he<br />

stated: "under the Rule of Law the government is prevented from stultifying individual efforts by<br />

ad hoc action. Within the known rules of the game the individual is free to pursue his personal<br />

ends and desires, certain that the powers of government will not be used deliberately to frustrate<br />

his efforts." Hayek defined the Rule of Law as the opposite of arbitrary government: "The<br />

distinction we have drawn before between the creation of a permanent framework of laws within<br />

which the productive activity is guided by individual decisions and the direction of economic<br />

activity by a central authority is thus really a particular case of the more general distinction<br />

between the Rule of Law and arbitrary government. Under the first the government confines<br />

itself to fixing rules determining the conditions under which the available resources may be used,<br />

leaving to the individuals the decision for what ends they are to be used. Under the second the<br />

government directs the use of the means of production to particular ends. The first type of rules<br />

can be made in advance, in the shape of formal rules which do not aim at the wants and needs of<br />

particular people. They are intended to be merely instrumental in the pursuit of people's various<br />

individual ends. And they are, or ought to be, intended for such long periods that it is impossible<br />

to know whether they will assist particular people more than others. They could almost be<br />

described as a kind of instrument of production, helping people to predict the behavior of those<br />

with whom they must collaborate, rather than as efforts toward the satisfaction of particular<br />

needs."<br />

Page 70 of 115


Page 71 of 115


Rule of Higher Law<br />

The Rule According To A Higher<br />

Law means that no law may be enforced by<br />

the government unless it conforms with<br />

certain universal principles (written or<br />

unwritten) of fairness, morality, and justice.<br />

Thus, the rule according to a higher law may<br />

serve as a practical legal criterion to qualify<br />

the instances of political or economical<br />

decision-making, when a government, even<br />

though acting in conformity with clearly<br />

defined and properly enacted legal rules, still<br />

produces results which many observers find<br />

unfair or unjust.<br />

"Higher law" can be interpreted in this context as the divine or natural law or basic legal values,<br />

established in the international law, – the choice depending on the viewpoint. But this is<br />

definitely a Law above the law. And it is in this capacity that it possesses the equal legal value<br />

for both the common and civil law jurisdictions, as opposed to natural law which is largely<br />

associated with common law. "To recognize the necessary connection between the rule of law as<br />

an ideal and well-constructed constitutional government does not and should not be taken to<br />

imply that all states can or should maintain the same constitutional structures in practice".<br />

The rule according to higher law is a practical approach to the implementation of the higher law<br />

theory which creates a bridge of mutual understanding (with regard to universal legal values)<br />

between the English language doctrine of the rule of law, traditional for the countries of common<br />

law, and the originally German doctrine of Rechtsstaat, translated into other languages of<br />

continental Europe as État de droit (Fr.), Estado de derecho (Sp.), Stato di diritto (It.), and<br />

Правовое государство (Ru.). The latter doctrine is the product of continental European legal<br />

thought which had adopted it from German legal philosophy. Its name can be translated into<br />

English as ―legal state‖ or "state of law" or "state of rights" or "constitutional state" –<br />

consistently meaning the state in which the exercise of governmental power is kept in check by<br />

the higher law rather than by the changeable law established by this state. Amartya Sen<br />

mentioned that the legal theorists in ancient India used term of classical Sanscrit "nyaya" in the<br />

sense of not just a matter of judging institutions and rules, but of judging the societies<br />

themselves.<br />

Before the U.S. Civil War, African Americans were legally denied equal rights and freedoms<br />

pursuant to formally valid codes prescribing the relations between master and slave. Although<br />

these codes were de jure fully suitable for application in legal practice, their enforcement by the<br />

then U.S. government de facto violated basic human rights of a significant part of the population.<br />

William H. Seward famously proclaimed that slavery is forbidden under "a higher law than the<br />

Constitution."<br />

Page 72 of 115


Generally speaking, the occurrence of such "justly enacted unjust laws" fully depends on the<br />

stance taken by the country's political leadership towards the rule of law principle.<br />

In some countries, the political leaders assert that the rule of law is purely a procedural concept.<br />

Therefore, they argue that any government may strip its subjects of their fundamental freedoms<br />

or infringe their vital interests so long as this is done by way of a duly implemented legal<br />

mechanism. For example, at the Nuremberg trials, in an attempt to justify their crimes against<br />

Jewish and Romany population of Europe during World War II, some of the former leaders of<br />

Nazi Germany argued that they had broken none of the laws effective when Hitler had been in<br />

power. It was only by invoking the rule according to a higher law that the Allied prosecutors<br />

were able to legitimately overcome such defenses.<br />

In other countries, conversely, the political leaders assert that all written laws must be kept in<br />

line with the universal principles of morality, fairness, and justice. These leaders argue that, as a<br />

necessary corollary to the axiom that "no one is above the law," the rule of law requires the<br />

government to treat all persons equally under the law. However, the proclaimed right to equal<br />

treatment is susceptible to instantly becoming void each time the government denies a sufficient<br />

level of respect, dignity, and autonomy to a certain class of individuals or to human rights in<br />

general." Therefore, the unwritten and universally self-explanatory principles of equality,<br />

autonomy, dignity, and respect are said to overrule conventional written laws enacted by the<br />

government. It is these principles that are often referred to as "natural law." They also constitute<br />

the basis of the "higher law theory."<br />

Constitutional Governance<br />

The Rechtsstaat doctrine (Legal state, State of right, Constitutional state, Constitutional<br />

government) was first introduced by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant in his latest works<br />

completed after the U.S. and French constitutions had been adopted in the late 18th century.<br />

Kant’s approach is based on the supremacy of country’s written constitution created using<br />

principles of the Higher Law. This supremacy meant creating guarantees for the implementation<br />

of his central idea: a permanently peaceful life as a basic condition for the happiness and<br />

prosperity of the citizens. Kant was basing his doctrine exclusively on the idea of<br />

constitutionalism and constitutional government.<br />

Kant had formulated the main problem of constitutionalism as an instrument for the practical<br />

implementation of the Higher Law as follows, ―The constitution of a state is eventually based on<br />

the morals of its citizens, which, in its turn, is based on the goodness of this constitution.‖ This<br />

idea of Kant’s has become the foundation for the constitutional theory of the 21st century. The<br />

Legal state concept is based on the ideas introduced by Immanuel Kant, for example, in his<br />

Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals:<br />

―The task of establishing a universal and permanent peaceful life is not only a part of theory of<br />

law within the framework of pure reason, but per se an absolute and ultimate goal. To achieve<br />

this goal, a state must become the community of a large number of people, living provided with<br />

legislative guarantees of their property rights secured by a common constitution. The supremacy<br />

of this constitution… must be derived a priori from the considerations for achievement of the<br />

Page 73 of 115


absolute ideal in the most just and fair organization of people’s life under the aegis of public<br />

law.‖<br />

The Russian legal system, born in the 19th century as a result of the transformations initiated by<br />

the reforms of the Emperor Alexander II, was (and still is) based primarily upon the German<br />

legal tradition. It was from the latter that Russia had adopted the doctrine of Rechtsstaat, which<br />

literally translates as "Legal State." Its closest English analogue is "the rule of law." The Russian<br />

Legal state concept adopts the written constitution as the country's supreme law (the rule of<br />

constitution). It is a fundamental but undefined principle that appears in the very first dispositive<br />

provision of Russia’s post-Communist constitution: "The Russian Federation – Russia –<br />

constitutes a democratic federative legal state with a republican form of governance." Similarly,<br />

the very first dispositive provision of Ukraine’s Constitution declares that "Ukraine is a<br />

sovereign and independent, democratic, social, legal state." Hence, the effort to invest meaning<br />

to the "Legal State" definition is anything but theoretical.<br />

Valery Zorkin, President of the Constitutional Court of Russia, wrote in 2003, "Becoming a legal<br />

state has long been our ultimate goal, and we have certainly made serious progress in this<br />

direction over the past several years. However, no one can say now that we have reached this<br />

destination. Such a legal state simply cannot exist without a lawful and just society. Here, as in<br />

no other sphere of our life, the state reflects the level of maturity reached by the society."<br />

The Russian concept of Legal state has adopted many segments of constitutional economics<br />

which serves as a practical implementation of the higher law theory in economics.<br />

Economist James M. Buchanan argues that, in the framework of constitutional government, any<br />

governmental intervention or regulation must be conditioned by the three following assumptions.<br />

First, every failure of the market economy to function smoothly and perfectly can be corrected<br />

by governmental intervention. Second, those holding political office and manning the<br />

bureaucracies are altruistic upholders of the public interest, unconcerned with their own personal<br />

economic well-being. And third, changing the government responsibilities towards more<br />

intervention and control will not profoundly and perversely affect the social and economic life.<br />

Buchanan rejects "any organic conception of the state as superior in wisdom, to the individuals<br />

who are its members." This philosophical position is, in fact, the very subject matter of<br />

constitutional economics. A constitutional economics approach allows for a combined economic<br />

and constitutional analysis, helping to avoid a one-dimensional understanding. Buchanan,<br />

together with Kant, believes that a constitution in its capacity as the Higher Law, intended for<br />

use by at least several generations of citizens, must be able to adjust itself for pragmatic<br />

economic decisions, while balancing interests of the state and society against those of<br />

individuals, with their constitutional rights to personal freedom and private happiness.<br />

Buchanan also outlines importance of protection of the moral principles underlying<br />

constitutional norms. He writes that "the ethics of constitutional citizenship is not directly<br />

comparable to ethical behavior in interaction with other persons within the constraints imposed<br />

by the rules of an existing regime. An individual may be fully responsible, in the standard ethical<br />

sense, and yet fail to meet the ethical requirement of constitutional citizenship." [<br />

Page 74 of 115


Page 75 of 115


Political Corruption of The Judiciary<br />

Political Corruption is the use of powers by government<br />

officials for illegitimate private gain. An illegal act by an<br />

officeholder constitutes political corruption only if the act is<br />

directly related to their official duties, is done under color of<br />

law or involves trading in influence.<br />

Forms of corruption vary, but include bribery, extortion,<br />

cronyism, nepotism, patronage, graft, and embezzlement.<br />

Corruption may facilitate criminal enterprise such as drug<br />

trafficking, money laundering, and human trafficking, though is not restricted to these activities.<br />

Misuse of government power for other purposes, such as repression of political opponents and<br />

general police brutality, is not considered political corruption. Neither are illegal acts by private<br />

persons or corporations not directly involved with the government.<br />

The activities that constitute illegal corruption differ depending on the country or jurisdiction.<br />

For instance, some political funding practices that are legal in one place may be illegal in<br />

another. In some cases, government officials have broad or ill-defined powers, which make it<br />

difficult to distinguish between legal and illegal actions. Worldwide, bribery alone is estimated<br />

to involve over 1 trillion US dollars annually. A state of unrestrained political corruption is<br />

known as a kleptocracy, literally meaning "rule by thieves".<br />

Some forms of corruption – now called "institutional corruption" – are distinguished from<br />

bribery and other kinds of obvious personal gain. A similar problem of corruption arises in any<br />

institution that depends on financial support from people who have interests that may conflict<br />

with the primary purpose of the institution.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Corruption<br />

There are two methods of corruption of the judiciary: the state (through budget planning and<br />

various privileges), and the private. Budget of the judiciary in many transitional and developing<br />

countries is almost completely controlled by the executive. The latter undermines the separation<br />

of powers, as it creates a critical financial dependence of the judiciary. The proper national<br />

wealth distribution including the government spending on the judiciary is subject of the<br />

constitutional economics.<br />

Effects on Politics, Administration, and Institutions<br />

In politics, corruption undermines democracy and good governance by flouting or even<br />

subverting formal processes. Corruption in elections and in the legislature reduces accountability<br />

and distorts representation in policymaking; corruption in the judiciary compromises the rule of<br />

law; and corruption in public administration results in the inefficient provision of services. It<br />

violates a basic principle of republicanism regarding the centrality of civic virtue. More<br />

Page 76 of 115


generally, corruption erodes the institutional capacity of government if procedures are<br />

disregarded, resources are siphoned off, and public offices are bought and sold. Corruption<br />

undermines the legitimacy of government and such democratic values as trust and tolerance.<br />

Recent evidence suggests that variation in the levels of corruption amongst high-income<br />

democracies can vary significantly depending on the level of accountability of decision-makers.<br />

Evidence from fragile states also shows that corruption and bribery can adversely impact trust in<br />

institutions.<br />

Economic Effects<br />

In the private sector, corruption increases the cost of business through the price of illicit<br />

payments themselves, the management cost of negotiating with officials and the risk of breached<br />

agreements or detection. Although some claim corruption reduces costs by cutting bureaucracy,<br />

the availability of bribes can also induce officials to contrive new rules and delays. Openly<br />

removing costly and lengthy regulations are better than covertly allowing them to be bypassed by<br />

using bribes. Where corruption inflates the cost of business, it also distorts the playing field,<br />

shielding firms with connections from competition and thereby sustaining inefficient firms.<br />

Corruption also generates economic distortions in the public sector by diverting public<br />

investment into capital projects where bribes and kickbacks are more plentiful. Officials may<br />

increase the technical complexity of public sector projects to conceal or pave the way for such<br />

dealings, thus further distorting investment. Corruption also lowers compliance with<br />

construction, environmental, or other regulations, reduces the quality of government services and<br />

infrastructure, and increases budgetary pressures on government.<br />

Economists argue that one of the factors behind the differing economic development in Africa<br />

and Asia is that in Africa, corruption has primarily taken the form of rent extraction with the<br />

resulting financial capital moved overseas rather than invested at home (hence the stereotypical,<br />

but often accurate, image of African dictators having Swiss bank accounts). In Nigeria, for<br />

example, more than $400 billion was stolen from the treasury by Nigeria's leaders between 1960<br />

and 1999. University of Massachusetts Amherst researchers estimated that from 1970 to 1996,<br />

capital flight from 30 Sub-Saharan countries totaled $187bn, exceeding those nations' external<br />

debts. (The results, expressed in retarded or suppressed development, have been modeled in<br />

theory by economist Mancur Olson.) In the case of Africa, one of the factors for this behavior<br />

was political instability, and the fact that new governments often confiscated previous<br />

government's corruptly obtained assets. This encouraged officials to stash their wealth abroad,<br />

out of reach of any future expropriation. In contrast, Asian administrations such as Suharto's<br />

New Order often took a cut on business transactions or provided conditions for development,<br />

through infrastructure investment, law and order, etc.<br />

Environmental and Social Effect<br />

Corruption is often most evident in countries with the smallest per capita incomes, relying on<br />

foreign aid for health services. However, political exploitation of these funds have been noted to<br />

occur in the past, especially in the Sub-Saharan African nations, where it was reported in the<br />

2006 World Bank Report that about half of the funds that were donated for health usages, were<br />

Page 77 of 115


never invested into the health sectors or given to those needing medical attention. Instead, they<br />

were expended through "counterfeit drugs, siphoning off of drugs to the black market, and<br />

payments to ghost employees". Ultimately, there is a sufficient amount of money for health in<br />

developing countries, but this cash is given to the wrong hands, which leads to political and<br />

governmental corruption that takes away medical attention necessary for the citizens of these<br />

regions, and rather, used for personal gain.<br />

Corruption facilitates environmental destruction. Corrupt countries may formally have legislation<br />

to protect the environment, it cannot be enforced if officials can easily be bribed. The same<br />

applies to social rights worker protection, unionization prevention, and child labor. Violation of<br />

these laws rights enables corrupt countries to gain illegitimate economic advantage in the<br />

international market.<br />

The Nobel Prize-winning economist<br />

Amartya Sen has observed that<br />

"there is no such thing as an<br />

apolitical food problem."<br />

While drought and other naturally occurring<br />

events may trigger famine conditions, it is<br />

government action or inaction that<br />

determines its severity, and often<br />

even whether or not a famine will occur.<br />

Governments with strong tendencies<br />

towards kleptocracy can undermine food<br />

security even when harvests are good.<br />

Officials often steal state property. In Bihar,<br />

India, more than 80% of<br />

the subsidized food aid to<br />

poor is stolen by corrupt<br />

officials. Similarly, food<br />

aid is often robbed at gunpoint by governments, criminals,<br />

and warlords alike, and sold for a<br />

profit. The 20th century is full of<br />

many examples of governments undermining the food security of their own nations – sometimes<br />

intentionally.<br />

Effects on Humanitarian Aid<br />

The scale of humanitarian aid to the poor and unstable regions of the world grows, but it is<br />

highly vulnerable to corruption, with food aid, construction and other highly valued assistance as<br />

the most at risk. Food aid can be directly and physically diverted from its intended destination, or<br />

indirectly through the manipulation of assessments, targeting, registration and distributions to<br />

favor certain groups or individuals. Elsewhere, in construction and shelter, there are numerous<br />

opportunities for diversion and profit through substandard workmanship, kickbacks for contracts<br />

and favoritism in the provision of valuable shelter material. Thus while humanitarian aid<br />

agencies are usually most concerned about aid being diverted by including too many, recipients<br />

themselves are most concerned about exclusion. Access to aid may be limited to those with<br />

connections, to those who pay bribes or are forced to give sexual favors. Equally, those able to<br />

do so may manipulate statistics to inflate the number of beneficiaries and siphon off additional<br />

assistance.<br />

Page 78 of 115


Other Areas: Health, Public Safety, Education, Trade Unions, Etc.<br />

Corruption is not specific to poor, developing, or transition countries. In western countries, cases<br />

of bribery and other forms of corruption in all possible fields exist: under-the-table payments<br />

made to reputed surgeons by patients attempting to be on top of the list of forthcoming surgeries,<br />

bribes paid by suppliers to the automotive industry in order to sell low-quality connectors used<br />

for instance in safety equipment such as airbags, bribes paid by suppliers to manufacturers of<br />

defibrillators (to sell low-quality capacitors), contributions paid by wealthy parents to the "social<br />

and culture fund" of a prestigious university in exchange for it to accept their children, bribes<br />

paid to obtain diplomas, financial and other advantages granted to unionists by members of the<br />

executive board of a car manufacturer in exchange for employer-friendly positions and votes,<br />

etc. Examples are endless. These various manifestations of corruption can ultimately present a<br />

danger for the public health; they can discredit specific, essential institutions or social<br />

relationships.<br />

Corruption can also affect the various components of sports activities (referees, players, medical<br />

and laboratory staff involved in anti-doping controls, members of national sport federation and<br />

international committees deciding about the allocation of contracts and competition places).<br />

Cases exist against (members of) various types of non-profit and non-government organizations,<br />

as well as religious organizations.<br />

Ultimately, the distinction between public and private sector corruption sometimes appears rather<br />

artificial, and national anti-corruption initiatives may need to avoid legal and other loopholes in<br />

the coverage of the instruments.<br />

Types of Corruption<br />

Bribery<br />

A bribe is a payment given personally to a government official in exchange of his use of official<br />

powers. Bribery requires two participants: one to give the bribe, and one to take it. Either may<br />

initiate the corrupt offering; for example, a customs official may demand bribes to let through<br />

allowed (or disallowed) goods, or a smuggler might offer bribes to gain passage. In some<br />

countries the culture of corruption extends to every aspect of public life, making it extremely<br />

difficult for individuals to stay in business without resorting to bribes. Bribes may be demanded<br />

in order for an official to do something he is already paid to do. They may also be demanded in<br />

order to bypass laws and regulations. In addition to using bribery for private financial gain, they<br />

are also used to intentionally and maliciously cause harm to another (i.e. no financial incentive).<br />

In some developing nations, up to half of the population has paid bribes during the past 12<br />

months.<br />

In recent years, efforts have been made by the international community to encourage countries to<br />

dissociate and incriminate as separate offences, active and passive bribery. Active bribery can be<br />

defined for instance as the promising, offering or giving by any person, directly or indirectly, of<br />

any undue advantage [to any public official], for himself or herself or for anyone else, for him or<br />

Page 79 of 115


her to act or refrain from acting in the exercise of his or her<br />

functions. (article 2 of the Criminal Law Convention on<br />

Corruption (ETS 173) of the Council of Europe). Passive<br />

bribery can be defined as the request or receipt [by any<br />

public official], directly or indirectly, of any undue<br />

advantage, for himself or herself or for anyone else, or the<br />

acceptance of an offer or a promise of such an advantage,<br />

to act or refrain from acting in the exercise of his or her<br />

functions (article 3 of the Criminal Law Convention on<br />

Corruption (ETS 173)). The reason for this dissociation is<br />

to make the early steps (offering, promising, requesting an<br />

advantage) of a corrupt deal already an offence and, thus, to<br />

give a clear signal (from a criminal policy point of view)<br />

that bribery is not acceptable. Furthermore, such a<br />

dissociation makes the prosecution of bribery offences<br />

easier since it can be very difficult to prove that two parties<br />

(the bribe-giver and the bribe-taker) have formally agreed<br />

upon a corrupt deal. In addition, there is often no such<br />

formal deal but only a mutual understanding, for instance<br />

when it is common knowledge in a municipality that to obtain a building permit one has to pay a<br />

"fee" to the decision maker to obtain a favorable decision. A working definition of corruption is<br />

also provided as follows in article 3 of the Civil Law Convention on Corruption (ETS 174):<br />

For the purpose of this Convention, "corruption" means requesting, offering, giving or accepting, directly<br />

or indirectly, a bribe or any other undue advantage or prospect thereof, which distorts the proper<br />

performance of any duty or behavior required of the recipient of the bribe, the undue advantage or the<br />

prospect thereof.<br />

Trading in Influence<br />

Trading in influence, or influence peddling, refers a person selling his/her influence over the<br />

decision making process to benefit a third party (person or institution). The difference with<br />

bribery is that this is a tri-lateral relation. From a legal point of view, the role of the third party<br />

(who is the target of the influence) does not really matter although he/she can be an accessory in<br />

some instances. It can be difficult to make a distinction between this form of corruption and<br />

some forms of extreme and loosely regulated lobbying where for instance law- or decisionmakers<br />

can freely "sell" their vote, decision power or influence to those lobbyists who offer the<br />

highest compensation, including where for instance the latter act on behalf of powerful clients<br />

such as industrial groups who want to avoid the passing of specific environmental, social, or<br />

other regulations perceived as too stringent, etc. Where lobbying is (sufficiently) regulated, it<br />

becomes possible to provide for a distinctive criteria and to consider that trading in influence<br />

involves the use of "improper influence", as in article 12 of the Criminal Law Convention on<br />

Corruption (ETS 173) of the Council of Europe.<br />

Page 80 of 115


Patronage<br />

Patronage refers to favoring supporters, for example with government employment. This may be<br />

legitimate, as when a newly elected government changes the top officials in the administration in<br />

order to effectively implement its policy. It can be seen as corruption if this means that<br />

incompetent persons, as a payment for supporting the regime, are selected before more able ones.<br />

In nondemocracies many government officials are often selected for loyalty rather than ability.<br />

They may be almost exclusively selected from a particular group (for example, Sunni Arabs in<br />

Saddam Hussein's Iraq, the nomenklatura in the Soviet Union, or the Junkers in Imperial<br />

Germany) that support the regime in return for such favors. A similar problem can also be seen<br />

in Eastern Europe, for example in Romania, where the government is often accused of patronage<br />

(when a new government comes to power it rapidly changes most of the officials in the public<br />

sector).<br />

Nepotism and Cronyism<br />

Favoring relatives (nepotism) or personal friends (cronyism) of an official is a form of<br />

illegitimate private gain. This may be combined with bribery, for example demanding that a<br />

business should employ a relative of an official controlling regulations affecting the business.<br />

The most extreme example is when the entire state is inherited, as in North Korea or Syria. A<br />

lesser form might be in the Southern United States with Good ol' boys, where women and<br />

minorities are excluded. A milder form of cronyism is an "old boy network", in which appointees<br />

to official positions are selected only from a closed and exclusive social network – such as the<br />

alumni of particular universities – instead of appointing the most competent candidate.<br />

Seeking to harm enemies becomes corruption when official powers are illegitimately used as<br />

means to this end. For example, trumped-up charges are often brought up against journalists or<br />

writers who bring up politically sensitive issues, such as a politician's acceptance of bribes.<br />

Electoral Fraud<br />

Electoral fraud is illegal interference with the process of an election. Acts of fraud affect vote<br />

counts to bring about an election result, whether by increasing the vote share of the favored<br />

candidate, depressing the vote share of the rival candidates, or both. Also called voter fraud, the<br />

mechanisms involved include illegal voter registration, intimidation at polls, and improper vote<br />

counting.<br />

Embezzlement<br />

Embezzlement is theft of entrusted funds. It is political when it involves public money taken by a<br />

public official for use by anyone not specified by the public. A common type of embezzlement is<br />

that of personal use of entrusted government resources; for example, when an official assigns<br />

public employees to renovate his own house.<br />

Page 81 of 115


Kickbacks<br />

A kickback is an official's share of misappropriated funds allocated from his or her organization<br />

to an organization involved in corrupt bidding. For example, suppose that a politician is in<br />

charge of choosing how to spend some public funds. He can give a contract to a company that is<br />

not the best bidder, or allocate more than they deserve. In this case, the company benefits, and in<br />

exchange for betraying the public, the official receives a kickback payment, which is a portion of<br />

the sum the company received. This sum itself may be all or a portion of the difference between<br />

the actual (inflated) payment to the company and the (lower) market-based price that would have<br />

been paid had the bidding been competitive.<br />

Another example of a kickback would be if a judge receives a portion of the profits that a<br />

business makes in exchange for his judicial decisions.<br />

Kickbacks are not limited to government officials; any situation in which people are entrusted to<br />

spend funds that do not belong to them are susceptible to this kind of corruption.<br />

Unholy Alliance<br />

An unholy alliance is a coalition among seemingly antagonistic groups for ad hoc or hidden gain,<br />

generally some influential non-governmental group forming ties with political parties, supplying<br />

funding in exchange for the favorable treatment. Like patronage, unholy alliances are not<br />

necessarily illegal, but unlike patronage, by its deceptive nature and often great financial<br />

resources, an unholy alliance can be much more dangerous to the public interest. An early use of<br />

the term was by former US President Theodore "Teddy" Roosevelt:<br />

"To destroy this invisible Government, to dissolve the unholy alliance between corrupt<br />

business and corrupt politics is the first task of the statesmanship of the day." – 1912<br />

Progressive Party Platform, attributed to Roosevelt and quoted again in his<br />

autobiography, where he connects trusts and monopolies (sugar interests, Standard Oil,<br />

etc.) to Woodrow Wilson, Howard Taft, and consequently both major political parties.<br />

Involvement in organized crime<br />

An illustrative example of official involvement in organized crime can be found from 1920s and<br />

1930s Shanghai, where Huang Jinrong was a police chief in the French concession, while<br />

simultaneously being a gang boss and co-operating with Du Yuesheng, the local gang ringleader.<br />

The relationship kept the flow of profits from the gang's gambling dens, prostitution, and<br />

protection rackets undisturbed.<br />

The United States accused Manuel Noriega's government in Panama of being a<br />

"narcokleptocracy", a corrupt government profiting on illegal drug trade. Later the U.S. invaded<br />

Panama and captured Noriega.<br />

Page 82 of 115


Conditions Favorable for Corruption<br />

It is argued that the following conditions are favorable for corruption:<br />

<br />

Information deficits<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

Lacking freedom of information legislation. For example: The Indian Right to<br />

Information Act 2005 is perceived to have "already engendered mass movements<br />

in the country that is bringing the lethargic, often corrupt bureaucracy to its knees<br />

and changing power equations completely."<br />

Lack of investigative reporting in the local media.<br />

Contempt for or negligence of exercising freedom of speech and freedom of the<br />

press.<br />

Weak accounting practices, including lack of timely financial management.<br />

Lack of measurement of corruption. For example, using regular surveys of<br />

households and businesses in order to quantify the degree of perception of<br />

corruption in different parts of a nation or in different government institutions<br />

may increase awareness of corruption and create pressure to combat it. This will<br />

also enable an evaluation of the officials who are fighting corruption and the<br />

methods used.<br />

Tax havens which tax their own citizens and companies but not those from other<br />

nations and refuse to disclose information necessary for foreign taxation. This<br />

enables large-scale political corruption in the foreign nations.<br />

<br />

Lacking control of the government.<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

Lacking civic society and non-governmental organizations which monitor the<br />

government.<br />

An individual voter may have a rational ignorance regarding politics, especially in<br />

nationwide elections, since each vote has little weight.<br />

Weak civil service, and slow pace of reform.<br />

Weak rule of law.<br />

Weak legal profession.<br />

Weak judicial independence.<br />

Lacking protection of whistleblowers.<br />

• Government Accountability Project<br />

Lack of benchmarking, that is continual detailed evaluation of procedures and<br />

comparison to others who do similar things, in the same government or others, in<br />

particular comparison to those who do the best work. The Peruvian organization<br />

Ciudadanos al Dia has started to measure and compare transparency, costs, and<br />

efficiency in different government departments in Peru. It annually awards the<br />

best practices which has received widespread media attention. This has created<br />

competition among government agencies in order to improve.<br />

Individual officials routinely handle cash, instead of handling payments by giro or<br />

on a separate cash desk – illegitimate withdrawals from supervised bank accounts<br />

are much more difficult to conceal.<br />

Page 83 of 115


o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

o<br />

Public funds are centralized rather than distributed. For example, if $1,000 is<br />

embezzled from a local agency that has $2,000 funds, it is easier to notice than<br />

from a national agency with $2,000,000 funds. See the principle of subsidiarity.<br />

Large, unsupervised public investments.<br />

Pay disproportionately lower than that of the average citizen.<br />

Government licenses needed to conduct business, e.g., import licenses, encourage<br />

bribing and kickbacks.<br />

Long-time work in the same position may create relationships inside and outside<br />

the government which encourage and help conceal corruption and favoritism.<br />

Rotating government officials to different positions and geographic areas may<br />

help prevent this; for instance certain high rank officials in French government<br />

services (e.g. treasurer-paymasters general) must rotate every few years.<br />

Costly political campaigns, with expenses exceeding normal sources of political<br />

funding, especially when funded with taxpayer money.<br />

A single group or family controlling most of the key government offices. Lack of<br />

laws forbidding and limiting number of members of the same family to be in<br />

office .<br />

Less interaction with officials reduces the opportunities for corruption. For<br />

example, using the Internet for sending in required information, like applications<br />

and tax forms, and then processing this with automated computer systems. This<br />

may also speed up the processing and reduce unintentional human errors. See e-<br />

Government.<br />

A windfall from exporting abundant natural resources may encourage corruption.<br />

War and other forms of conflict correlate with a breakdown of public security.<br />

<br />

Social conditions<br />

o Self-interested closed cliques and "old boy networks".<br />

o Family-, and clan-centered social structure, with a tradition of<br />

nepotism/favouritism being acceptable.<br />

o A gift economy, such as the Soviet blat system, emerges in a Communist centrally<br />

planned economy.<br />

o Lacking literacy and education among the population.<br />

o Frequent discrimination and bullying among the population.<br />

o Tribal solidarity, giving benefits to certain ethnic groups. In India for example,<br />

the political system, it has become common that the leadership of national and<br />

regional parties are passed from generation to generation.<br />

o creating a system in which a family holds the center of power. Some examples are<br />

most of the Dravidian parties of south India and also the Congress party, which is<br />

one of the two major political parties in India.<br />

o Lack of strong laws which forbid members of the same family to contest elections<br />

and be in office as in India where local elections are often contested between<br />

members of the same powerful family by standing in opposite parties so that<br />

whoever is elected that particular family is at tremendous benefit.<br />

Page 84 of 115


Media<br />

Thomas Jefferson observed a tendency for "The functionaries of every government ... to<br />

command at will the liberty and property of their constituents. There is no safe deposit [for<br />

liberty and property] ... without information. Where the press is free, and every man able to read,<br />

all is safe."<br />

Recent research supports Jefferson's claim. Brunetti and Weder found "evidence of a significant<br />

relationship between more press freedom and less corruption in a large cross-section of<br />

countries." They also presented "evidence which suggests that the direction of causation runs<br />

from higher press freedom to lower corruption." Adserà, Boix, and Payne found that increases in<br />

newspaper readership led to increased political accountability and lower corruption in data from<br />

roughly 100 countries and from different states in the US.<br />

Snyder and Strömberg found "that a poor fit between newspaper markets and political districts<br />

reduces press coverage of politics. ... Congressmen who are less covered by the local press work<br />

less for their constituencies: they are less likely to stand witness before congressional hearings ...<br />

. Federal spending is lower in areas where there is less press coverage of the local members of<br />

congress." Schulhofer-Wohl and Garrido found that the year after the Cincinnati Post closed in<br />

2007, "fewer candidates ran for municipal office in the Kentucky suburbs most reliant on the<br />

Post, incumbents became more likely to win reelection, and voter turnout and campaign<br />

spending fell.<br />

An analysis of the evolution of mass media in the US and Europe since World War II noted<br />

mixed results from the growth of the Internet: "The digital revolution has been good for freedom<br />

of expression [and] information [but] has had mixed effects on freedom of the press": It has<br />

disrupted traditional sources of funding, and new forms of Internet journalism have replaced only<br />

a tiny fraction of what's been lost.<br />

Page 85 of 115


Size of Public Sector<br />

Extensive and diverse public spending is, in itself, inherently at risk of cronyism, kickbacks, and<br />

embezzlement. Complicated regulations and arbitrary, unsupervised official conduct exacerbate<br />

the problem. This is one argument for privatization and deregulation. Opponents of privatization<br />

see the argument as ideological. The argument that corruption necessarily follows from the<br />

opportunity is weakened by the existence of countries with low to non-existent corruption but<br />

large public sectors, like the Nordic countries. However, these countries score high on the Ease<br />

of Doing Business Index, due to good and often simple regulations, and have rule of law firmly<br />

established. Therefore, due to their lack of corruption in the first place, they can run large public<br />

sectors without inducing political corruption. Recent evidence that takes both the size of<br />

expenditures and regulatory complexity into account has found that high-income democracies<br />

with more expansive state sectors do indeed have higher levels of corruption.<br />

Like other governmental economic activities, also privatization, such as in the sale of<br />

government-owned property, is particularly at the risk of cronyism. Privatizations in Russia,<br />

Latin America, and East Germany were accompanied by large-scale corruption during the sale of<br />

the state owned companies. Those with political connections unfairly gained large wealth, which<br />

has discredited privatization in these regions. While media have reported widely the grand<br />

corruption that accompanied the sales, studies have argued that in addition to increased operating<br />

efficiency, daily petty corruption is, or would be, larger without privatization, and that corruption<br />

is more prevalent in non-privatized sectors. Furthermore, there is evidence to suggest that<br />

extralegal and unofficial activities are more prevalent in countries that privatized less.<br />

There is the counterpoint, however, that industries with an oligarchy of companies can be quite<br />

corrupt, with collusive price-fixing, pressuring dependent businesses, etc., and only by having a<br />

portion of the market owned by someone other than that oligarchy, i.e. public sector, can keep<br />

them in line. If the public sector company is making money and selling their product for half of<br />

the price of the private sector companies, the private sector companies won't be able to<br />

simultaneously gouge to that degree and keep their customers: the competition keeps them in<br />

line. Private sector corruption can increase the poverty and helplessness of the population, so it<br />

can affect government corruption, in the long-term.<br />

In the European Union, the principle of subsidiarity is applied: a government service should be<br />

provided by the lowest, most local authority that can competently provide it. An effect is that<br />

distribution of funds into multiple instances discourages embezzlement, because even small sums<br />

missing will be noticed. In contrast, in a centralized authority, even minute proportions of public<br />

funds can be large sums of money.<br />

Governmental Corruption<br />

If the highest echelons of the governments also take advantage from corruption or embezzlement<br />

from the state's treasury, it is sometimes referred with the neologism kleptocracy. Members of<br />

the government can take advantage of the natural resources (e.g., diamonds and oil in a few<br />

prominent cases) or state-owned productive industries. A number of corrupt governments have<br />

enriched themselves via foreign aid, which is often spent on showy buildings and armaments.<br />

Page 86 of 115


A corrupt dictatorship typically results in many years of general hardship and suffering for the<br />

vast majority of citizens as civil society and the rule of law disintegrate. In addition, corrupt<br />

dictators routinely ignore economic and social problems in their quest to amass ever more wealth<br />

and power.<br />

The classic case of a corrupt, exploitive dictator often given is the regime of Marshal Mobutu<br />

Sese Seko, who ruled the Democratic Republic of the Congo (which he renamed Zaire) from<br />

1965 to 1997. It is said that usage of the term kleptocracy gained popularity largely in response<br />

to a need to accurately describe Mobutu's regime. Another classic case is Nigeria, especially<br />

under the rule of General Sani Abacha who was de facto president of Nigeria from 1993 until his<br />

death in 1998. He is reputed to have stolen some US$3–4 billion. He and his relatives are often<br />

mentioned in Nigerian 419 letter scams claiming to offer vast fortunes for "help" in laundering<br />

his stolen "fortunes", which in reality turn out not to exist. More than $400 billion was stolen<br />

from the treasury by Nigeria's leaders between 1960 and 1999.<br />

More recently, articles in various financial periodicals, most notably Forbes magazine, have<br />

pointed to Fidel Castro, General Secretary of the Republic of Cuba since 1959, of likely being<br />

the beneficiary of up to $900 million, based on "his control" of state-owned companies.<br />

Opponents of his regime claim that he has used money amassed through weapons sales,<br />

narcotics, international loans, and confiscation of private property to enrich himself and his<br />

political cronies who hold his dictatorship together, and that the $900 million published by<br />

Forbes is merely a portion of his assets, although that needs to be proven.<br />

Opposition and Measurement<br />

Mobile telecommunications and radio broadcasting help to fight corruption, especially in<br />

developing regions like Africa, where other forms of communications are limited. In India, the<br />

anti-corruption bureau fights against corruption, and a new ombudsman bill called Jan Lokpal<br />

Bill is being prepared.<br />

In the 1990s, initiatives were taken at an international level (in particular by the European<br />

Community, the Council of Europe, the OECD) to put a ban on corruption: in 1996, the<br />

Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe, for instance, adopted a comprehensive<br />

Program of Action against Corruption and, subsequently, issued a series of anti-corruption<br />

standard-setting instruments:<br />

the Criminal Law Convention on Corruption (ETS 173);<br />

the Civil Law Convention on Corruption (ETS 174);<br />

the Additional Protocol to the Criminal Law Convention on Corruption (ETS 191);<br />

the Twenty Guiding Principles for the Fight against Corruption (Resolution (97) 24);<br />

the Recommendation on Codes of Conduct for Public Officials (Recommendation No. R<br />

(2000) 10);<br />

the Recommendation on Common Rules against Corruption in the Funding of Political<br />

Parties and Electoral Campaigns (Rec(2003)4)<br />

Page 87 of 115


The purpose of these instruments was to address the various forms of corruption (involving the<br />

public sector, the private sector, the financing of political activities, etc.) whether they had a<br />

strictly domestic or also a transnational dimension. To monitor the implementation at national<br />

level of the requirements and principles provided in those texts, a monitoring mechanism – the<br />

Group of States Against Corruption (also known as GRECO) (French: Groupe d'Etats contre la<br />

corruption) was created.<br />

Further conventions were adopted at the regional level under the aegis of the Organization of<br />

American States (OAS or OEA), the African Union, and in 2003, at the universal level under that<br />

of the United Nations Convention against Corruption.<br />

The Global Integrity Index<br />

Measuring corruption statistically is difficult if not impossible due to the illicit nature of the<br />

transaction and imprecise definitions of corruption. While "corruption" indices first appeared in<br />

1995 with the Corruption Perceptions Index CPI, all of these metrics address different proxies<br />

for corruption, such as public perceptions of the extent of the problem.<br />

Transparency International, an anti-corruption NGO, pioneered this field with the CPI, first<br />

released in 1995. This work is often credited with breaking a taboo and forcing the issue of<br />

corruption into high level development policy discourse. Transparency International currently<br />

publishes three measures, updated annually: a CPI (based on aggregating third-party polling of<br />

public perceptions of how corrupt different countries are); a Global Corruption Barometer (based<br />

on a survey of general public attitudes toward and experience of corruption); and a Bribe Payers<br />

Index, looking at the willingness of foreign firms to pay bribes. The Corruption Perceptions<br />

Index is the best known of these metrics, though it has drawn much criticism and may be<br />

declining in influence. In 2013 Transparency International published a report on the<br />

"Government Defence Anti-corruption Index". This index evaluates the risk of corruption in<br />

countries' military sector.<br />

The World Bank collects a range of data on corruption, including survey responses from over<br />

100,000 firms worldwide and a set of indicators of governance and institutional quality.<br />

Moreover, one of the six dimensions of governance measured by the Worldwide Governance<br />

Indicators is Control of Corruption, which is defined as "the extent to which power is exercised<br />

for private gain, including both petty and grand forms of corruption, as well as 'capture' of the<br />

state by elites and private interests." While the definition itself is fairly precise, the data<br />

aggregated into the Worldwide Governance Indicators is based on any available polling:<br />

questions range from "is corruption a serious problem?" to measures of public access to<br />

information, and not consistent across countries. Despite these weaknesses, the global coverage<br />

of these datasets has led to their widespread adoption, most notably by the Millennium Challenge<br />

Corporation.<br />

A number of parties have collected survey data, from the public and from experts, to try and<br />

gauge the level of corruption and bribery, as well as its impact on political and economic<br />

outcomes. A second wave of corruption metrics has been created by Global Integrity, the<br />

International Budget Partnership, and many lesser known local groups. These metrics include the<br />

Page 88 of 115


Global Integrity Index, first published in 2004. These second wave projects aim to create policy<br />

change by identifying resources more effectively and creating checklists toward incremental<br />

reform. Global Integrity and the International Budget Partnership each dispense with public<br />

surveys and instead uses in-country experts to evaluate "the opposite of corruption" – which<br />

Global Integrity defines as the public policies that prevent, discourage, or expose corruption.<br />

These approaches compliment the first wave, awareness-raising tools by giving governments<br />

facing public outcry a checklist which measures concrete steps toward improved governance.<br />

Typical second wave corruption metrics do not offer the worldwide coverage found in first wave<br />

projects, and instead focus on localizing information gathered to specific problems and creating<br />

deep, "unpackable" content that matches quantitative and qualitative data.<br />

Alternative approaches, such as the British aid agency's Drivers of Change research, skips<br />

numbers and promotes understanding corruption via political economy analysis of who controls<br />

power in a given society.<br />

Institutions Dealing with Political Corruption<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

Global Witness, an international NGO established in 1993 that works to break the links<br />

between natural resource exploitation, conflict, poverty, corruption, and human rights<br />

abuses worldwide<br />

Group of States Against Corruption, a body established under the Council of Europe to<br />

monitor the implementation of instruments adopted by member states to combat political<br />

corruption<br />

Independent Commission Against Corruption (disambiguation)<br />

International Anti-Corruption Academy<br />

Transparency International, a non-governmental organization that monitors and<br />

publicizes corporate and political corruption in international development<br />

o Corruption Perceptions Index, published yearly by Transparency International<br />

TrustLaw, a service of the Thomson Reuters Foundation is a global hub for free legal<br />

assistance and news and information on anti-corruption<br />

Page 89 of 115


Page 90 of 115


Conflicts of Interest<br />

A Conflict of Interest is a situation in which a person or organization is involved in multiple<br />

interests (financial, emotional, or otherwise), one of which could possibly corrupt the<br />

motivation of the individual or organization.<br />

The presence of a<br />

conflict of interest is independent of<br />

the<br />

occurrence of impropriety. Therefore,<br />

a<br />

conflict of interest can be discovered<br />

and voluntarily defused before any<br />

corruption occurs. A widely used<br />

definition is: "A conflict of<br />

interest is a set of circumstances<br />

that creates a risk that professional judgement or actions<br />

regarding a primary interest will be unduly influenced by a<br />

secondary interest." Primary interest refers to the principal<br />

goals of the profession or activity, such as the protection of<br />

clients, the health of patients, the integrity of research,<br />

and the<br />

duties of public office. Secondary interest includes not<br />

only financial gain but also such motives as the desire for professional advancement and the wish<br />

to do favours for family and friends, but conflict of interest rules usually focus on financial<br />

relationships because they are relatively more objective, fungible, and quantifiable. The<br />

secondary interests are not treated as wrong in themselves, but become objectionable when they<br />

are believed to have greater weight than the primary interests. The conflict in a conflict of<br />

interest exists whether or not a particular individual is actually influenced by the secondary<br />

interest. It exists if the circumstances are reasonably believed (on the basis of past experience<br />

and objective evidence) to create a risk that decisions may be unduly influenced by secondary<br />

interests.<br />

The following are the most common forms of conflicts of interests:<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

Self-dealing, in which an official who controls an organization causes it to enter into a<br />

transaction with the official, or with another organization that benefits the official only.<br />

The official is on both sides of the "deal."<br />

Outside employment, in which the interests of one job conflict with another.<br />

Nepotism, in which a spouse, child, or other close relative is employed (or applies for<br />

employment) by an individual, or where goods or services are purchased from a relative<br />

or from a firm controlled by a relative. To avoid nepotism in hiring, many employment<br />

applications ask if the applicant is related to a current employee of the company. This<br />

allows recusal if the employed relative has a role in the hiring process. If this is the case,<br />

the relative could then recuse from any hiring decisions.<br />

Gifts from friends who also do business with the person receiving the gifts or from<br />

individuals or corporations who do business with the organization in which the gift<br />

recipient is employed. Such gifts may include non-tangible things of value such as<br />

transportation and lodging.<br />

Page 91 of 115


Pump and dump, in which a stock broker who owns a security artificially inflates the<br />

price by "upgrading" it or spreading rumors, sells the security and adds short position,<br />

then "downgrades" the security or spreads negative rumors to push the price down.<br />

Other improper acts that are sometimes classified as conflicts of interests are probably better<br />

classified elsewhere. Accepting bribes can be classified as corruption. Use of government or<br />

corporate property or assets for personal use is fraud. Nor should unauthorized distribution of<br />

confidential information, in itself, be considered a conflict of interest. For these improper acts,<br />

there is no inherent conflict of roles (see above).<br />

COI is sometimes termed competition of interest rather than "conflict", emphasizing a<br />

connotation of natural competition between valid interests rather than violent conflict with its<br />

connotation of victimhood and unfair aggression. Nevertheless, denotatively, there is too much<br />

overlap between the terms to make any objective differentiation.<br />

Inherent Problems<br />

Self-Policing<br />

Self-policing of any group is also a conflict of interest. If any organization, such as a corporation<br />

or government bureaucracy, is asked to eliminate unethical behavior within their own group, it<br />

may be in their interest in the short run to eliminate the appearance of unethical behavior, rather<br />

than the behavior itself, by keeping any ethical breaches hidden, instead of exposing and<br />

correcting them. An exception occurs when the ethical breach is already known by the public. In<br />

that case, it could be in the group's interest to end the ethical problem to which the public has<br />

knowledge, but keep remaining breaches hidden.<br />

Government Officials<br />

Regulating conflict of interest in government is one of the aims of political ethics. Public<br />

officials are expected to put service to the public and their constituents ahead of their personal<br />

interests. Conflict of interest rules are intended to prevent officials from making decisions in<br />

circumstances that could reasonably be perceived as violating this duty of office. Rules in the<br />

executive branch tend to be stricter and easier to enforce than in the legislative branch. Two<br />

problems make legislative ethics of conflicts difficult and distinctive. First, as James Madison<br />

wrote, legislators should share a "communion of interests" with their constituents. Legislators<br />

cannot adequately represent the interests of constituents without also representing some of their<br />

own. As Senator Robert S. Kerr once said, "I represent the farmers of Oklahoma, although I have<br />

large farm interests. I represent the oil business in Oklahoma...and I am in the oil business...They<br />

don't want to send a man here who has no community of interest with them, because he wouldn't<br />

be worth a nickel to them." The problem is to distinguish special interests from the general<br />

interests of all constituents. Second, the "political interests" of legislatures include campaign<br />

contributions which they need to get elected, and which are generally not illegal and not the<br />

same as a bribe. But under many circumstances they can have the same effect. The problem here<br />

is how to keep the secondary interest in raising campaign funds from overwhelming what should<br />

be their primary interest—fulfilling the duties of office.<br />

Page 92 of 115


Politics in the United States is dominated in many ways by political campaign contributions<br />

Candidates are often not considered "credible" unless they have a campaign budget far beyond<br />

what could reasonably be raised from citizens of ordinary means. The impact of this money can<br />

be found in many places, most notably in studies of how campaign contributions affect<br />

legislative behavior. For example, the price of sugar in the United States has been roughly<br />

double the international price for over half a century. In the 1980s, this added $3 billion to the<br />

annual budget of U.S. consumers, according to Stern, who provided the following summary of<br />

one part of how this happens:<br />

Contributions from the sugar lobby,<br />

1983–1986<br />

Percent voting in 1985 against gradually reducing<br />

sugar subsidies<br />

> $5,000 100%<br />

$2,500–5,000 97%<br />

$1,000–2,500 68%<br />

$1–1,000 45%<br />

$0 20%<br />

This $3 billion translates into $41 per household per year. This is in essence a tax collected by a<br />

nongovernmental agency: It is a cost imposed on consumers by governmental decisions, but<br />

never considered in any of the standard data on tax collections.<br />

Stern notes that sugar interests contributed $2.6 million to political campaigns, representing well<br />

over $1,000 return for each $1 contributed to political campaigns. This, however, does not<br />

include the cost of lobbying. Lessig cites six different studies that consider the cost of lobbying<br />

with campaign contributions on a variety of issues considered in Washington, D.C. These studies<br />

produced estimates of the anticipated return on each $1 invested in lobbying and political<br />

campaigns that ranged from $6 to $220. Lessig notes that clients who pay tens of millions of<br />

dollars to lobbyists typically receive billions.<br />

Lessig insists that this does not mean that any legislator has sold his or her vote. One of several<br />

possible explanations Lessig gives for this phenomenon is that the money helped elect candidates<br />

more supportive of the issues pushed by the big money spent on lobbying and political<br />

campaigns. He notes that if any money perverts democracy, it is the large contributions beyond<br />

the budgets of citizens of ordinary means; small contributions from common citizens have long<br />

been considered supporting of democracy.<br />

When such large sums become virtually essential to a politician's future, it generates a<br />

substantive conflict of interest contributing to a fairly well documented distortion on the nation's<br />

priorities and policies.<br />

Beyond this, governmental officials, whether elected or not, often leave public service to work<br />

for companies affected by legislation they helped enact or companies they used to regulate or<br />

companies affected by legislation they helped enact. This practice is called the "revolving door".<br />

Former legislators and regulators are accused of (a) using inside information for their new<br />

employers or (b) compromising laws and regulations in hopes of securing lucrative employment<br />

Page 93 of 115


in the private sector. This possibility creates a conflict of interest for all public officials whose<br />

future may depend on the Revolving door.<br />

Mitigating Conflicts of Interest<br />

Disclosure<br />

Commonly, politicians and high-ranking government officials are required to disclose financial<br />

information—assets such as stock, debts such as loans, and/or corporate positions held, typically<br />

annually. To protect privacy (to some extent), financial figures are often disclosed in ranges such<br />

as "$100,000 to $500,000" and "over $2,000,000". Certain professionals are required either by<br />

rules related to their professional organization, or by statute, to disclose any actual or potential<br />

conflicts of interest. In some instances, the failure to provide full disclosure is a crime.<br />

However, there is limited evidence regarding the effect of conflict of interest disclosure despite<br />

its widespread acceptance. A 2012 study published in the Journal of the American Medical<br />

Association showed that routine disclosure of conflicts of interest by American medical school<br />

educators to pre-clinical medical students were associated with an increased desire among<br />

students for limitations in some industry relationships. However, there were no changes in the<br />

Page 94 of 115


perceptions of students about the value of disclosure, the influence of industry relationships on<br />

educational content, or the instruction by faculty with relevant conflicts of interest.<br />

And, an increasing line of research suggests that disclosure can have "perverse effects" or, at<br />

least, is not the panacea regulators often take it to be.<br />

Recusal for Conflict<br />

Those with a conflict of interest are expected to recuse themselves from (i.e., abstain from<br />

decisions where such a conflict exists). The imperative for recusal varies depending upon the<br />

circumstance and profession, either as common sense ethics, codified ethics, or by statute. For<br />

example, if the governing board of a government agency is considering hiring a consulting firm<br />

for some task, and one firm being considered has, as a partner, a close relative of one of the<br />

board's members, then that board member should not vote on which firm is to be selected. In<br />

fact, to minimize any conflict, the board member should not participate in any way in the<br />

decision, including discussions.<br />

Judges are supposed to recuse themselves from cases when personal conflicts of interest may<br />

arise. For example, if a judge has participated in a case previously in some other judicial role<br />

he/she is not allowed to try that case. Recusal is also expected when one of the lawyers in a case<br />

might be a close personal friend, or when the outcome of the case might affect the judge directly,<br />

such as whether a car maker is obliged to recall a model that a judge drives. This is required by<br />

law under Continental civil law systems and by the Rome Statute, organic law of the<br />

International Criminal Court.<br />

Third-Party Evaluations<br />

Consider a situation where the owner of a majority of a public companies decides to buy out the<br />

minority shareholders and take the corporation private. What is a fair price? Obviously it is<br />

improper (and, typically, illegal) for the majority owner to simply state a price and then have the<br />

(majority-controlled) board of directors approve that price. What is typically done is to hire an<br />

independent firm (a third party), well-qualified to evaluate such matters, to calculate a "fair<br />

price", which is then voted on by the minority shareholders.<br />

Third-party evaluations may also be used as proof that transactions were, in fact, fair ("arm'slength").<br />

For example, a corporation that leases an office building that is owned by the CEO<br />

might get an independent evaluation showing what the market rate is for such leases in the<br />

locale, to address the conflict of interest that exists between the fiduciary duty of the CEO (to the<br />

stockholders, by getting the lowest rent possible) and the personal interest of that CEO (to<br />

maximize the income that the CEO gets from owning that office building by getting the highest<br />

rent possible).<br />

Conclusion<br />

Generally, conflicts of interests should be eliminated. Often, however, the specifics can be<br />

controversial. Should therapists, such as psychiatrists, be allowed to have extra-professional<br />

Page 95 of 115


elations with patients, or ex-patients? Should a faculty member be allowed to have an extraprofessional<br />

relationship with a student, and should that depend on whether the student is in a<br />

class of, or being advised by, the faculty member?<br />

Codes of ethics help to minimize problems with conflicts of interests because they can spell out<br />

the extent to which such conflicts should be avoided, and what the parties should do where such<br />

conflicts are permitted by a code of ethics (disclosure, recusal, etc.). Thus, professionals cannot<br />

claim that they were unaware that their improper behavior was unethical. As importantly, the<br />

threat of disciplinary action (for example, a lawyer being disbarred) helps to minimize<br />

unacceptable conflicts or improper acts when a conflict is unavoidable.<br />

Since codes of ethics cannot cover all situations, some governments have established an office of<br />

the ethics commissioner, who can be appointed by the legislature and report to the legislature.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Disqualification<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> disqualification, also referred to as recusal, refers to the act of abstaining from<br />

participation in an official action such as a legal proceeding due to a conflict of interest of the<br />

presiding court official or administrative officer. Applicable statutes or canons of ethics may<br />

provide standards for recusal in a given proceeding or matter. Providing that the judge or<br />

presiding officer must be free from disabling conflicts of interest makes the fairness of the<br />

proceedings less likely to be questioned.<br />

Recusal Generally<br />

In the United States, the term "recusal" is used most often with respect to court proceedings. Two<br />

sections of Title 28 of the United States Code (the <strong>Judicial</strong> Code) provide standards for judicial<br />

disqualification or recusal. Section 455, captioned "Disqualification of justice, judge, or<br />

magistrate judge," provides that a federal judge "shall disqualify himself in any proceeding in<br />

which his impartiality might reasonably be questioned." The section also provides that a judge is<br />

disqualified "where he has a personal bias or prejudice concerning a party, or personal<br />

knowledge of disputed evidentiary facts concerning the proceeding"; when the judge has<br />

previously served as a lawyer or witness concerning the same case or has expressed an opinion<br />

concerning its outcome; or when the judge or a member of his or her immediate family has a<br />

financial interest in the outcome of the proceeding.<br />

28 U.S.C. Section 144, captioned "Bias or prejudice of judge," provides that under<br />

circumstances, when a party to a case in a United States District Court files a "timely and<br />

sufficient Motion that the judge before whom the matter is pending has a personal bias or<br />

prejudice either against him or in favor of an adverse party," the case shall be transferred to<br />

another judge.<br />

The General Rule is that, to warrant recusal, a judge's expression of an opinion about the merits<br />

of a case, or his familiarity with the facts or the parties, must have originated in a source outside<br />

the case itself. This is referred to in the United States as the "extra-judicial source rule" and was<br />

Page 96 of 115


ecognized as a general presumption, although not an invariable one, in the 1994 U.S. Supreme<br />

Court decision in Liteky v. United States.<br />

At times justices or judges will recuse themselves sua sponte (on their own motion), recognizing<br />

that facts leading to their disqualification are present. However, where such facts exist, a party to<br />

the case may suggest recusal. Generally, each judge is the arbiter of a motion for the judge's<br />

recusal, which is addressed to the judge's conscience and discretion. However, where lower<br />

courts are concerned, an erroneous refusal to recuse in a clear case can be reviewed on appeal or,<br />

under extreme circumstances, by a petition for a writ of prohibition.<br />

In certain special situations, circumstances, that would otherwise call for recusal of a judge or<br />

group of judges, may be disregarded, when otherwise no judge would be available to hear the<br />

case. For example, if a case concerns a salary increase payable to a judge, that judge would<br />

ordinarily be disqualified from hearing the case. However, if the pay increase is applicable to all<br />

of the judges in the court system, the judge will keep the case, because the grounds for recusal<br />

would be equally applicable to any other judge. The principle that a judge will not be<br />

disqualified when the effect would be that no judge could hear the case is sometimes referred to<br />

as the "rule of necessity".<br />

Supreme Court Cases<br />

In the Supreme Court of the United States, the Justices typically recuse themselves from<br />

participating in cases in which they have financial interests. For example, Justice Sandra Day<br />

O'Connor generally did not participate in cases involving telecommunications firms because she<br />

owned stock in these firms, and Justice Stephen Breyer has disqualified himself in some cases<br />

involving insurance companies because of his participation in a Lloyd's of London syndicate.<br />

Justices also have declined to participate in cases in which close relatives, such as their children,<br />

are lawyers for one of the parties. On occasion, recusal occurs under more unusual<br />

circumstances; for example, in two cases, Chief Justice William H. Rehnquist stepped down<br />

from the bench when cases were argued by Arizona attorney James Brosnahan, who had testified<br />

against Rehnquist at his confirmation hearing in 1986. Whatever the reason for recusal, the<br />

United States Reports will record that the named justice "took no part in the consideration or<br />

decision of this case."<br />

Historically, standards for recusal in the Supreme Court and lower courts were less rigorous than<br />

they have become in more recent years. In the 1803 case of Marbury v. Madison, Chief Justice<br />

John Marshall participated in the decision and authored the opinion of the Court even though<br />

Marshall's actions as Secretary of State two years prior could be seen as the subject of the<br />

proceeding. On the other hand, Marshall did recuse himself in both the 1813 and 1816 hearings<br />

of Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, despite its equally significant constitutional implications, as he and<br />

his brother had contracted with Martin to buy the land in dispute. Moreover, during the 19th<br />

century, the U.S. federal court system was structured so that an appeal from a judge's decision<br />

was often heard by an appellate panel containing the same judge, who was expected to sit in<br />

impartial review of his own earlier ruling. This situation is no longer permissible, and 28 U.S.C.<br />

Sec. 47 provides that "No judge shall hear or determine an appeal from the decision of a case or<br />

issue tried by him."<br />

Page 97 of 115


One of notable dispute over recusal in U.S. Supreme Court history took place in 1946, when<br />

Justice Hugo Black participated in deciding the Jewell Ridge Coal case, although a former law<br />

partner of Black argued for the prevailing side. The losing party in the 5–4 decision sought<br />

reargument on the ground that Black should have been disqualified; Black declined to recuse<br />

himself and the decision stood, but Justice Robert H. Jackson wrote a short opinion suggesting<br />

that the decision that Black should sit in the case was Black's alone and the Court did not endorse<br />

it. The dispute aggravated infighting between Black and Jackson, and it has been suggested that<br />

this was one of the reasons that, when Chief Justice Harlan Fiske Stone died, President Harry S.<br />

Truman appointed Fred M. Vinson to succeed Stone rather than promote a sitting Associate<br />

Justice to Chief Justice.<br />

In 1973, then-Associate Justice Rehnquist wrote a lengthy in-chambers opinion declining to<br />

recuse himself in Laird v. Tatum, a case challenging the validity of certain arrests, even though<br />

Rehnquist had previously served as a White House lawyer and opined that the arrest program<br />

was valid. In 2004, Justice Antonin Scalia wrote an opinion declining to recuse himself in a case<br />

to which Vice President Dick Cheney was a party in his official capacity, despite the contention<br />

of several environmental groups that Scalia's participation created an appearance of impropriety<br />

because Scalia had recently participated in a widely publicized hunting trip with the Vice<br />

President. The same year, however, Scalia recused himself without explanation in Elk Grove<br />

Unified School District v. Newdow, a First Amendment case challenging inclusion of the words<br />

"under God" in the Pledge of Allegiance, after giving a public speech in which Scalia stated his<br />

view that Newdow's claims were meritless.<br />

Other Federal Cases<br />

In 1974, Black federal Judge Leon Higginbotham issued his decision in Comm. of Pa. v. Local<br />

542, Int'l Union of Operating Engineers, explaining why he as an African American judge with a<br />

history of active involvement in the civil rights struggle was not obligated to recuse himself from<br />

presiding over litigation concerning claims of racial discrimination. He held, in an opinion that<br />

was followed by later judges, including a series of Black judges who faced recusal requests, that<br />

if a judge could be forced to step aside from a case merely because of their membership in a<br />

group that was the subject of discrimination, minorities would constantly be removed from cases.<br />

Jewish federal Judge Paul Borman relied on the Higginbotham opinion in part in his 2014<br />

decision not to recuse himself from the trial of Palestinian-American Rasmea Odeh. Similarly, in<br />

1994, Jewish then-federal-Judge Michael Mukasey refused to recuse himself in a case<br />

concerning the 1993 World Trade Center bombing, warning that the demand for his recusal<br />

would ―disqualify not only an obscure district judge such as the author of this opinion, but also<br />

Justices Brandeis and Frankfurter … each having been both a Jew and a Zionist.‖<br />

Administrative Agency and Other Matters<br />

Outside the judicial system, the concept of recusal is also applied in administrative agencies.<br />

When a member of a multi-member administrative body is recused, the remaining members<br />

typically determine the outcome. When the sole occupant of an official position is recused, the<br />

matter may be delegated to the official's deputy or to a temporarily designated official; for<br />

Page 98 of 115


example, when the Solicitor General of the United States is recused from a case, the Deputy<br />

Solicitor General will handle the matter in his or her place.<br />

Concepts analogous to recusal also exist in the legislative branch. The rules of the United States<br />

Senate and House of Representatives provide that a Member should not vote on a measure as to<br />

which he or she has a personal financial interest. In such cases, the Senator or Representative<br />

may record a vote of "present" rather than "yea" or "nay".<br />

International Standards of Recusal<br />

Laws or court rules provide the recusal of judges. Although the details vary, the following are<br />

nearly universal grounds for recusal.<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

The judge is related to a party, attorney, or spouse of either party (usually) within three<br />

degrees of kinship.<br />

The judge is a party.<br />

The judge is a material witness unless pleading purporting to make the Judge a party is<br />

false (determined by presiding judge, but see Substitution (law)).<br />

The judge has previously acted in the case in question as an attorney for a party, or<br />

participated in some other capacity.<br />

The judge prepared any legal instrument (such as a contract or will) whose validity or<br />

construction is at issue.<br />

Appellate judge previously handled case as a trial judge.<br />

The judge has personal or financial interest in the outcome. This particular ground varies<br />

by jurisdiction. Some require recusal if there is any interest at all in the outcome, while<br />

others only require recusal if there is interest beyond a certain value.<br />

The judge determines he or she cannot act impartially.<br />

Consequences for Non-Recusal<br />

A judge who has grounds to recuse himself is expected to do so. If a judge does not know that<br />

grounds exist to recuse themselves (but does) the error is harmless. If a judge does not recuse<br />

themselves when they should have known to do so, they may be subject to sanctions, which vary<br />

by jurisdiction. Depending on the jurisdiction, if an appellate court finds a judgment to have been<br />

made when the judge in question should have been recused, it may set aside the judgment and<br />

return the case for retrial.<br />

Waiver & Substitution<br />

The recusal rule may be avoided or ignored if all parties and the judge agree, although in practice<br />

this rarely occurs. If recusal is avoided in this manner, a full and complete record of the facts that<br />

qualify as grounds, above, must be made for the appellate court.<br />

If a judge fails to recuse themselves sua sponte and a party believes the judge has a bias the party<br />

may motion for substitution. In some jurisdictions litigants may have the right to substitute a<br />

judge, even if no bias is demonstrated.<br />

Page 99 of 115


International Case Law Standard for Recusal – Landmark Case<br />

R v Sussex Justices, Ex parte McCarthy ([1924] 1 KB 256, [1923] All ER Rep 233) is a leading<br />

English case on the impartiality and recusal of judges. It is famous for its precedence in<br />

establishing the principle that the mere appearance of bias is sufficient to overturn a judicial<br />

decision. It also brought into common parlance the oft-quoted aphorism "Not only must Justice<br />

be done; it must also be seen to be done."<br />

In 1923 McCarthy, a motorcyclist, was involved in a road accident which resulted in his<br />

prosecution before a magistrates court for dangerous driving. Unknown to the defendant and his<br />

solicitor, the clerk to the justices was a member of the firm of solicitors acting in a civil claim<br />

against the defendant arising out of the accident that had given rise to the prosecution. The clerk<br />

retired with the justices, who returned to convict the defendant.<br />

On learning of the clerk's provenance, the defendant applied to have the conviction quashed. The<br />

justices swore affidavits stating that they had reached their decision to convict the defendant<br />

without consulting their clerk.<br />

The appeal was essentially one of judicial review and was heard at the King's Bench division by<br />

Lord Chief Justice Hewart. In a landmark and far-reaching judgement, Lord Hewart CJ said:<br />

“<br />

It<br />

is said, and, no doubt, truly, that when that gentleman retired in the<br />

usual way with the justices, taking with him the notes of the evidence<br />

in case the justices might desire to consult him, the justices came to a<br />

conclusion without consulting him, and that he scrupulously abstained<br />

from referring to the case in any way. But while that is so, a long line<br />

of cases shows that it is not merely of some importance but is of<br />

fundamental importance that justice should not only be done, but<br />

should manifestly and undoubtedly be seen to be done.<br />

The question therefore is not whether in this case the deputy clerk<br />

made any observation or offered any criticism which he might not<br />

properly have made or offered; the question is whether he was so<br />

related to the case in its civil aspect as to be unfit to act as clerk to the<br />

justices in the criminal matter. The answer to that question depends<br />

not upon what actually was done but upon what might appear to be<br />

done.<br />

Nothing is to be done which creates even a suspicion that there has<br />

been an improper interference with the course of justice. Speaking for<br />

myself, I accept the statements contained in the justices' affidavit, but<br />

they show very clearly that the deputy clerk was connected with the<br />

case in a capacity which made it right that he should scrupulously<br />

abstain from referring to the matter in any way, although he retired<br />

”<br />

Page 100 of 115


with the justices; in other words, his one position was such that he<br />

could not, if he had been required to do so, discharge the duties which<br />

his other position involved. His twofold position was a manifest<br />

contradiction.<br />

In those circumstances I am satisfied that this conviction must be<br />

quashed, unless it can be shown that the applicant or his solicitor was<br />

aware of the point that might be taken, refrained from taking it, and<br />

took his chance of an acquittal on the facts, and then, on a conviction<br />

being recorded, decided to take the point. On the facts I am satisfied<br />

that there has been no waiver of the irregularity, and, that being so, the<br />

rule must be made absolute and the conviction quashed.<br />

The ruling is derived from the principle of natural justice and has been followed throughout the<br />

world in countries that use the English legal system. It has been applied in many diverse<br />

situations, including immigration cases, professional disciplinary cases, domestic tribunals such<br />

as members' clubs, and perhaps most famously in the Pinochet case, where the House of Lords<br />

overturned its own decision on the grounds of Lord Hoffman's conflict of interest.<br />

Page 101 of 115


Page 102 of 115


<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism is judicial rulings suspected of being based on personal or political<br />

considerations rather than on existing law. It is sometimes used as an antonym of judicial<br />

restraint. The definition of judicial activism, and which specific decisions are activist, is a<br />

controversial political issue, particularly in the United States. The question of judicial activism is<br />

closely related to constitutional interpretation, statutory construction, and separation of powers.<br />

Arthur Schlesinger Jr. introduced the term "<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism" in a January 1947<br />

Fortune magazine article titled "The Supreme Court: 1947".<br />

The phrase has been controversial since its beginning. An<br />

article by Craig Green, "An Intellectual History of <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Activism," is critical of Schlesinger's use of the term;<br />

"Schlesinger's original introduction of judicial<br />

activism was doubly blurred: not only did he<br />

fail to explain what counts as activism, he<br />

also declined to say whether activism<br />

is good or bad."<br />

Even before this phrase was first<br />

used, the general concept already<br />

existed. For example, Thomas Jefferson referred to the "despotic behaviour" of Federalist federal<br />

judges, in particular, John Marshall.<br />

Black's Law Dictionary defines judicial activism as a "philosophy of judicial decision-making<br />

whereby judges allow their personal views about public policy, among other factors, to guide<br />

their decisions."<br />

Political science professor Bradley Canon has posited six dimensions along which judge courts<br />

may be perceived as activist: majoritarianism, interpretive stability, interpretive fidelity,<br />

substance/democratic process, specificity of policy, and availability of an alternate policymaker.<br />

David Strauss has argued that judicial activism can be narrowly defined as one or more of three<br />

possible actions: overturning laws as unconstitutional, overturning judicial precedent, and ruling<br />

against a preferred interpretation of the constitution.<br />

Others have been less confident of the term's meaning, finding it instead to be little more than a<br />

rhetorical shorthand. Kermit Roosevelt III has argued that "in practice 'activist' turns out to be<br />

little more than a rhetorically charged shorthand for decisions the speaker disagrees with";<br />

likewise, the solicitor general under George W. Bush, Theodore Olson, said in an interview on<br />

Fox News Sunday, in regards to a case for same-sex marriage he had successfully litigated, that<br />

"most people use the term 'judicial activism' to explain decisions that they don't like." Supreme<br />

Page 103 of 115


Court Justice Anthony Kennedy has said that, "An activist court is a court that makes a decision<br />

you don't like."<br />

The Great <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism Debate<br />

Detractors of judicial activism charge that it usurps the power of the elected branches of<br />

government or appointed agencies, damaging the rule of law and democracy. Defenders of<br />

judicial activism say that in many cases it is a legitimate form of judicial review, and that the<br />

interpretation of the law must change with changing times.<br />

A third view is that so-called "objective" interpretation of the law does not exist. According to<br />

law professor Brian Z. Tamanaha, "Throughout the so-called formalist age, it turns out, many<br />

prominent judges and jurists acknowledged that there were gaps and uncertainties in the law and<br />

that judges must sometimes make choices."<br />

Some proponents of a stronger judiciary argue that the judiciary helps provide checks and<br />

balances and should grant itself an expanded role to counterbalance the effects of transient<br />

majoritarianism, i.e., there should be an increase in the powers of a branch of government which<br />

is not directly subject to the electorate, so that the majority cannot dominate or oppress any<br />

particular minority through its elective powers. Other scholars have proposed that judicial<br />

activism is most appropriate when it restrains the tendency of democratic majorities to act out of<br />

passion and prejudice rather than after reasoned deliberation.<br />

Moreover, they argue that the judiciary strikes down both elected and unelected official action, in<br />

some instances acts of legislative bodies reflecting the view the transient majority may have had<br />

at the moment of passage and not necessarily the view the same legislative body may have at the<br />

time the legislation is struck down. Also, the judges that are appointed are usually appointed by<br />

previously elected executive officials so that their philosophy should reflect that of those who<br />

nominated them, that an independent judiciary is a great asset to civil society since special<br />

interests are unable to dictate their version of constitutional interpretation with threat of stopping<br />

political donations.<br />

Landmark Cases in <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

The following are [cases] cited as examples of judicial activism:<br />

1. R v Sussex Justices, ex p McCarthy<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

Brown v. Board of Education – 1954 Supreme Court ruling ordering the desegregation of<br />

public schools.<br />

Roe v. Wade – 1973 Supreme Court ruling decriminalizing abortion.<br />

Bush v. Gore – The United States Supreme Court case between the major-party<br />

candidates in the 2000 presidential election, George W. Bush and Al Gore. The judges<br />

voted 5-4 to halt the recount of ballots in Florida and, as a result, George Bush was<br />

elected President.<br />

Page 104 of 115


Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission – 2010 Supreme Court decision<br />

declaring Congressionally enacted limitations on corporate political spending and<br />

transparency as unconstitutional restrictions on free speech.<br />

Hollingsworth v. Perry – 2013 decision by federal judge Vaughn R. Walker overturning<br />

California's constitutional amendment to ban same-sex marriage.<br />

Contempt of Court and disqualification of Pakistani Prime Minister Yusuf Raza Gilani by<br />

the Supreme Court of Pakistan chief justice Iftikhar Muhammad Chaudhry.<br />

2. R v Bow Street Metropolitan Stipendiary Magistrate, ex p Pinochet<br />

(No 2)<br />

R v Bow Street Metropolitan Stipendiary Magistrate, Ex Parte Pinochet Ugarte (No 2) was an<br />

English legal case which involved the unprecedented setting aside of a House of Lords judgment<br />

based upon the possibility of bias. Lord Hoffmann's failure to declare links to Amnesty<br />

International meant that a previous House of Lords judgment on the immunity of former Chilean<br />

dictator General Augusto Pinochet had to be set aside.<br />

Page 105 of 115


Page 106 of 115


References<br />

1. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_reform<br />

2. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Judiciary<br />

3. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Supreme_court<br />

4. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_independence<br />

5. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Judiciary_of_Russia<br />

6. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Law_reform<br />

7. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_review<br />

8. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_review_in_the_United_States<br />

9. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rule_of_law<br />

10. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Political_corruption<br />

11. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_disqualification<br />

12. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/<strong>Judicial</strong>_activism<br />

13. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_landmark_court_decisions_in_the_United_States<br />

14. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Conflict_of_interest<br />

15. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/R_v_Sussex_Justices,_ex_p_McCarthy<br />

16. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/R_v_Bow_Street_Metropolitan_Stipendiary_Magistrate,_ex<br />

_p_Pinochet_%28No_2%29<br />

17. http://iosrjournals.org/iosr-jhss/papers/Vol19-issue2/Version-4/C019242025.pdf<br />

18. http://www.texaslrev.com/wp-content/uploads/Stone-89-TLR-1423.pdf<br />

19. http://regentuniversity.org/acad/schlaw/student_life/studentorgs/lawreview/docs/issues/v<br />

14n1/Vol.%2014,%20No.%201,%205%20Jones.pdf<br />

Page 107 of 115


Page 108 of 115


Attachment A<br />

The Role of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

Page 109 of 115


IOSR Journal Of Humanities And Social Science (IOSR-JHSS)<br />

Volume 19, Issue 2, Ver. IV (Feb. 2014), PP 20-25<br />

e-ISSN: 2279-0837, p-ISSN: 2279-0845.<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

“The Role of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism in the Implementation and<br />

Promotion of Constitutional Laws and Influence of <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Overactivism”<br />

Vipin Kumar (NET, M.Phil.),<br />

Research Scholar, Shri Venkateshwara University, Rajabpur, Gajraula (UP) Address- near K.G.K (P G)<br />

College Dev Vihar Colony, Line Par, Moradabad, Mob- 945806777, 8194005705<br />

Abstract: <strong>Judicial</strong> activism is today one of the most misused constitutional terms. India practices<br />

constitutionaldemocracy with emphasis on constitutionalism. This comes with it to high rates of political<br />

activities with misuse of political powers granted in the Constitution by the political actors. Naturally, the court<br />

is called upon to wear its active posture and interpret theConstitution as it affects the political class. However,<br />

each decision of the courts interpreting the constitution against the political class is met with cries of “judicial<br />

activism” from one side of the political spectrum or the other. The other cry seems to be that the courts are<br />

encroaching into the domain of the political class thereby violating the doctrine of political questions which is<br />

essentially a function of separation of powers. The paper sees these terms as being misused and makes an<br />

analytical exposition of the term and judicial intervention into political questions in India. It contends that<br />

courts should ensure the limits of governmental action under the principles of a constitutional democracy, even<br />

in the delicate field of internal affairs of governmental institutions. For this purpose, various constitutional<br />

provisions and judicial decisions are examined.<br />

Key Words: <strong>Judicial</strong> activism, constitutional democracy , separation of powers, constitutional provisions ,<br />

I. Introduction:-<br />

Today judicial activism has touched almost each and every aspect of life ranges from human rights<br />

issues to maintenance of public roads! <strong>Judicial</strong> activism means the power of the Supreme Court and the high<br />

court but not the sub-ordinate courts to declare the laws as unconstitutional and void. If it infringes or if the law<br />

is inconsistent with one or more provisions of the constitution. To the extent of such inconsistency while<br />

declaring a law as constitutional and void the courts do not suggest any alternative measures.<br />

The term judicial activism despites its popularity to amongst legal experts, judges, scholars and<br />

politicians has not until recently been given an appropriate definition of what the term should mean so that it<br />

will not be subject to abuse. 1 The effect of this has been a misconception about what the term is all about. 2<br />

This therefore creates series of definitions about the concept. Although definitions are usually products of<br />

individual idiosyncrasies and it‟s often influenced by the individual perception or world view, a<br />

combination of various definitions gives a description of the concept.<br />

the <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism as innovative, dynamic and law making role of the Court with a forward looking<br />

attitude discarding reliance on old cases, and also mechanical, conservative and static views. It is the creative<br />

thought process through which the court displays vigour, enter- prise, initiative pulsating with the urge of<br />

creating new and refined principles of law. It means when the Court plays a positive role the court is said to be<br />

exhibiting the „<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism‟. There are different opinions about the origin of doctrine of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism.<br />

Some scholars like Justice M.N. Roy believe that it is born in 1804 when Chief Justice Marshall, the greatest<br />

judge of English-speaking world, decided Marbury V Madison. But P.P. Vijayan differs with saying that<br />

Marbury V Madison is a case of <strong>Judicial</strong> Review and not of a <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism. However he opines that the<br />

judicial activism has a hoary past in Dr. Bonham‟s case in which Justice Coke derived doctrine of natural justice<br />

in the year 1610. In this context Dr. Suresh Mane observed that “As a result English Courts by its interpretation<br />

role extended the necessary protection; but truly, the movement of judicial activism got momentum on the soil<br />

ofAmerica under the shadow of first ever written Constitution.” 1 The role of the judiciary in a modern legal<br />

system is immense social significance.... Law is in a constant process of flux and development, and though<br />

much of this development is due to the enactment of the legislature, the judges and the courts have an essential<br />

role to play in developing the law and adopting it to the needs of the Society. 3<br />

Paul Mahoney in offering his own definition of the concept submits that judicial activism exists where<br />

the judges modified the law from what was previously stated to be the existing law which often leads to<br />

substituting their own decisions from that of the elected representatives of the people. 4 This definition would<br />

consider invalid actions or decisions of the judges given for the purpose of seeking the justice in a particular<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

20 | Page


“The Role Of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism In The Implementation And Promotion Of Constitutional Laws And<br />

case or to interpret the law insuch a way as to conform to social realities thereby not permitting the correction of<br />

mistakes in the previous jurisprudence of law. 5<br />

Famous Author SubhashKashyap says, “What has come to be called hyper activism of the judiciary<br />

draws its strength, Relevance and legitimacy from the inactivity, incompetence, disregard of law and<br />

constitution, criminal negligence, corruption, greed for power and money, utter indiscipline and lack of<br />

character and integrity among the leaders, ministers and administrators. As a result of this a vacuum was created<br />

in which the governmental machinery seemed to be totally helpless with the corruption in legislative and<br />

executive fields. The vacuum was filled in by the judiciary”.<br />

A contrary view has also been offered that the judicial activism becomes the most valuable<br />

instrument when the legislative machinery comes to a halt in a case. 6 Thus, where legislative machinery could<br />

not apply to a given situation, judicial activism appears to be the most valuable instrument. In other words,<br />

judges should not be scared of adjudicating a particular case because the law has not been enacted by the<br />

legislature to cover the situation. This therefore justifies the application of judicial creativity in the matter.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism in India: The significant feature of Indian Constitution is partial separation of powers. -The<br />

doctrine of separation of powers was propounded by the French Jurist, Montesquieu. It is partly adopted tit India<br />

since the executive powers are vested in the president, Legislative powers tit the Parliament and the judicial<br />

powers in the Supreme Court and subordinate courts. The role of separation of powers in India is simple. The<br />

three organs of the Government viz. the Executive, Legislature and the Judiciary are not independently<br />

independent but inter-dependently independent. (The executive encroaches upon judicial power, while<br />

appointing the judges of Supreme Court and High Courts. Similarly the Judiciary, by its review power examines<br />

the law passed by file legislature parliament and the legislature also, intervenes in respect of impeachment of the<br />

president).<br />

As stated earlier, the <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism tit India can he witnessed with reference to the review power of<br />

the Supreme Court and High Court under Art. 32 and 226 of the Constitution particularly in public interest<br />

litigation cases. The Supreme Court played crucial role in formulating several principles in public interest<br />

litigation cases. For instance, the principle of "absolute liability" was propounded in Oleum Gas Leak case.<br />

Public Trust Doctrine in Kamalnath Case (1998 I SCC .388) etc.<br />

Further, the Supreme Court, gave variety of guidelines in various cases of public interest litigation. eg:<br />

Ratlam Municipality Case, Oleum Gas Leak Case, Ganga Pollution Case etc.<br />

In India the concept originated after a public interest litigation was filed before the supreme court<br />

when the then Chief justice P N Bhagwati took an unknown case directly from the public who did not had any<br />

involvement in the case but it was just for the public welfare and also was related to public in large. Justice<br />

P N Bhagwati has said that “One basic and fundamental question that confronts every democracy, run by a<br />

rule of law is, what is the role or function of a judge. Is it the function of a judge merely to declare law as it<br />

exists-or to make law? And this question is very important, for on it depends the scope of judicial activism. The<br />

anglo-saxon tradition persists in the assertion that a judge does not make law; he merely interprets. Law is<br />

existing and eminent; the judge merely finds it. He merely reflects what the legislature has said. This is the<br />

photographic theory of the judicial function”. It is for the judge to give meaning to what the legislature has said<br />

and it is this process of interpretation which constitutes the most creative and thrilling function of a judge. In the<br />

initial years of 1950-67, the Supreme Court adopted the attitude of judicial restraint in which the court gave a<br />

strict and literal interpretation of the constitution.<strong>Judicial</strong> review in India was provided for expressly in the<br />

Constitution. Article 13, clause (1) says that all laws in force in the territory of India immediately before the<br />

commencement of the Constitution, in so far as they are inconsistent with the provisions containing the<br />

fundamental rights, shall, to the extent of such inconsistency, be void. Clause (2) of that article further says that<br />

the State shall not make any law that takes away or abridges any of the fundamental rights and any law made in<br />

contravention of the above mandate shall, to the extent of the contravention, be void. The Constitution also<br />

divides the legislative power between the Centre and the states and forbids either of them to encroach upon the<br />

power given to the other. Who is to decide whether a legislature or an executive has acted in excess of its<br />

powers or in contravention of any of the restrictions imposed by the Constitution on its power? Obviously, such<br />

function was assigned to the courts. The Constitution was criticized by some members of the Constituent<br />

Assembly for being a potential lawyers‟ paradise. Dr. B.R. Ambedkar defended the provisions of judicial<br />

review as being absolutely necessary and rejected the above criticism. According to him, the provisions for<br />

judicial review and particularly for the writ jurisdiction that gave quick relief against the abridgement of<br />

fundamental rights constituted the heart of the Constitution, the very soul of it. The nature and scope of judicial<br />

review was first examined by the Supreme Court in A.K. Gopalan case where it accepted the principle of<br />

judicial subordination to legislative wisdom. But on the whole it limited itself and exercised judicial restraint.<br />

The second phase unfolded with the Golaknath case which resulted in on open conflict between the judiciary<br />

and legislature. The parliament asserted its supremacy and the Supreme Court asserted its power of <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

21 | Page


“The Role Of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism In The Implementation And Promotion Of Constitutional Laws And<br />

Review, which resulted in a series of constitutional amendments in which the parliament tried to limit the power<br />

of <strong>Judicial</strong> review. In the Emergency of 1975-77, the judiciary was made subservient to the legislature and<br />

executive. In Golaknath case, the Supreme Court gave an unprecedented judgment, which was clearly a case of<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism. The reason of imposing emergency was the decision of Allahabad High Court setting aside<br />

the election of Prime Minister Indira Gandhi to the LokSabha. The 42nd constitutional Amendment Act was<br />

also passed which put new limitations on the judiciary. After the emergency the 44th constitutional Act was<br />

passed which restored the judiciary‟s position as it had existed before the emergency. In Minerva mills case the<br />

Supreme Court declared judicial review as part of the basic structure. Since 1980‟s we saw the emergence of<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism as a powerful tool in Indian Polity. Thus now we find that the Supreme Court is no longer<br />

exercising judicial restraint. But in fact, it has taken up <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism so much. A court giving new meaning<br />

to a provision so as to suit the changing social or economic conditions or expanding the horizons of the right of<br />

the individual is said to be an activist court. Thus has given birth to <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism. In the words of Justice J.<br />

S. Varma “The role of the Judiciary in interpreting existing laws according to the needs of the times and filling<br />

in the gaps appears to be the true meaning of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism. 7<br />

Present scenario of <strong>Judicial</strong> activism or <strong>Judicial</strong> overactivism:-<br />

Of late the Indian judiciary appears to have become overactive, and is often accused of judicial<br />

overreach. This accusation was usually leveled by politicians or others outside the judicial system, until in 2008<br />

it was leveled by Justice A.K. Mathur and the writer (as Judges of the Supreme Court) in Divisional Manager,<br />

Aravalli Golf Course v. Chander Haas.The Indian Supreme Court surely came a long way since Anwar Ali<br />

Sarkar Vs. State of West BengalAIR 1952 SC 75 and A.K. Gopalan Vs. State of Madras where the judiciary<br />

refused to indulge in making judicial policy and instead exercised judicial restraint keeping in mind the Doctrine<br />

of Separation of Powers. However, the pendulum later swung to the opposite direction. Thus, in Maneka<br />

Gandhi vs. Union of India AIR 1978 SC 593 the 7 Judge Bench of the Indian Supreme Court, while overruling<br />

the 5 Judge Bench decision in A.K. Gopalan‟scase introduced the due process clause in the Indian Constitution<br />

by a judicial pronouncement. In S. P. Gupta Vs. Union of India ,AIR 1982 SC 149 it was held that:“He [the<br />

judge] has to inject flesh and blood in the dry skeleton provided by the legislature and by a process of dynamic<br />

interpretation, invest it with a meaning which will harmonize the law with the prevailing concepts and values<br />

and make it an effective, instrument for delivery of justice.”<br />

Similarly, in the case of Supreme Court Advocates on Record Vs. Union of India,1993 4 SCC 44it was held<br />

that:“It belongs to the Judiciary to ascertain the meaning of the constitutional provisions and the laws enacted by<br />

the Legislature.”<br />

This was the advent of an over active judiciary which assumed upon itself the need to adjudicate even<br />

where it was not perceived to be warranted. Although Article 50 (8) of the Indian Constitution expressly provides<br />

for Separation of Powers between the different organs of the State, but time and again, the Indian Supreme<br />

Court has taken on itself the task of filling in the gaps created by the Legislature and the Executive to do<br />

„justice‟.<br />

While doing so, the judiciary has been often criticized for overstepping its limits. In the case of<br />

VineetNarainvs. Union of India, 1998 Cri. L. J. 1208 the Supreme Court had invented a new writ called<br />

“continuing mandamus” where it wanted to monitor the investigating agencies which were guilty of inaction to<br />

proceed against persons holding high offices in the executive who had committed offences. Furthermore, the<br />

Court created by its judicial order a body called the Central Vigilance Commission, which was not contemplated<br />

by the statute (the Delhi Special Police Establishment Act, 1946), for supervising the functioning of a statutory<br />

body, the Central Bureau of Investigation. The Court also laid down a number of guidelines for the<br />

appointments of chiefs of investigating agencies like Central Bureau of Investigation, Central Vigilance<br />

Commission and the Enforcement Directorate; apart from the Chiefs of the State Police. These guidelines, apart<br />

from being in relation to appointment, were also with regard to their status, transfer and tenure, etc. The<br />

question arises whether this was legitimate exercise of judicial power.In the case of Indian Council for Enviro-<br />

Legal Action Vs. Union of India, (1996) 5 SCC 281the Court passed various orders especially directed<br />

towards the States requiring them to submit management plans to control pollution to both, the Central<br />

Government as well as the Court. Here, the Court held that it was only discharging its judicial functions in<br />

ensuring that it remedies the errors of the executive.<br />

In the case of M. C. Mehta vs. Union of India, (2001) 3 SCC 763where a writ was filed with regard<br />

to the vehicular pollution in Delhi, the Supreme Court had passed directions for the phasing out of diesel buses<br />

and for the conversion to CNG. When these directions were not complied with due to shortage in supply of<br />

CNG, the Court held that orders and directions of the Court could not be nullified or modified by State or<br />

Central governments. This was a case where, despite several directions being given by the Supreme Court, the<br />

government did not act speedily in responding to the Order.<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

22 | Page


“The Role Of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism In The Implementation And Promotion Of Constitutional Laws And<br />

The Court has prescribed norms regarding the running of the prisons and mental intuitions , 9 instructed the<br />

Government to implement labor laws at construction sites, 10 recognised admissions in medical colleges<br />

throughout India laying down examination schedules, 11 prescribing hawking zones in metropolitan cities, 12 laid<br />

down the guidelines for the retail outlets for essential commodities such as LPG, 13 resolving disputes between<br />

public undertakings of Central Government, 14 directed the authorities like C.B.I to conduct and complete<br />

investigation expeditiously in cases of national importance, 15 directed the noxious factories to restart on the<br />

technical reports on safety measures, 16 prescribed the poverty limits for the low income urban housing 17 or set<br />

up an expert panel headed by a retired Supreme Court to study the vehicular pollution level 18 etc. In these<br />

decisions the court did legislate, but in the process was criticized for having infringed upon the executive<br />

domain.<br />

With due respect to these and other decisions it has to be said that many judges often forget that the<br />

judiciary cannot solve all problems in the country. Suppose the Court passes an order that from tomorrow<br />

poverty in India, or unemployment, or malnutrition etc. are abolished. Will these orders mean anything? Can<br />

they really be implemented? India is a poor country with limited financial resources. Moreover, many such<br />

orders e.g. for interlinking rivers vide In re Networking of Rivers (2012) 4 S.C.C. 51 raise great technical and<br />

administrative problems, and are really in the domain of the legislature or executive.<br />

The most recent case on judicial activism was the case of ArunaRamchandraShanbaugVs. Union of<br />

India and Others. JT 2011 (3) SC 300.ArunaShanbaug, a nurse in 1973, while working at a Hospital at<br />

Mumbai, was sexually assaulted and has been in a permanent vegetative state since the assault. In 2011, after<br />

she had been in this status for 37 years, the Supreme Court of India heard the petition to the plea for euthanasia<br />

filed by a social activist claiming to be Aruna‟s friend. The Court turned down the petition, but in its landmark<br />

judgment (authored by the writer) it allowed passive euthanasia i.e. withdrawal of life support to a person in<br />

permanently vegetative state, subject to approval by the High Court.<br />

II. Trends in <strong>Judicial</strong> Restraint:-<br />

Rising judicial activism was hindering governance in the country and impacting growth in Asia's third<br />

largest economy, finance minister P Chidambaram said.<br />

"Nowhere in the world would we see ideal balance between legislature and judiciary. But in India, we have seen<br />

intensifying judicial activism, which had impacted the balance of governance," Chidambaram said at The<br />

Economic Times Awards for Corporate Excellence.<br />

"The balance in India has swung away from the executive and the parliament," he said. "The judiciary has taken<br />

an upper hand. Unless the executive has a final say, we cannot have sustained high growth rate. Countries like<br />

China, Brazil and Mexico, with a stronger executive authority, have exhibited better growth trajectory," he<br />

argued.<br />

"<strong>Judicial</strong> institutions cannot take over governance. We must rediscover the balance between our<br />

institutions and we have to reassert the balance between reforms, development and institutions," Chidambaram<br />

said.<br />

Sounding a note of caution on judicial activism, The President of India Mr. Pranab Mukherjee said judicial<br />

pronouncements must respect the boundaries that separate the legislature, executive and judiciary. Making his<br />

first visit outside the national capital after assuming the office of President on July 25, Mukherjee also said that<br />

everything must be done to protect the independence of judiciary from any form of encroachment. Addressing<br />

the valedictory function of the 150th anniversary celebrations of the Madras High Court, he urged judiciary to<br />

keep reinventing itself through a process of introspection and self-correction at the same time. In his address,<br />

Mukherjee touched upon various issues that dominate legal discourse including judicial accountability and the<br />

appointment of judges. The President referred to judicial activism and said the judges through innovation and<br />

activism have contributed enormously to expanding the frontiers of justice and providing access to the poorest<br />

of the poor. 19<br />

The Supreme Court in an order has said that the judiciary must refrain from encroaching on legislative<br />

and executive domain otherwise it will boomerang in the form of political class stepping to clip their wings. A<br />

bench comprising Justice AK Mathur and Justice MarkandeyKatju said, "If the judiciary does not exercise<br />

restraint and over-stretches its limit there is bound to be reaction from politicians and others. The politicians will<br />

then step in and curtail the powers or even independence of the judiciary. The judiciary should, therefore,<br />

confine itself to its proper sphere, realizing that in a democracy many matters and controversies are best<br />

resolved in a non-judicial setting." The court said that justification often given for judicial encroachment into the<br />

domain of the executive or legislature is that the other two organs are not doing their jobs properly. Even<br />

assuming this is so, the same allegation can then be made against the judiciary too because there are cases<br />

pending in courts for half-a-century, bench said. If they are not discharging their assigned duties, the remedy is<br />

not judicial interference as it will violate delicate balance of power enshrined in the constitution, remarked the<br />

court. 20<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

23 | Page


“The Role Of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism In The Implementation And Promotion Of Constitutional Laws And<br />

There are many examples where judiciary had encroached upon the turf which was unwarranted. The<br />

Jagdambika Pal caseof 1998 involving UP legislative assembly and the Jharkhand assembly case of 2005 are<br />

the two glaring examples of deviations from the clearly provided constitutional scheme of separation of powers,<br />

said bench.<br />

There is broad (though not absolute) separation of powers in the Indian Constitution vide Divisional Manager,<br />

Aravali Golf Course vs. Chander Haas, 2008. The Constitution of India did not provide for the judiciary to<br />

be a super legislature or a substitute for the failure of the other two organs. Thus, the need arises for the<br />

judiciary to lay down its own limitations.<br />

Some people say that the judiciary can enter into the domain of the executive or legislature because these organs<br />

are not functioning properly. But then it can also be said that the judiciary, too, is not functioning properly, there<br />

is great delay in deciding cases, corruption in a section of the judiciary, etc. Should then the legislature or<br />

executive take over the judiciary‟s function?<br />

One of the examples of judicial restraint is the case of State of Rajasthan Vs. Union of India,AIR<br />

1977 SC 1361, in which the court rejected the petition on the ground that it involved a political question and<br />

therefore the court would not go into the matter. In S.R. Bommai Vs. Union of India,(1994) 3 SCC 1, the<br />

judges said that there are certain situations where the political element dominates and no judicial review is<br />

possible. The exercise of power under Art.356 was a political question and therefore the judiciary should not<br />

interfere. Ahmadi J. said that it was difficult to evolve judicially manageable norms to scrutinize the political<br />

decisions and if the courts do it then it would be entering the political thicket and questioning the political<br />

wisdom, which the court must avoid. 21<br />

In Almitra H. Patel Vs. Union of India, (2000) 2 SCC 679, where the issue was whether directions should be<br />

issued to the Municipal Corporation regarding how to make Delhi clean, the Court held that it was not for the<br />

Supreme Court to direct them as to how to carry out their most basic functions and resolve their difficulties, and<br />

that the Court could only direct the authorities to carry out their duties in accordance with what has been<br />

assigned to them by law. Also, in Union of India Vs. Kishan K. Sharma, (2004) 5 SCC 518,when the High<br />

Court issued a Mandamus to the Government to pay a particular scale to its officers, the Supreme Court laying<br />

down the boundaries of judicial activism in general held that such Mandamus would not be permissible as<br />

fixation of salaries was an administrative decision. Similarly, creation of a post is an administrative or<br />

legislative functions, and cannot be done by the court vide Divisional Manager, Aravali Golf Course (supra)<br />

III. Conclusion:-<br />

However, the governance cannot be replaced by the judicial institutions. There is a need to discover a<br />

balance between judicial and executive institutions. We need to reassert the balance between reforms,<br />

development and institutions. <strong>Judicial</strong> activism should not be used to lead to the Constitutional principles of<br />

separation of power getting eroded. Our Hon‟ble Judges should not cross their limits in the name of judicial<br />

activism and not to try to take over the functions of other organs of administration. <strong>Judicial</strong> pronouncements<br />

must respect the boundaries that separate the Legislature, Executive and Judiciary. The<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism has<br />

touched almost every aspect of life in the present times. Be it the case of bonded labor, illegal detentions, torture<br />

and maltreatment of women, the implementation of various provisions of the constitution, environmental<br />

problems, health, sports etc. the courts took cognizance of each case and laid down various judgments to protect<br />

the basic human rights of each and every member of society. However, the politicians and some constitutional<br />

experts criticize judicial activism and on the other hand the lawyers and public has welcomed it with warm<br />

hands. It is important to note that judicial Activism has so many merits but it has certain demerits. Here it is<br />

important to note that we cannot lead the government on judicial basis only. Frequent confrontation between the<br />

Legislature, Executive and the judiciary will also damage our well established democratic system of<br />

governance. The members of every institutionsworn to uphold the constitution, which alone is supreme. Both<br />

sides will maintain and respect the line of demarcation of power under the constitution and will not allow a<br />

conflict to develop between them.<br />

By evolving the doctrine of Basic Structure of the Constitution, the Hon‟ble Supreme Court of India<br />

has limited the power of Parliament to amend the constitution. The court‟s increased activism has been good and<br />

contributed a lot for India‟s democracy. The expensive, technical justice now becomes inexpensive and nontechnical<br />

through the growth of Public Interest Litigations. The important question today is not whether the<br />

Supreme Court could activate its judicial role, but to what extent the concepts of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism and<br />

creativity are exercised. A balance between the powers of Judiciary, Legislature and executive is necessary to<br />

carry the nation on the true path of democracy.<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

24 | Page


“The Role Of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism In The Implementation And Promotion Of Constitutional Laws And<br />

References:-<br />

[1]. See for instance some of the work that are on judicial activism without really defining the term. Chad M. Old father, “Defining<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Inactivism: Models of Adjudication and the Duty to Decide” (2005) 94, Geo. L.J. 121, 122<br />

[2]. Keenan D. Kmiec, “The Origin and Current Meanings of "<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism," (2004) 92, Cal. L. Rev., 1441, 1442;See also<br />

Bradley C. Canon, “A Framework for the Analysis of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism” in Stephen C. Halpem& Charles M. Lamb eds., Supreme<br />

Court Activism And Restraint 1982, 385, 386 (describing prevalent activism debates as "little more than a babel of loosely<br />

connected discussion").<br />

[3]. Cardozo Benjamin N, The Nature of the <strong>Judicial</strong> Process, Universal Law Publishing Co.Pvt.Ltd., Delhi, (2004)<br />

[4]. Paul Mahoney, “<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism and <strong>Judicial</strong> Self-Restraint in the European Court of Human Rights: Two Sides of the Same<br />

Coin” (1990) 11, Hum. Rts. L.J. 57, 58.<br />

[5]. DragoljubPopovic, “Prevailing <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism over Self Restraint in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights”<br />

( 2009) vol. 42, Creighton Law Review, 361 at 363.<br />

[6]. Thijmen Koopmans, “The Roots of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism in Protecting Human Rights: The European Dimension, Studies In<br />

Honor Of Gérard J. Wiarda 326 (F Matscher& H. Petzold Eds., 1988).<br />

[7]. JUDICIAL ACTIVISM IN INDIA- An Overview (By Arjun.M, Administrative Assistant, Centre for Public Policy Research)<br />

[8]. Article 50: The State shall take steps to separate the judiciary from the executive in the public services of the State.<br />

[9]. SheelaBarsevs. State of Maharashtra, (1983) 2 SCC 96<br />

[10]. Labors on Sala Hydro Electricity Project Vs. State of J & K, (1984) 3 SCC 538<br />

[11]. Pradeep Kumar Jain Vs. State of .P., AIR 1984 SC 1420<br />

[12]. Bombay Hawkers Union Vs. B.M.C., (1985) 3 SCC 528<br />

[13]. Center for PIL Vs. Union of India, 1995 Sppl. (3) SCC 382<br />

[14]. ONGC Vs. Collector of Central Excise, 1995 Sppl. (3) SCC 541 (This decision has since been reversed)<br />

[15]. Supra footnote 51.<br />

[16]. M. C. Mehta v. Union of India, (1986) 2 SCC 176<br />

[17]. Shantisar Builders Vs. L. Narayan, (1990) 1 SCC 520<br />

[18]. M. C. Mehta v. Union of India, (1991) 2 SCC 353<br />

[19]. Pranab Mukherjee's note of caution on judicial activism PTI Sep 8, 2012, 07.33PM IST<br />

[20]. SC asks courts to curb judicial activism Sanjay K Singh, TNN Dec 11, 2007, 12.49am IST<br />

[21]. “<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism v. <strong>Judicial</strong> Self-Restraint” athttp://legalsutra.org/933/judicial-activism-v-judicial-self-restraint/ as last on 10<br />

July, 2011<br />

www.iosrjournals.org<br />

25 | Page


Attachment B<br />

Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

Page 110 of 115


Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

JUSTICE BRENNAN: LIBERAL CHAMPION. By Seth Stern & Stephen Wermiel.<br />

Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. 2010. Pp. 688, $35.00.<br />

Geoffrey R. Stone *<br />

When the term “judicial activist” was first coined by Arthur<br />

Schlesinger, Jr. in 1947, it “did not have a derogatory connotation.” 1 By the<br />

time William J. Brennan, Jr. had completed his thirty-four years on the<br />

Supreme Court, the phrase had become a pejorative, implying the<br />

irresponsible exercise of judicial authority.<br />

Critics on and off the Court have vilified Brennan and his liberal<br />

colleagues for their activism. In 1966, the political scientist Robert<br />

McCloskey accused Brennan and his fellow “judicial activists” of creating<br />

“Constitutional rules out of whole cloth.” 2 Judge Learned Hand complained<br />

that the “judicial activists” on the Supreme Court were acting like “a bevy of<br />

Platonic guardians.” 3 Anthony Lewis reported that critics had vehemently<br />

attacked “judicial activists” like Brennan for “taking too much joy” in their<br />

own power and “trying too boldly to fix up the wrongs of our system.” 4 And<br />

Justice Felix Frankfurter castigated the “judicial activists” for making<br />

decisions on the basis of “‘their prejudices and their respective pasts and selfconscious<br />

desires to join Thomas Paine and T. Jefferson in the Valhalla of<br />

“liberty.”’” 5 To this day, no Supreme Court nominee—not Anthony<br />

Kennedy, not Ruth Bader Ginsburg, not John Roberts, not Elena Kagan—has<br />

dared to describe him or herself as a “judicial activist.” Such a selfcharacterization<br />

would certainly be the kiss of death for any nominee.<br />

* Edward H. Levi Distinguished Service Professor of Law, The University of Chicago. I<br />

would like to thank the University of Chicago Law School’s Leonard Sorkin Law Faculty Fund for<br />

its generous support of my work and, most especially, Justice William J. Brennan, Jr., for giving me<br />

the extraordinary opportunity to serve as one of his law clerks during the Supreme Court’s 1973<br />

Term.<br />

1. SETH STERN & STEPHEN WERMIEL, JUSTICE BRENNAN: LIBERAL CHAMPION 232 (2010).<br />

2. Id. at 232–33 (quoting Robert G. McCloskey, Reflections on the Warren Court, 51 VA. L.<br />

REV. 1229, 1259 (1965)).<br />

3. Id. at 231 (quoting LEARNED HAND, THE BILL OF RIGHTS: THE OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES<br />

LECTURES 1958, at 73 (1958)).<br />

4. Id. at 231 (quoting Anthony Lewis, Supreme Court Moves Again to Exert Its Powerful<br />

Influence, N.Y. TIMES, June 20, 1964, at E3).<br />

5. Id. at 102 (quoting Melvin I. Urofsky, Conflict Among the Brethren: Felix Frankfurter,<br />

William O. Douglas and the Clash of Personalities and Philosophies on the United States Supreme<br />

Court, 1988 DUKE L.J. 71, 105 (1988)).


1424 Texas Law Review [Vol. 89:1423<br />

Is the pejorative “judicial activist” warranted? To answer that question,<br />

we must begin with the Court’s economic substantive due process decisions<br />

in cases like Lochner v. New York, 6 half a century before William Brennan<br />

joined the Court. Lochner and its progeny, which held unconstitutional a<br />

broad range of progressive legislation regulating such matters as maximum<br />

hours and minimum wages, represented a highly controversial form of<br />

conservative judicial activism. Over time, Lochner, the bête noire of<br />

progressives of that era, came to be “one of the most condemned cases in<br />

United States history.” 7<br />

Critics of the Lochner-era jurisprudence took away two quite distinct<br />

lessons. Some, like Frankfurter, concluded that judicial activism was<br />

presumptively illegitimate and unwarranted. The only principled stance for a<br />

responsible Justice was one of judicial restraint. As Seth Stern and Stephen<br />

Wermiel aptly observe, “Frankfurter believed firmly that judges should act<br />

with restraint and largely defer to the elected branches.” 8 Indeed, this was<br />

“something he had preached as a professor at a time when a conservative<br />

Supreme Court was overturning the progressive economic regulations . . .<br />

that he favored.” 9 It was for this reason that Frankfurter was so condemning<br />

of his “judicial activist” colleagues on the Court.<br />

Other critics of Lochner, like Hugo Black, William O. Douglas, and<br />

William Brennan, took away a very different lesson. In their view, Lochner<br />

was wrong not because judicial activism is wrong, but because Lochner was<br />

not an appropriate case for judicial activism. It was this view that Chief<br />

Justice Harlan Fiske Stone set forth in 1938 in his famous footnote 4 in<br />

United States v. Carolene Products Co. 10 While burying the doctrine of<br />

economic substantive due process, Stone at the same time suggested that<br />

“[t]here may be narrower scope for operation of the presumption of<br />

constitutionality when legislation . . . restricts those political processes which<br />

can ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation,”<br />

or when it discriminates “against discrete and insular minorities” in<br />

circumstances in which it is reasonable to infer that prejudice, intolerance, or<br />

indifference might seriously have curtailed “the operation of those political<br />

processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities . . . .” 11<br />

It was this conception of selective judicial activism that shaped<br />

Brennan’s jurisprudence. It is important to emphasize that, Frankfurter to the<br />

contrary notwithstanding, this view of the judicial role is not necessarily the<br />

product of individual Justices’ personal “prejudices” and experiences.<br />

6. 198 U.S. 45 (1905).<br />

7. BERNARD H. SIEGAN, ECONOMIC LIBERTIES AND THE CONSTITUTION 23 (1980).<br />

8. STERN & WERMIEL, supra note 1, at 101.<br />

9. Id.<br />

10. 304 U.S. 144 (1938).<br />

11. Id. at 152–53 n.4.


2011] Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism 1425<br />

Rather, it is deeply rooted in the original understanding of the purpose of<br />

judicial review in our system of constitutional governance.<br />

The Framers of our Constitution wrestled with the problem of how to<br />

cabin the dangers of an overbearing or intolerant majority. For example,<br />

those who initially opposed a bill of rights argued that such a list of rights<br />

would serve little, if any, practical purpose, for in a self-governing society<br />

the majority could simply disregard whatever rights might be “guaranteed” in<br />

the Constitution. In the face of strenuous objections from the Anti-<br />

Federalists during the ratification debates, however, it became necessary to<br />

reconsider the issue.<br />

On December 20, 1787, Thomas Jefferson wrote James Madison from<br />

Paris that, after reviewing the proposed Constitution, he regretted “the<br />

omission of a bill of rights.” 12 In response, Madison expressed doubt that a<br />

bill of rights would “provide any check on the passions and interests of the<br />

popular majorities.” 13 He maintained that “experience proves the inefficacy<br />

of a bill of rights on those occasions when its controul is most needed.<br />

Repeated violations of these parchment barriers have been committed by<br />

overbearing majorities in every State” that already had a bill of rights. 14 In<br />

such circumstances, he asked, “What use . . . can a bill of rights serve in<br />

popular Governments?” 15<br />

Jefferson replied, “Your thoughts on the subject of the Declaration of<br />

rights” fail to address one consideration “which has great weight with me, the<br />

legal check which it puts into the hands of the judiciary. This is a body,<br />

which if rendered independent . . . merits great confidence for their learning<br />

& integrity.” 16 This exchange apparently carried some weight with Madison.<br />

On June 8, 1789, Madison proposed a bill of rights to the House of<br />

Representatives. At the outset, he reminded his colleagues that “the greatest<br />

danger” to liberty was found “in the body of the people, operating by the<br />

majority against the minority.” 17 Echoing Jefferson’s letter, he stated the<br />

position for judicial review, contending that if these rights are:<br />

incorporated into the constitution, independent tribunals of justice will<br />

consider themselves . . . the guardians of those rights; they will be an<br />

impenetrable bulwark against every assumption of power in the<br />

legislative or executive; they will be naturally led to resist every<br />

12. Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Dec. 20, 1787), reprinted in JACK N.<br />

RAKOVE, DECLARING RIGHTS: A BRIEF HISTORY WITH DOCUMENTS 154, 156 (1998).<br />

13. RAKOVE, supra note 12, at 159.<br />

14. Letter from James Madison to Thomas Jefferson (Oct. 17, 1788), reprinted in RAKOVE,<br />

supra note 12, at 160, 161.<br />

15. Id. at 162.<br />

16. Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Mar. 15, 1789), reprinted in RAKOVE,<br />

supra note 12, at 165, 165.<br />

17. James Madison, Speech to the House of Representatives (June 8, 1789), reprinted in<br />

RAKOVE, supra note 12 at 170, 177.


1426 Texas Law Review [Vol. 89:1423<br />

encroachment upon rights expressly stipulated for in the constitution<br />

by the declaration of rights. 18<br />

This reliance on judges, whose lifetime tenure would hopefully insulate<br />

them from the need to curry favor with the governing majority, was central to<br />

the Framers’ understanding. Alexander Hamilton, for example, strongly<br />

endorsed judicial review as obvious and uncontroversial. The “independence<br />

of the judges,” he reasoned, is “requisite to guard the Constitution and the<br />

rights of individuals from the effects of those ill humours, which . . .<br />

sometimes disseminate among the people themselves” Judges, he insisted,<br />

have a duty to resist invasions of constitutional rights even if they are<br />

“instigated by the major voice of the community.” 19<br />

It was this “originalist” conception of judicial review that informed<br />

Justice Brennan’s selective judicial activism. As a rule, he gave a great deal<br />

of deference to the elected branches of government—except when he felt<br />

such deference would effectively abdicate the responsibility the Framers had<br />

imposed upon the Judiciary to serve as an essential check against the inherent<br />

dangers of democratic majoritarianism. He therefore invoked activist<br />

judicial review primarily in two situations: (1) when the governing majority<br />

systematically disregarded the interests of a historically underrepresented<br />

group (such as blacks, ethnic minorities, political dissidents, religious<br />

dissenters, women, and persons accused of crime), and (2) when there was a<br />

risk that a governing majority was using its authority to stifle its critics,<br />

entrench the status quo, and/or perpetuate its own political power.<br />

Because Brennan played so central a role in crafting many of the key<br />

decisions of the Warren Court, it may be useful to note just a few of those<br />

decisions to illustrate my point. Consider, for example, Brown v. Board of<br />

Education, 20 which prohibited racial segregation in public schools; Loving v.<br />

Virginia, 21 which invalidated laws forbidding interracial marriage; Engel v.<br />

Vitale, 22 which prohibited school prayer; Goldberg v. Kelly, 23 which<br />

guaranteed a hearing before an individual’s welfare benefits could be<br />

terminated; Reynolds v. Sims, 24 which guaranteed “one person, one vote”;<br />

Miranda v. Arizona, 25 which gave effect to the prohibition of compelled selfincrimination;<br />

Gideon v. Wainwright, 26 which guaranteed all persons accused<br />

of crime the right to effective assistance of counsel; New York Times v.<br />

18. Id. at 179.<br />

19. THE FEDERALIST NO. 78 (Alexander Hamilton).<br />

20. 347 U.S. 483 (1954).<br />

21. 388 U.S. 1 (1967).<br />

22. 370 U.S. 421 (1962).<br />

23. 397 U.S. 254 (1970).<br />

24. 377 U.S. 533 (1964).<br />

25. 384 U.S. 436 (1966).<br />

26. 372 U.S. 335 (1963).


2011] Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism 1427<br />

Sullivan, 27 which limited the ability of public officials to use libel actions to<br />

silence their critics; and Elfbrandt v. Russell, 28 which protected the First<br />

Amendment rights of members of the Communist Party. Each of these<br />

decisions clearly reflected the central purpose of judicial review—to guard<br />

against the greatest dangers of majoritarian abuse. 29<br />

By definition, antimajoritarian decisions generally do not sit well with<br />

the majority. It is therefore hardly surprising that this jurisprudence excited<br />

biting criticism, especially in the political arena, where candidates curry<br />

favor with that very same majority. By the late 1960s, Richard Nixon was<br />

able to make the Court’s “judicial activism” a significant issue in national<br />

politics. During his nomination acceptance speech in 1968, for example, he<br />

insisted that the Court had “gone too far in weakening the peace forces as<br />

against the criminal forces in this country and we must act to restore that<br />

balance.” 30 Nixon decried the activism of the Warren Court and pledged to<br />

appoint “strict constructionists” rather than “judicial activists” to the Court.<br />

In the discourse of the time, a strict constructionist was a judge committed to<br />

judicial restraint. In a few short years, Nixon appointed Warren Burger,<br />

Harry Blackmun, Lewis Powell, and William Rehnquist to the Court.<br />

Although these Justices varied over time in their adherence to “strict<br />

constructionism,” their presence quickly transformed the Court, leaving<br />

Justice Brennan in the minority for the rest of his tenure.<br />

The change in the Court’s role since 1968 has been dramatic. In the<br />

twenty-five years between 1968 and 1993, shortly after Brennan left the<br />

Court, Republican presidents made twelve consecutive appointments to the<br />

Supreme Court. According to research by Lee Epstein, William Landes, and<br />

Richard Posner, in 1968 the average voting record of the five most liberal<br />

Justices (Marshall, Douglas, Brennan, Fortas, and Warren) in civil liberties<br />

cases was .185. (This is on a scale in which .000 is the most liberal and<br />

1.000 is the most conservative.) The swing Justice was Earl Warren, whose<br />

voting record was .263. 31 By 1993, after twelve consecutive Republican<br />

27. 376 U.S. 254 (1964).<br />

28. 384 U.S. 11 (1966).<br />

29. Many of these decisions reflected, indirectly if not directly, the “gravitational pull” of the<br />

quest for racial justice and equality. See Burt Neuborne, The Gravitational Pull of Race on the<br />

Warren Court, 2010 SUP. CT. REV. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 9–27) (on file with Texas<br />

Law Review) (arguing that race exercised a strong influence on the Warren Court’s federalism,<br />

separation of powers, and First Amendment jurisprudence); HARRY KALVEN, JR., THE NEGRO AND<br />

THE FIRST AMENDMENT 4 (1965) (arguing that recent constitutional decisions relating to race and<br />

free speech challenge the law’s prior conceptions of racial equality).<br />

30. Richard M. Nixon, Presidential Nomination Acceptance Speech (Aug. 8, 1968) (transcript<br />

available at http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=25968).<br />

31. See LEE EPSTEIN, WILLIAM M. LANDES AND RICHARD A. POSNER, ARE JUDGES REALISTS?<br />

AN EMPIRICAL STUDY tbl.3-2 (forthcoming HARV. L. REV. 2011); see also Geoffrey R. Stone,<br />

Understanding Supreme Court Confirmations, 2010 SUP. CT. REV. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript<br />

at 21) (on file with Texas Law Review).


1428 Texas Law Review [Vol. 89:1423<br />

appointments, the average voting record of the five most conservative<br />

Justices (Thomas, Rehnquist, Scalia, O’Connor, and Kennedy) was .798, and<br />

the swing Justice, Anthony Kennedy, had a voting record of .695. 32 Thus,<br />

the Court majority was roughly as conservative in 1993 as it had been liberal<br />

in 1968. Even more striking, by 1993 the “liberals” on the Court were<br />

almost as conservative as the “conservatives” on the Court in 1968. 33<br />

But what does “conservative” mean in the modern era? In Nixon’s<br />

time, the term meant a Justice committed to judicial restraint. But beginning<br />

with the Reagan era, this began to change. Justices like Antonin Scalia,<br />

Clarence Thomas, John Roberts, and Samuel Alito are anything but<br />

restrained. Rather, like Justice Brennan, they employ a form of selective<br />

judicial activism. On the one hand, it seems clear that these Justices would<br />

have joined few, if any, of the Warren Court decisions I mentioned earlier.<br />

On the other hand, though, despite all the conservative rhetoric about “strict<br />

constructionism,” “originalism,” “judicial restraint,” and “call[ing] balls and<br />

strikes,” 34 these conservative Justices have been just as activist as their liberal<br />

predecessors, but in a wholly different set of cases.<br />

In a series of unmistakably activist decisions, the conservative Justices<br />

have held unconstitutional affirmative action programs, 35 gun control<br />

regulations, 36 limitations on the authority of corporations to spend at will in<br />

the political process, 37 restrictions on commercial advertising, 38 laws<br />

prohibiting groups like the Boy Scouts from discriminating on the basis of<br />

sexual orientation, 39 federal legislation regulating guns, age discrimination,<br />

32. EPSTEIN ET AL., supra note 31.<br />

33. The four conservatives in 1968 (Harlan, White, Stewart, and Black) had an average voting<br />

record of .521, whereas the four liberals in 1993 (Stevens, Souter, Blackmun, and White) had an<br />

average voting record of .436. See EPSTEIN, LANDES & POSNER, supra note 31, at tbl.3-2.<br />

34. Confirmation Hearing on the Nomination of John G. Roberts, Jr. to Be Chief Justice of the<br />

United States: Hearing Before the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 109th Cong. 56 (2005) (statement of<br />

John G. Roberts, Jr., Supreme Court C.J. Nominee).<br />

35. See Parents Involved in Cmty. Sch. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 551 U.S. 701, 747–78 (2007)<br />

(holding unconstitutional an affirmative action program that took race into account when<br />

determining school placement).<br />

36. See McDonald v. City of Chi., 130 S. Ct. 3020, 3050 (2010) (holding that the Second<br />

Amendment is applicable to the states and remanding the case for further proceedings); D.C. v.<br />

Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 595, 635 (2008) (holding that D.C.’s ban on handgun possession in the home<br />

violated the individual right to bear arms conferred by the Second Amendment).<br />

37. See Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 913 (2010) (holding that<br />

“[t]he First Amendment does not permit Congress to make . . . categorical distinctions based on the<br />

corporate identity of the speaker and the content of the political speech”).<br />

38. See Thompson v. W. States Med. Ctr., 535 U.S. 357, 376–77 (2002) (“If the Government’s<br />

failure to justify its decision to regulate speech were not enough to convince us that the FDAMA’s<br />

advertising provisions were unconstitutional, the amount of beneficial speech prohibited by the<br />

FDAMA would be. . . . [W]e affirm the . . . judgment that the speech-related provisions . . . are<br />

unconstitutional.”).<br />

39. See Boy Scouts of Am. v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 661 (2000) (overturning application of a state<br />

public accommodations law that would have prohibited discrimination based on sexual orientation).


2011] Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism 1429<br />

the environment, and violence against women, 40 and policies of the State of<br />

Florida relating to the outcome of the 2000 presidential election. 41<br />

Nothing about this jurisprudence smacks of “judicial restraint.” To the<br />

contrary, it has about it the distinctive air of Platonic guardianship. The<br />

challenge is to figure out what theory of judicial review or constitutional law<br />

drives this particular form of activism. Although one can readily discern the<br />

specific conception of judicial review that undergirds Justice Brennan’s use<br />

of judicial activism, which is clearly rooted in the concerns of Jefferson,<br />

Madison, and Hamilton, no similar principle of judicial review or<br />

constitutional methodology explains the jurisprudence of contemporary<br />

conservative judicial activists. To understand Brennan’s theory of activist<br />

judicial review, all one needs to do is to look at the results and then ask,<br />

“Why these cases and not others?” If one attempts the same inquiry of the<br />

decisions of the current conservative Justices, however, no principled<br />

explanation emerges for their version of selective activism. Rather, to return<br />

to Justice Frankfurter’s ill-tempered observation, the selective activism of<br />

Justices like Scalia, Thomas, Roberts, and Alito seems to be born out of<br />

“‘their prejudices and their respective pasts and self-conscious desires to join<br />

[Ronald Reagan and George W. Bush] in the Valhalla of “liberty.”’” 42 The<br />

point, in other words, is that judicial activism itself is neither inherently good<br />

nor inherently bad. It is a legitimate and essential method of constitutional<br />

interpretation when used in appropriate circumstances.<br />

I sometimes wonder what constitutional law might look like today if<br />

Justices with the same vision as Justice Brennan had remained a majority on<br />

the Supreme Court over the past forty years. It is not so difficult to imagine<br />

such a state of affairs. Had Hubert Humphrey defeated Richard Nixon,<br />

Jimmy Carter defeated Ronald Reagan, or Al Gore defeated George W.<br />

Bush, the path of constitutional law might have been very different. What is<br />

more difficult to imagine is how constitutional law might have evolved in<br />

that counterfactual universe. It has been so long since there has been a<br />

liberal majority on the Court that it is difficult even to conceive what a liberal<br />

jurisprudence might look like today.<br />

40. See Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898, 933 (1997) (holding that “[t]he mandatory<br />

obligation imposed on CLEOs to perform background checks on prospective handgun purchasers<br />

plainly runs afoul of [the law]”); Kimel v. Fla. Bd. of Regents, 528 U.S. 62, 91 (2000) (holding<br />

“that the [Age Discrimination in Employment Act] is not a valid exercise of Congress’ power”);<br />

Solid Waste Agency v. United States Army Corps of Eng’rs, 531 U.S. 159, 174 (2001) (holding a<br />

federal law claiming jurisdiction over ponds and mudflats was unconstitutional); United States v.<br />

Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 627 (2000) (holding that a federal law dealing with violence against<br />

women was not constitutional).<br />

41. See Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 103 (2000) (invalidating Florida’s “use of standardless<br />

manual recounts” as violative of the “Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses”).<br />

42. STERN & WERMIEL, supra note 1, at 102 (quoting Melvin I. Urofsky, Conflict Among the<br />

Brethren: Felix Frankfurter, William O. Douglas and the Clash of Personalities and Philosophies<br />

on the United States Supreme Court, 1988 DUKE L.J. 71, 105).


1430 Texas Law Review [Vol. 89:1423<br />

Here are some possibilities: the counterfactual Court might have held,<br />

not that affirmative action is unconstitutional, but that it is sometimes<br />

constitutionally required; it might have held, not that cigarette companies<br />

have a constitutional right to shill their products to children, 43 but that<br />

children have a constitutional right to an adequate and equal education; 44 it<br />

might have held not that silence constitutes waiver of the right to remain<br />

silent, 45 but that individuals accused of a crime have a constitutional right to<br />

DNA testing; it might have held, not that the government can constitutionally<br />

ban partial birth abortions, 46 but that it cannot constitutionally ban stem-cell<br />

research in order to enforce the faith-based beliefs of the religious right; it<br />

might have held, not that corporations have a constitutional right to spend<br />

millions to buy the elected representatives of their choice, 47 but that public<br />

officials cannot constitutionally use partisan gerrymandering to ensure their<br />

perpetuation in power; 48 it might have held, not that the Boy Scouts have a<br />

constitutional right to discriminate against gays and lesbians, 49 but that gays<br />

and lesbians have a constitutional right to marry.<br />

Constitutional interpretation is not a mechanical, value-free enterprise.<br />

It requires judges to exercise judgment. It calls upon them to consider text,<br />

history, precedent, values, and ever-changing social and cultural conditions.<br />

It requires restraint, wisdom, empathy, 50 and intelligence. Perhaps above all,<br />

it requires a recognition of the Judiciary’s unique strengths and weaknesses<br />

and a deep and accurate understanding of our nation’s most fundamental<br />

constitutional aspirations.<br />

43. See Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly, 533 U.S. 525, 566 (2001) (holding that regulations on<br />

tobacco advertising violate the First Amendment because they fail Central Hudson’s four-part<br />

analysis).<br />

44. See San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 54–55 (1973) (holding that the<br />

Texas system of financing public education rationally furthers a legitimate state purpose or interest<br />

and therefore satisfies the Equal Protection Clause).<br />

45. See Berghuis v. Thompkins, 130 S. Ct. 2250, 2264 (2010) (holding that unless a suspect<br />

explicitly invoked his Miranda rights he waived them by making voluntary statements and that<br />

police did not have to obtain a waiver of the suspect’s Miranda rights before interrogating him).<br />

46. See Gonzales v. Carhart, 550 U.S. 124, 168 (2007) (holding that the Partial-Birth Abortion<br />

Ban Act of 2003 was not unconstitutional on its face).<br />

47. See Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 913 (2010) (holding that<br />

“[t]he First Amendment does not permit Congress to make . . . categorical distinctions based on the<br />

corporate identity of the speaker and the content of the political speech”).<br />

48. See Vieth v. Jubelirer, 541 U.S. 267, 281 (2004) (holding that “political gerrymandering<br />

claims are nonjusticiable” because there are no “judicially discernable and manageable standards for<br />

adjudicating political gerrymandering claims”).<br />

49. See Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 644 (2000) (holding that applying New<br />

Jersey’s public accommodations law to require the Boy Scouts to readmit an avowed homosexual<br />

and gay rights activist violated the Boy Scouts’ First Amendment right of expressive association).<br />

50. Richard Cotton, one of Justice Brennan’s law clerks in the Court’s 1972 term, observed that<br />

Brennan “had the ability to see a case through the eyes of the people involved.” STERN &<br />

WERMIEL, supra note 1, at 206.


2011] Selective <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism 1431<br />

As Justice Brennan himself observed, the Supreme “‘Court is not a<br />

council of Platonic guardians given the function of deciding our most<br />

difficult and emotional questions according to the Justices’ own notions of<br />

what is just or wise or politic.’” 51 Rather, “‘our government structure assigns<br />

to the people’s elected representatives the function of making policy for<br />

handling the social and economic problems of state and nation’” and “‘the<br />

impropriety of a judiciary with life tenure writing its own social and<br />

economic creed into the Constitution is therefore clear.’” 52 At the same time,<br />

though, Brennan insisted that “‘[j]ust as an individual may be untrue to<br />

himself, so may society be untrue to itself.’” 53 The Court’s responsibility in<br />

interpreting and applying the Constitution, he rightly insisted, is to “‘keep the<br />

community true to its own fundamental principles.’” 54<br />

51. Id. at 233 (quoting Justice William James Brennan, The U.S. Constitution, Speech at<br />

Maxwell Air Force Base (Sept. 9, 1963), reprinted in 2 AIR WAR C. SUPPLEMENT 3, 43).<br />

52. Id. (quoting A Visit with Justice Brennan, LOOK, Dec. 18, 1962).<br />

53. Id. at 234 (quoting Justice William James Brennan, Bouton Lecture at Princeton University<br />

(Feb. 4, 1969)).<br />

54. Id.


Attachment C<br />

Proper <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism<br />

Page 111 of 115


PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

Greg Jones*<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review, and judicial activism in particular, have never<br />

enjoyed a wealth of popular support in this country. Indeed, the practice<br />

of judges overturning legislative enactments has been the subject of<br />

several sharp critiques over the years, particularly in the area of<br />

constitutional law. As President, Ronald Reagan described the kinds of<br />

judges of which he disapproves as those who love "short-circuiting the<br />

electoral process and disenfranchising the people through judicial<br />

activism." 1 His one-time nominee to the Supreme Court, Robert Bork,<br />

has commented that "[wle have known judicial activism of the right and<br />

of the left; neither is legitimate." 2 Regardless of ideology, it has become a<br />

staple of opponents of a particular judicial decision to accuse the court of<br />

activism, which is synonymous with an affront. 3<br />

Despite its negative connotation, judicial activism, in several forms,<br />

has a long, if not storied, tradition in this country. Since Marbury v.<br />

Madison, 4 striking down legislation passed at the federal and state levels<br />

has been met with varying degrees of acceptance and criticism. It is the<br />

premise of this paper that in constitutional law there is a correct kind of<br />

judicial activism, toward which the Supreme Court should be focused. As<br />

mandated by the Constitution, the proper form of judicial activism is<br />

activism based upon preserving the structure of our constitutional<br />

government. Professor Steven Calabresi comments, "There is nothing in<br />

the U.S. Constitution that should absorb more completely the attention<br />

of the U.S. Supreme Court" than the structures embedded in "[t]hat<br />

great document." s This article aims to demonstrate that a faithful<br />

rendering of the Constitution by the Supreme Court demands<br />

* Law clerk to Chief Justice Roy S. Moore of the Alabama Supreme Court; J.D.,<br />

Regent University School of Law.<br />

1 Ronald Reagan, I PUB. PAPERS 1270, (Oct. 21, 1985).<br />

2 Id. at 41, Jan. 14, 1988. In describing Bork and his "disciples," Professor Harry<br />

Jaffa says they believe "that judicial activism is usurpation, denying to the political<br />

processes of democracy their rightful role in governance." Harry V. Jaffa, Jaffa Replies to<br />

His Critics 235 app. IV-A, at 292 (The Closing of the Conservative Mind) in ORIGINAL<br />

INTENT AND THE FRAMERS OF THE CONSTITUTION (Harry V. Jaffa et al., 1994). In part, that<br />

is exactly the sentiment this paper hopes to refute. Proper judicial activism flows from the<br />

nature of our system, as will be shown, and as such is not usurpation.<br />

3 See David L. Anderson, Note, When Restraint Requires Activism: Partisan<br />

Gerrymandering and the Status Quo Ante, 42 STAN. L. REV. 1549, 1559 (1990).<br />

4 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).<br />

5 Steven G. Calabresi, "A Government of Limited and Enumerated Powers": In<br />

Defense of United States v. Lopez, 94 MIcH. L. REV. 752, 770 (1995).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 141 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

concentration on the structures of government as the most justified and<br />

least dangerous way to practice judicial review.<br />

To explain and substantiate this claim, it is necessary to divide this<br />

paper into five parts. Part I defines the terms involved in order to help<br />

the reader better understand what is and is not being argued. Part II<br />

explains the vast importance of structure to our constitutional scheme as<br />

it relates to the Founding and today. Part III spells out why judicial<br />

review is a tool best employed on the structural front. Part IV examines<br />

some criticisms of and alternatives to the approach espoused here, as<br />

well as some responses to those various views. Finally, Part V reflects on<br />

why this argument is important to our world today and to the<br />

government in which we participate.<br />

I. DEFINITIONS<br />

In general terms, the structures of the Constitution are not difficult<br />

to discover or define. They include the separation of powers, checks and<br />

balances, federalism, bicameralism, representation, an independent<br />

judiciary, and judicial review. 6 Many of these structures are rarely, if<br />

ever, questioned on propriety or efficacy grounds. "Elections are held<br />

when they are supposed to be held, presidents and congresses come and<br />

go, California and Wyoming send two representatives to the Senate,<br />

[and] constitutional amendments are proposed and are almost always<br />

defeated . . . ."7 Most of these structures have held a consistent definition<br />

since the Founding; after all, little is left to the imagination when the<br />

Constitution says that Congress shall consist of two houses or that a<br />

senator has a six-year term of office. Two of these structures, however,<br />

have displayed fluid tendencies over the years, causing many to question<br />

their wisdom and even their very existence: the separation of powers and<br />

federalism. 8 Ironically, the Founders considered these the most<br />

important innovations placed in the Constitution, 9 and are the<br />

structures on which this article will focus.1 0<br />

6 Edwin Meese III, The Law of the Constitution, 61 TUL. L. REV. 979, 982 (1987).<br />

7 Steven G. Calabresi, The Tradition of the Written Constitution: A Comment on<br />

Professor Lessig's Theory of Translation, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1435, 1452 (1997).<br />

8 The legitimacy of judicial review has also been questioned at length, given the<br />

lack of any Constitutional text on the subject. However, there seems little doubt that,<br />

whether the device was intended by the Framers or not (this paper will make a structural<br />

argument that it was), it is not going away. As Professor Erwin Chemerinsky has pointed<br />

out, "What we really should be talking about is what is the appropriate content of judicial<br />

review, not whether the power exists or not." Erwin Chemerinsky, The Goldwater Institute<br />

and the Federalist Society: Federalism and <strong>Judicial</strong> Mandates, 28 ARIz. ST. L.J. 17, 51<br />

(1996). That is exactly what this paper is about-the appropriate content of judicial review.<br />

9 WILLIAM EATON, WHO KILLED THE CONSTITUTION: THE JUDGES V. THE LAW 3<br />

(1988): "The Founding Fathers understood thoroughly the corruptions of power and the<br />

temptations of office. They feared most of all the tyranny of unchecked government power.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 142 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

The concept of judicial activism requires some careful elucidation. It<br />

falls under the rubric of what is commonly called judicial review."<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review occurs, as Justice Marshall famously put it,<br />

If a law be in opposition to the constitution; if both the law and the<br />

constitution apply to a particular case, so that the court must either<br />

decide that case conformably to the law, disregarding the constitution;<br />

or conformably to the constitution, disregarding the law; the court<br />

must determine which of these conflicting rules governs the case. 12<br />

At the broadest level, judicial activism is any occasion where a court<br />

intervenes and strikes down a piece of duly enacted legislation. This is<br />

activism because it "impose Is] a judicial solution over an issue erstwhile<br />

subject to political resolution." 13 The key to categorizing this broad<br />

definition of activism is determining on what basis the legislation or<br />

policy is struck down.<br />

For instance, Professor Lino Graglia describes judicial activism as<br />

"the practice by judges of disallowing policy choices by other<br />

governmental officials or institutions that the Constitution does not<br />

clearly prohibit." 1 4 Professor Graglia's version of activism is actually<br />

improper judicial activism because it possesses no constitutional basis.<br />

However, rarely, if ever, does a judge admit in an opinion that his<br />

And so they fashioned a system of checks and balances to operate against the institutions<br />

of government to which particular powers are granted." Id.<br />

10 While I will elaborate extensively on these devices, it is important to note that<br />

this paper does not attempt to present any definitive standards the Supreme Court ought<br />

to use in the line-drawing problems raised in cases dealing with these issues. What is an<br />

executive function as opposed to a legislative one, how much sovereignty do the states<br />

retain, and how far does the power to regulate commerce extend are all intriguing<br />

questions, but each are topics for full papers in themselves.<br />

For some sample answers to these questions along the lines of the kind of<br />

jurisprudence espoused in this paper, see Gary Lawson & Patricia Granger, The "Proper"<br />

Scope of Federal Power: A Jurisdictional Interpretation of the Sweeping Clause, 43 DUKE<br />

L.J. 267 (1993) (arguing for a structural interpretation of the Necessary and Proper Clause<br />

which fundamentally restricts its scope); Thomas W. Merrill, Toward a Principled<br />

Interpretation of the Commerce Clause, 22 HARV. J.L. & PUB. PoL'Y 31 (1998) (presenting a<br />

clearer alternative to the understanding in Lopez of the Commerce Clause for the purpose<br />

of enabling the Court to continue to police constitutional limitations on federal power);<br />

Bernard Schwartz, Of Administrators and Philosopher-Kings: The Republic, the Laws, and<br />

Delegations of Power, 72 Nw. U. L. REV. 443, 446 (1977) (reflecting on the practical nonexistence<br />

of the current delegation doctrine).<br />

My concern is drawing attention to the intrinsic nature and importance of these<br />

structures, and consequently, the need for vigorous judicial policing in these areas.<br />

I Of course, judicial activism also can occur when no constitutional question is at<br />

issue. This paper, however, focuses on the use of activism in constitutional cases.<br />

12 Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 178 (1803).<br />

13 See Anderson, supra note 3, at 1570.<br />

14 Lino A. Graglia, It's Not Constitutionalism, It's <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism, 19 HARV. J.L.<br />

& PUB. POL'Y 293, 296 (1996).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 143 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

decision does not come from the Constitution. Thus, more precision is<br />

necessary to differentiate proper from improper activism.<br />

Improper activism finds its roots in the "belief that law is only<br />

policy and that the judge should concentrate on building the good society<br />

according to the judge's own vision."' 5 Judge William Wayne Justice, 16 a<br />

self-proclaimed activist, is illustrative when he describes his own<br />

thinking in a certain case: "Having found a constitutional violation by a<br />

state institution, I acted upon the belief that simply declaring a practice<br />

unconstitutional was not the limit of my duty as a judge. Judges are<br />

more than social critics. The power of law and justice lies in actions, not<br />

pronouncements." 17 Thus, this kind of activism employs "natural law or<br />

basic notions of humanity, land] the necessary consultation of<br />

extratextual source[s] for constitutional interpretation." 18 It is the kind<br />

of activism Judge Skelly Wright called, when referring approvingly to<br />

the Warren Court, "judging in the service of conscience." 19<br />

In contrast, proper judicial activism stresses restraint, even when<br />

striking down duly enacted legislation.<br />

In this understanding of judicial review, the power to initiate policy<br />

remains with the legislature or the executive. The Court merely<br />

exercises a judicial veto in the event that an act of one of the other<br />

branches of government goes beyond the power granted to that branch<br />

by the Constitution, or is in conflict with some provision of the<br />

Constitution. 20<br />

While practicing this "restraint in activism," it is my contention that<br />

the Supreme Court's focus ought to be on the structures of the<br />

Constitution, especially the separation of powers and federalism. In<br />

discussing the history of Supreme Court judicial review, Calabresi notes,<br />

"The Supreme Court's main role until 1937 was to police the lines of<br />

jurisdictional competence set out in the constitutional text ....<br />

Federalism and separation of powers were thus core concerns of<br />

American constitutional law .. ."21 They should be again.<br />

As we shall see, proper judicial activism focuses on policing the<br />

boundaries of power between the jurisdictional government entities<br />

15 Archibald Cox, The Role of the Supreme Court: <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism or Self-<br />

Restraint, 47 MD. L. REV. 118, 121-22 (1987).<br />

16 United States District Court for the Eastern District of Texas.<br />

17 William Wayne Justice, The Two Faces of <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism, 61 GEO. WASH. L.<br />

REV. 1, 10 (1992).<br />

18 Id. at 4.<br />

19 J. Skelly Wright, The <strong>Judicial</strong> Right and the Rhetoric of Restraint: A Defense of<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Activism in an Age of Conservative Judges, 14 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 487, 489<br />

(1987).<br />

20 See EATON, supra note 9, at 17.<br />

21 Steven G. Calabresi, Textualism and the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, 66 GEO.<br />

WASH. L. REV. 1373, 1375 (1988) (footnotes omitted).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 144 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

within our system. Improper activism seeks to substantively correct<br />

perceived injustices in the law through the use of any number of extraconstitutional<br />

sources. The bottom line reason why the former is to be<br />

preferred to the latter is that judicial review based upon the Constitution<br />

demands nothing less. As Judge Frank Easterbrook 22 puts it, "The text of<br />

the Constitution is about structure - about form. Application of the<br />

Marbury principle means that rules . .. must be applied mechanically.<br />

Anything else is faithless to the premise of constitutionalism.23<br />

II. OUR CONSTITUTIONAL SCHEME AND THE IMPORTANCE OF STRUCTURE<br />

A. The Principles of Structure<br />

On a recent visit to the campus of Regent University, Associate<br />

Justice of the Supreme Court Antonin Scalia made an observation to the<br />

matriculating law students that where Constitutional Law is concerned,<br />

"structure is destiny." 24 Stalwart proponents of the Bill of Rights would<br />

disagree, but the point still maintains cogent force. To put Justice<br />

Scalia's point a slightly different way, "[T]he text of our written<br />

Constitution devotes only fifty-two words to the protection of individual<br />

liberty from the depredations of state government in the Fourteenth<br />

Amendment, while devoting several thousand words to the subject of<br />

allocating and dividing power among government institutions." 25 That<br />

point reminds us of something that many tend to forget: the whole of our<br />

Constitution was written without a Bill of Rights originally in mind.<br />

James Wilson said, "[Ilt would have been superfluous and absurd to<br />

have stipulated with a fcederal body of our own creation, that we should<br />

enjoy those privileges, of which we are not divested either by the<br />

intention or the act [the Constitution], that has brought that body into<br />

existence." 26 When we keep this fact in mind, the awesome importance of<br />

22 United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit.<br />

?3 Frank H. Easterbrook, Formalism, Functionalism, Ignorance, Judges, 22 HARV.<br />

J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 13, 18 (1998).<br />

24 Justice Antonin Scalia, Address at Regent University (Fall 1998).<br />

25 Calabresi, supra note 21, at 1376-77.<br />

26 JAMES WILSON, JAMES WILSON'S SPEECH AT A PUBLIC MEETING (October 6, 1787),<br />

reprinted in 1 DEBATE ON THE CONSTITUTION, at 64 (Bernard Bailyn ed., 1993) [hereinafter<br />

1 DEBATES]. Several other Founders made similar statements. See Answers to Mason's<br />

"Objections", "Marcus" [James Iredell] I-V, NORFOLK AND PORTSMOUTH JOURNAL, Feb. 20,<br />

1788, in 1 DEBATES, supra, at 364; Benjamin Rush, Benjamin Rush to David Ramsay,<br />

COLUMBIAN HERALD (Charleston, S.C.), Apr. 19, 1788, reprinted in 2 DEBATE ON THE<br />

CONSTITUTION, 417 (Bernard Bailyn ed., 1993) [hereinafter 2 DEBATES]; John Marshall on<br />

the Fairness and Jurisdiction of the Federal Courts, in 2 DEBATES, supra, at 740.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 145 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

structure to our constitutional scheme, in the light of history, becomes<br />

more readily apparent. 27<br />

Chief Justice John Marshall reminds us that "[tihe security of a<br />

people against the misconduct of their rulers, must lie in the frequent<br />

recurrence to first principles, and the imposition of adequate<br />

constitutional restrictions." 28 Following the jurist's sage advice, we start<br />

with the first principles upon which the structure of this government<br />

was designed to operate. The overarching practical principle guiding the<br />

Founders was a fear of the concentration of political power in<br />

government. "[I]t would be difficult to deny that in establishing their<br />

complex structure, the Framers were virtually obsessed with a fear -<br />

bordering on what some might uncharitably describe as paranoia - of the<br />

concentration of political power." 29 This fear arose out of another first<br />

principle, that man by his nature is corrupt. Madison stated it<br />

exquisitely:<br />

It may be a reflection on human nature, that such devices should<br />

be necessary to controul the abuses of government. But what is<br />

government itself but the greatest of all reflections on human nature?<br />

If men were angels, no government would be necessary. If angels were<br />

to govern men, neither external nor internal controuls on government<br />

would be necessary. In framing a government which is to be<br />

administered by men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: You<br />

must first enable the government to controul the governed; and in the<br />

next place, oblige it to controul itself. 30<br />

The "devices" he refers to are the structures of government. For, if it<br />

is true that "[e]nlightened statesmen will not always be at the helm," 3 1<br />

then "the defect must be supplied, by so contriving the interior structure<br />

of the government, as that its several constituent parts may, by their<br />

mutual relations, be the means of keeping each other in their proper<br />

places." 32 In essence, the Founders devised the tools of separation of<br />

powers, federalism, checks and balances, and judicial review to keep at<br />

27 "So convinced were the Framers that liberty of the person inheres in structure<br />

that at first they did not consider a Bill of Rights necessary." Clinton v. City of New York,<br />

524 U.S. 417, 450 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring).<br />

28 Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. 87, 144 (1810).<br />

29 Martin H. Redish & Elizabeth J. Cisar, "If Angels Were to Govern". The Need for<br />

Pragmatic Formalism in Separation of Powers Theory, 41 DuKE L.J. 449, 451 (1991).<br />

30 THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 164. As Madison observed elsewhere, "The latent causes of faction are thus sown in the<br />

nature of man; and we see them every where brought into different degrees of activity,<br />

according to different circumstances of civil society." THE FEDERALIST No. 10 (James<br />

Madison), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 406.<br />

31 THE FEDERALIST No. 10 (James Madison), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 407.<br />

32 THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 163.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 146 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

bay the grasping desires of people in government to obtain more power. 33<br />

The best way to achieve that result was to divide power among various<br />

individuals and groups. 34<br />

A third major principle underlying this system is that "The<br />

government of the United States has been emphatically termed a<br />

government of laws, and not of men." 35 This means that rules are<br />

followed despite circumstances and the law offers favor to no one. As<br />

Judge Bork put it during his confirmation hearings: "The judge, to<br />

deserve that trust and that authority, must be every bit as governed by<br />

law as is the Congress, the President, the State Governors and<br />

legislatures, and the American people. No one, including a judge, can be<br />

above the law." 36 Connected with this principle is the fact that we have a<br />

written constitution, which carries with it certain implications. 37<br />

The first implication of our written constitution is that "(tihe<br />

Constitution created a Federal government of limited powers." 38 The<br />

government, therefore, cannot enlarge or contract its powers without<br />

amending the Constitution. The second implication is that the courts<br />

usually should invoke the Constitution as an instrument of continuity in<br />

the system. This is how judges employed the Constitution originally. In<br />

the past, "Decisions holding acts unconstitutional had done no more than<br />

uphold or block legislative or executive initiatives." 39 The reason for this<br />

necessarily follows from the first implication: if the government's powers<br />

are limited and enumerated, then a judge invoking the Constitution has<br />

only so much material to call upon in making his decision. Charles<br />

Cooper, former clerk to Chief Justice Rehnquist, elaborates: "Once a<br />

33 See John Fonte & John Andrews, Why 'The Federalist' Belongs in the Classroom,<br />

INDEPENDENCE ISSUE PAPER (Independence Institute), Dec. 6, 1991, at<br />

http://i2i.org/SuptDocs/Education/FederalistBelongs.htm (last visited Nov. 15, 2001).<br />

In a sense, the entire American constitutional edifice of a democratic<br />

republic with majority rule and minority rights, federalism, limited<br />

government, and the separation of powers among legislative, executive and<br />

judicial branches is based [upon] the Founders' concept of human nature as<br />

derived from their experience and their reading of history.<br />

34 See Calabresi, supra note 5, at 785-86.<br />

35 Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 163 (1803).<br />

36 Nomination of Robert H. Bork to be Associate Justice of the Supreme Court of the<br />

United States: Hearings Before the Comm. on the Judiciary, United States Senate, 100th<br />

Cong. 103 (1987) (opening statement of Robert H. Bork). This speaks to the boundaries<br />

within which a judge can make a ruling. Improper judicial activism, as I said earlier, relies<br />

on the judge's personal predilections of what the law should be, rather than what the law<br />

is. The hope is that structural activism is less likely to be used this way, and thus conforms<br />

to this important principle of our republic.<br />

37 Calabresi, supra note 7, at 1438.<br />

38 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 457 (1991); see also, United States v. Lopez,<br />

514 U.S. 549, 552 (1995) ("The Constitution creates a Federal Government of enumerated<br />

powers.").<br />

39 Cox, supra note 15, at 128.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 147 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

judge ventures beyond the Constitution and the laws of our society, he<br />

has only his individual conscience to call upon, and a judge's conscience<br />

is not law." 40 In other words, the judge should not amend the<br />

Constitution. The Constitution should be a landmark of destination in<br />

constitutional jurisprudence, not a landmark of departure. The third<br />

implication of our written constitution is that judicial review is<br />

inferred. 41 Limited powers and written-down boundaries imply that<br />

there must be some enforcement of those provisions, since "Ithe<br />

distinction between a government with limited and unlimited powers is<br />

abolished, if those limits do not confine the persons on whom they are<br />

imposed." 42 Because "[uit is emphatically the province and duty of the<br />

judicial department to say what the law is," 43 the duty for policing the<br />

boundaries of Constitutional power falls prominently on the courts.<br />

In addition to a fear of centralized political power, the inherent<br />

corrupt nature of man, and the establishment of a government of laws<br />

with a written constitution, another key principle to understanding the<br />

role of structure in our government is the belief that "[n] o man is allowed<br />

to be a judge in his own cause; because his interest would certainly bias<br />

his judgment, and, not improbably, corrupt his integrity.""4 This rule<br />

represents another justification for judicial review. If Congress could<br />

pass laws without any check on whether the legislation was<br />

constitutional, it would "subvert the very foundation of all written<br />

constitutions," 5 because Congress, not the Constitution, would be the<br />

supreme law of the land. 46<br />

A final principle concerning structure and the foundation of our<br />

government, one that cannot be over-stressed, is that the constitutional<br />

design exists to protect the people, not just abstract ideas. In other<br />

words, "Any purported dichotomy between constitutional structure and<br />

40 Charles Cooper, Panel Discussion, supra note 8, at 59.<br />

41 See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 177-78 (1803); see also supra text<br />

accompanying note 11; see also EATON, supra note 9, at 14.<br />

42 Marbury, 5 U.S. at 176-77.<br />

43 Id. at 177. This particular passage is often quoted as purported support by<br />

Marshall of judicial exclusivity in constitutional interpretation. The misrepresentation is<br />

unfortunate because all Marshall was referring to, in the context of the opinion, is the duty<br />

of the judiciary to explain the law when a case comes before it. Of course the judge will tell<br />

the parties what the law is in adjudicating a dispute; that does not mean that Congress<br />

and the President are not able to make their own determinations of what the Constitution<br />

means. Indeed, Congress does so each time it passes legislation.<br />

44 THE FEDERALIST NO. 10 (James Madison), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 406.<br />

45 Marbury, 5 U.S. at 178.<br />

46 John C. Yoo, The <strong>Judicial</strong> Safeguards of Federalism, 70 S. CAL. L. REV. 1311,<br />

1383 (1997); see also City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507, 529 (1997).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 148 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

constitutional rights is a dangerous and false one." 47 Government<br />

institutions are designed to serve as buffers against encroachments on<br />

personal liberties. 4 8 This connects to the previous point that the Bill of<br />

Rights is not the whole or even the focus of the Constitution. The Bill of<br />

Rights was a supplement to the original Constitution, not a replacement.<br />

"The Bill of Rights and the structural elements of the Constitution<br />

should be viewed as a whole . . . ."49 To give short shrift to the structures<br />

of our Constitution is to do great violence to the system as a whole.<br />

"[Tihe entire Constitution was created to avoid tyranny and protect<br />

liberty. To separate out the individual rights provisions for special<br />

judicial protection ignores the document's careful intertwining of 'backup'<br />

systems." 50 Moreover, not only does "bifurcation between<br />

constitutional structure and substantive law" lead to unfaithful<br />

renderings of the text, it also "leads to most unsatisfactory<br />

conclusions."51<br />

These principles lead to one conclusion: that structure is vitally<br />

important to any proper understanding of the Constitution and,<br />

consequently, to proper use of judicial review. "The Framers of the<br />

Constitution could not command statesmanship. They could simply<br />

provide structures from which it might emerge." 52 The Founders did the<br />

only thing they could to provide for a lasting Constitution: frame the<br />

system for success, because after they died the substantive actions of<br />

government would be up to succeeding generations. If the system is<br />

ignored or, worse, deliberately sabotaged, then the parchment-inscribed<br />

words of the Constitution may as well turn to dust; the checks and<br />

balances designed to counteract man's power-hungry ambitions would be<br />

worthless, and even the precious freedoms embodied in the Bill of Rights<br />

would prove little protection against the onslaught of concentrated<br />

political power. 5 3<br />

47 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 452.<br />

48 Id.<br />

49 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1392.<br />

50 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 493.<br />

51 Richard A. Epstein, The Cartelization of Commerce, 22 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y<br />

209, 209 (1998). As usual, Epstein deals with the practical consequences of the structural<br />

theories on the market, rather than their logical pull. This particular article of Epstein's<br />

does not primarily focus on policy, but for an excellent piece focusing on this angle, see<br />

Richard A. Epstein, The Proper Scope of the Commerce Power, 73 VA. L. REV. 1387 (1987).<br />

52 Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417, 452-53 (1998) (Kennedy, J.,<br />

concurring).<br />

53 See Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 697 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 149 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

B. The Framework of Structure<br />

1. Separation of Powers<br />

Given their general importance, it is prudent to examine more<br />

closely each of these structures, and how they are intended to work.<br />

Light will be shone on these structures, bearing in mind the impact that<br />

proper judicial activism should have on each. There were no secrets to<br />

the overarching plan of the Founders in writing the Constitution. They<br />

designed<br />

a national government of limited powers, with those powers divided<br />

among the three branches, each with a different function and different<br />

personnel, and all of this in the context of a federal system in which a<br />

large amount of the totality of all governmental power would be<br />

reserved to the states. 5 4<br />

Two major features of that design are separation of powers and<br />

federalism.<br />

In arguing for passage of the Constitution, Madison tells us that the<br />

"accumulation of all powers legislative, executive and judiciary in the<br />

same hands, whether of one, a few or many, and whether hereditary, self<br />

appointed, or elective, may justly be pronounced the very definition of<br />

tyranny." 5 Because of this, the Founders wrote the principle of<br />

separation of powers directly into the Constitution. 56 As noted above, the<br />

Founders' primary concern was preventing the concentration of political<br />

power, and the separation of powers went directly to this goal. The idea<br />

was grounded on "the deceptively simple principle that no branch may<br />

be permitted to exercise any authority definitionally found to fall outside<br />

its constitutionally delineated powers." 57 The theory holds that if a<br />

person or body is given power to do two or all three of these functions, it<br />

would be very easy to go against the people's wishes and deny freedom<br />

unjustly. For instance, if a person possessing such power promulgated a<br />

law ordering that all babies under the age of two should be killed, that<br />

person could implement the law as well using the executive power. There<br />

would be no way to prevent the execution of the unjust law. If the<br />

legislative and executive functions are divided as the Constitution<br />

provides, however, then the executive could simply refuse to implement<br />

54 Pasco Bowman, The Separation of Powers: Myth or Reality?, in DERAILING THE<br />

CONSTITUTION 114, 117 (Edward B. McLean ed., 1995).<br />

55 THE FEDERALIST NO. 47 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 121.<br />

56 "All legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United<br />

States .... U.S. CONST. art. I, § 1. "The executive Power shall be vested in a President of<br />

the United States of America." U.S. CONST. art. II, § 1, cl. 1. "The judicial power of the<br />

United States, shall be vested in one Supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as<br />

Congress may from time to time ordain and establish." U.S. CONST. art. III, § 1.<br />

57 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 453.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 150 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

the unjust law, protecting the citizenry. Additionally, since the judicial<br />

department in such a system is separate and independent from the other<br />

two, it could declare the law void and have it thrown out altogether,<br />

using the power of judicial review.<br />

Of course, that is the theory. As the Supreme Court has noted, for<br />

the Founders, "[Tihe doctrine of separation of powers was not mere<br />

theory; it was a felt necessity." 58 Therefore, Madison and the others<br />

believed that "a mere demarkation [sic] on parchment of the<br />

constitutional limits of the several departments, is not a sufficient guard<br />

against those encroachments which lead to a tyrannical concentration of<br />

all the powers of government in the same hands." 59 They needed more<br />

than the words in the Constitution to insure that this vital principle<br />

would be observed. To that end, the Founders included what have<br />

become known as checks and balances in the framework of the<br />

Constitution. The goal was a government where "the powers of<br />

government should be so divided and balanced among several bodies of<br />

magistracy, as that no one could transcend their legal limits, without<br />

being effectually checked and restrained by the others." 60 When Madison<br />

said, "[aimbition must be made to counteract ambition," 61 he meant, in<br />

part, that each branch should watch the others. Thus, we have the<br />

Presidential veto, Senate confirmation of Presidential appointments,<br />

judicial appointments by the President, and so on. "[The Constitution]<br />

enjoins upon its branches separateness but interdependence, autonomy<br />

but reciprocity." 62<br />

The Founders were attacked for this "mixture" of powers, so<br />

ingrained was the idea of separation in the minds of the people.63 Yet,<br />

because they believed that the doctrine needed to be more than a<br />

"parchment barrier," the Founders stuck to their proposal.<br />

The men who met in Philadelphia in the summer of 1787 were<br />

practical statesmen, experienced in politics, who viewed the principle<br />

of separation of powers as a vital check against tyranny. But they<br />

likewise saw that a hermetic sealing off of the three branches of<br />

58 Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 593 (1952) (Frankfurter,<br />

J., concurring).<br />

59 THE FEDERALIST No. 48 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 141.<br />

60 Id. at 139.<br />

61 THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 164.<br />

62 Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co., 343 U.S. at 635 (Jackson, J., concurring).<br />

63 See, e.g., Reply to Wilson's Speech: "Centinel"[Samuel Bryan] 11 (1787), in 1<br />

DEBATES, supra note 26, at 77, 87; Reply to Wilson's Speech: "Cincinnatus"[Arthur Lee] V<br />

(1787), in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 114, 117; Joseph Spencer to James Madison,<br />

Enclosing John Leland's Objections (1788), in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 267, 269.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 151 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

(Vol. 14:141<br />

Government from one another would preclude the establishment of a<br />

Nation capable of governing itself effectively.64<br />

Out of the theory of separation comes the principle of nondelegation.<br />

Congress may not delegate its legislative power to the<br />

President, not only to prevent tyranny, but also to hold Congress<br />

accountable. 65 "Unchecked delegation would undercut the legislature's<br />

accountability to the electorate and subject people to rule through ad hoc<br />

commands rather than democratically considered general laws." 66 If<br />

Congress could delegate its legislative power to the executive, people<br />

could not find out easily who is responsible for legislation they disagree<br />

with or wish to change. 67 The non-delegation principle holds even though<br />

Congress presumably waives it voluntarily. This is because "the concept<br />

of congressional waiver ignores the fact that separation of powers<br />

protections were not inserted to protect the other branches, but rather to<br />

protect the populace." 68 So, not only is separation of powers designed to<br />

be a preventive measure against tyranny; it is also supposed to enhance<br />

the working of democracy. 69<br />

Separation of powers is clearly an important institutional tool, and<br />

as the Court has pointed out, "To preserve those checks, and maintain<br />

the separation of powers, the carefully defined limits on the power of<br />

each Branch must not be eroded." 70 The only questions remaining are:<br />

how are the lines between the branches drawn, and who is to draw<br />

them? The first question is beyond this paper's scope, and so it is<br />

minimally addressed. Traditionally, promulgation of laws is generally<br />

considered a legislative function, while their execution is considered an<br />

executive function, and interpretation of those laws in the context of a<br />

particular dispute is a judicial function. Defining which is which on some<br />

occasions is a difficult task, as even James Madison admitted. 71 No<br />

64 Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 121 (1976).<br />

65 Field v. Clark, 143 U.S. 649, 692 (1892).<br />

66 David Schoenbrod, The Delegation Doctrine: Could the Court Give it Substance?,<br />

83 MICH. L. REV. 1223, 1224 (1985).<br />

67 Id. at 1244-45.<br />

68 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 487. This point is similar to one we shall see<br />

later concerning federalism. Structural principles, just like the Bill of Rights, are first and<br />

foremost intended as protections for the people, not the government.<br />

69 Justice Kennedy puts it pointedly: "Abdication of responsibility is not part of the<br />

constitutional design." Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417, 452 (1998) (Kennedy, J.,<br />

concurring). For a work expounding on the value of the separation of powers as a bulwark<br />

of liberty, see Rebecca L. Brown, Separated Powers and Ordered Liberty, 139 U. PA. L.<br />

REV. 1513 (1991).<br />

70 INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 957-58 (1983).<br />

71 James Madison to Thomas Jefferson (Oct. 24, 1787), reprinted in 1 DEBATES,<br />

supra note 26, at 192, 198. "Even the boundaries between the Executive, Legislative &<br />

Judiciary powers, though in general so strongly marked in themselves, consist in many<br />

instances of mere shades of difference." Id.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 152 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

matter how they are defined in detail, because the Constitution explicitly<br />

states that the federal government only possesses those powers<br />

delegated to it (through written enumeration), "the separation of powers<br />

provisions clearly impose an absolute, rather than a conditional,<br />

standard of implementation." 72<br />

Tied closely to the necessity of an absolute standard is the answer to<br />

the second question: who draws the lines distinguishing power between<br />

the branches? This question dovetails directly with the themes of this<br />

paper. Two requirements are necessary to have a vigorous separation of<br />

powers doctrine: absolute standards and an independent judiciary. 73 The<br />

Founders believed that the courts would be a necessary part of<br />

separation enforcement. As mentioned above, checks and balances were<br />

a key ingredient to the Founders' version of separation of powers.<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> review was one of those checks. Alexander Hamilton referred to<br />

the courts as "bulwarks of a limited constitution against legislative<br />

encroachments." 4 The Founders believed that "the courts were designed<br />

to be an intermediate body between the people and the legislature, in<br />

order, among other things, to keep the latter within the limits assigned<br />

to their authority." 75 Part of that protection includes holding fast to the<br />

separation of powers principle. This is one of the several reasons that the<br />

Constitution provides for an independent judiciary: an independent<br />

arbiter is needed to settle disputes of power between the executive and<br />

legislative branches. To have Congress decide for itself what powers it<br />

can delegate would violate the founding principle, discussed in Part A,<br />

that no one is to be the judge in his own case; the conflict of interest for<br />

Congress is obvious. 76 Conversely, leaving the decision to the President<br />

feeds the natural desire for power that the Founders sought so far as<br />

possible to squelch.<br />

Dividing the powers of government seems almost second nature to<br />

us, since it has been practiced for so long. At the Constitution's<br />

inception, it was considered a relatively new, scientific advance in the<br />

72 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 503. For a work attempting to give an answer<br />

on how to define the powers along this line, see Schoenbrod, supra note 67 (offering a<br />

complex theory for the Court in attempting to enforce the delegation doctrine to replace the<br />

unworkable "intelligible principle" rule, and giving several reasons why it should do so. He<br />

argues for a qualitative test for proper delegation of power by Congress to the Executive, as<br />

opposed to a quantitative one).<br />

73 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 458.<br />

74 THE FEDERALIST No. 78 (Alexander Hamilton), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra<br />

note 26, at 471-72.<br />

75 Id. at 470.<br />

76 Redish & Cisar, supra note 30, at 498.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 153 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

practice of government. 77 It was deemed so important to the creation of<br />

the new government that the writers of the Constitution deliberately<br />

placed the powers of each branch of government in three separate<br />

articles of the document, to emphasize their distinct natures and unique<br />

responsibilities. Yet, separation for its own sake was not the goal, as we<br />

have seen with the simultaneous creation of the system of checks and<br />

balances. Protection of liberty, within a working system of government,<br />

was the goal. That is still the goal and the reason why judicial activism<br />

is necessary in this area. The judiciary fulfills its duty in the separation<br />

scheme, enforces congressional accountability, and protects the people as<br />

a whole when it enforces a strict separation of powers doctrine. 78<br />

2. Federalism<br />

On the subject of federalism, John Marshall stated that "[iun<br />

America, the powers of sovereignty are divided between the government<br />

of the Union, and those of the states. They are each sovereign, with<br />

respect to the objects committed to it, and neither is sovereign with<br />

respect to the objects committed to the other." 79 Put simply, "our<br />

Constitution establishes a system of dual sovereignty between the states<br />

and the Federal Government." 80 This design was nothing short of<br />

revolutionary, and, perhaps, not so simple. It was a common maxim of<br />

politics before the Constitution that two sovereign entities could not<br />

exist within the same boundaries. Anti-Federalists, such as Thomas<br />

Tredwell, pointed this out consistently as a flaw in the new<br />

governmental system. "The idea of two distinct sovereigns in the same<br />

country, separately possessed of sovereign and supreme power, in the<br />

same matters at the same time, is as supreme an absurdity, as that two<br />

distinct separate circles can be bounded exactly by the same<br />

circumference." 8 ' The idea understandably confused them, and even<br />

confused some of the Constitution's supporters. 8 2 This confusion led to<br />

77 "The chief improvement in government, in modern times, has been the compleat<br />

[sic] separation of the great distinctions of power. . . ."Reply to Wilson's Speech: "Centinel"<br />

[Samuel Bryan] 11 (1787), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 77, 87.<br />

78 Schoenbrod, supra note 67, at 1278. The Court is not the only check in the<br />

separation scheme, obviously, but it plays a pivotal role.<br />

79 McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316, 410 (1819).<br />

80 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 457 (1991).<br />

81 1 THE DEBATES, RESOLUTIONS, AND OTHER PROCEEDINGS, IN CONVENTION, ON<br />

THE ADOPTION OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION 6 (Jonathan Elliot ed., Washington 1827).<br />

82 "Can the sovereignty of each state in all its parts exist, if there be a sovereignty<br />

over the whole[?] Is it not nonsense in terms, to suppose an united government of any kind,<br />

over 13 co-existent sovereignties?" Rebuttal to "An Officer of the Late Continental Army":<br />

"Plain Truth", INDEPENDENT GAZETTEER (Philadelphia), Nov. 10, 1787, reprinted in 1<br />

DEBATES, supra note 26, at 105-06. Historian Forrest McDonald has observed, "[The<br />

Founders] introduced an entirely new concept into the discourse, that of federalism, and in<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 154 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

repeated attacks that the Constitution would destroy the sovereignty of<br />

the states. 83 The Founders, just as repeatedly, denied these claims. "The<br />

proposed Constitution, so far from implying an abolition of the State<br />

Governments, makes them constituent parts of the national sovereignty<br />

by allowing them a direct representation in the Senate, and leaves in<br />

their possession certain exclusive and very important portions of<br />

sovereign power."84<br />

Given the controversy, "[ilt would be in vain to deny the possibility<br />

of a clashing and collision between the measures of the two<br />

governments." 85 Accordingly, Justice O'Connor proclaimed that<br />

"discerning the proper division of authority between the Federal<br />

Government and the States" is a question "as old as the Constitution." 86<br />

This old question arises because the principle of federalism, that<br />

different levels of government possess authority in different areas, is not<br />

textually stated in the Constitution. The reason the Supreme Court<br />

accepts it as a "fundamental principle" is that federalism is fairly easily<br />

implied in the Constitution. 87 The Tenth Amendment all but states the<br />

principle in black and white: "The powers not delegated to the United<br />

States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are<br />

reserved to the States respectively, or to the people." 85 However, recall<br />

that many Founders felt the Bill of Rights originally unnecessary -<br />

particularly in this area. James Madison cited the principle of<br />

enumeration, flowing from a written constitution, as proof of the matter.<br />

"The powers delegated by the proposed Constitution to the Federal<br />

Government are few and defined. Those which are to remain in the State<br />

Governments are numerous and indefinite." 8 9 This fact, a written<br />

constitution, testifies to the existing sovereignty of the states.<br />

the doing, created a novas ordo seclorum: a new order of the ages." Forrest McDonald,<br />

Novus ORDO SECLORUM: THE INTELLECTUAL ORIGINS OF THE CONSTITUTION, 261 (1985).<br />

83 "[I] repeat, that the proposed constitution must eventually annihilate the<br />

independant [sic] sovereignty of the several states." "The Defect is in the System Itself:<br />

Robert Whitehill on the Dangers of the Powers of Congress and the Illogic of the Habeas<br />

Corpus Clause, reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 811.<br />

84 THE FEDERALIST No. 9 (Alexander Hamilton), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note<br />

26, at 344. It will be noticed that half of the argument Hamilton gives here for state<br />

sovereignty, i.e., the election of Senators to Congress by state legislatures, no longer exists<br />

because of the Seventeenth Amendment. This structural change will play a part in some<br />

observations later in the paper.<br />

85 Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. 1, 238 (1824) (Johnson, J., concurring).<br />

86 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 149 (1992).<br />

87 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 457 (1991).<br />

88 U.S. CONST. amend. X.<br />

89 THE FEDERALIST No. 45 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 105. Alexander Hamilton expressed a similar sentiment, believing that "the State<br />

Governments would clearly retain all the rights of sovereignty which they before had and<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 155 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

One statement in the text, however, arguably changes everything:<br />

the Supremacy Clause. 90 Several view this clause as the proverbial<br />

"trump card" in federalism issues. 91 That was certainly the feeling of<br />

many opposed to the proposed Constitution. The dissenters in the<br />

Pennsylvania ratifying convention, listing their reasons for voting in the<br />

negative, stated that:<br />

two co-ordinate sovereignties would be a solecism in politics... one or<br />

the other would necessarily triumph in the fullness of dominion.<br />

However, the contest could not be of long continuance, as the state<br />

governments are divested of every means of defence, and will be<br />

obliged by "the supreme law of the land" to yield at discretion. 92<br />

That threat of Federal dominance, however, remained relatively<br />

benign for about seventy-five years, as the Supreme Court policed the<br />

boundaries between state and federal power with a careful eye. 93 Then<br />

something happened which changed the federal-state structure<br />

dramatically: the Civil War. "[Hlistorical federalism has been repealed<br />

by history. Much of that repeal occurred at the time of the Civil War<br />

when the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments to the Constitution<br />

were passed, conferring broad new powers on the federal government." 9<br />

The Court did not take broad practical notice of this until the 1930s.<br />

Beginning in the 1930s, however, and with accelerating speed after<br />

1937, the Supreme Court began to abandon its textually implied role<br />

of playing jurisdictional policeman in order to take up a new<br />

antitextual role as a nationalist rights-creating body. The structural<br />

constitutionalism of the written text fell by the wayside .... 95<br />

Some believe that this change announced the death of federalism in<br />

America. 9 6 Today's Supreme Court apparently does not agree. Justice<br />

O'Connor referred to our system as one of "dual sovereignty" in an<br />

opinion for the Court in 199197 and quoted at length some very strong<br />

which were not by that act exclusively delegated to the United States." THE FEDERALIST<br />

No. 32 (Alexander Hamilton), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 678.<br />

90 "This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in<br />

Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of<br />

the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land.. . ." U.S. CONST. art. VI, cl. 2.<br />

91 Dissent of the Minority of the Pennsylvania Convention, PENNSYLVANIA PACKET<br />

(Philadelphia), Dec. 18, 1787, reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 538.<br />

92 Id.<br />

93 Calabresi, supra note 21, at 1377.<br />

94 Richard Neely, Mother, God, and Federalism, in DERAILING THE CONSTITUTION,<br />

supra note 55, at 89-90; see also Yoo, supra note 46, at 59 n.10.<br />

95 Calabresi, supra note 21, at 1377.<br />

96 Neely, supra note 94, at 90 ("When today's political science professors point out<br />

that the federal government is a government of'delegated' powers, we all chuckle because<br />

by common consent state power has become more a matter of administrative convenience<br />

than an element of sovereignty.").<br />

97 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 457 (1991).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 156 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

states-rights language from an 1869 Supreme Court decision. 98 While<br />

this may indeed represent more lip-service than reality to the federalism<br />

situation today, the Court has backed these strong words with several<br />

federalism-premised decisions. 99 So it seems that federalism's funeral<br />

was premature, and it behooves us to notice why this structural<br />

provision has been so resilient a constitutional player.<br />

The chief danger the Founders sought to guard against was a<br />

concentration of political power. In a republic, this could happen just as<br />

easily through a tyranny of the majority as a tyranny of one branch of<br />

government. One charge against the proposed Constitution, and one of<br />

the known political axioms of the time, was that for a republic to<br />

function, it must be small in geographic size, because the representatives<br />

of the government must be capable of gauging the needs and desires of<br />

the people. 10 0 The larger the sphere being governed, the more difficult<br />

this becomes.<br />

James Madison and the other Founders turned this axiom on its<br />

head, claiming that "the larger the society, provided it lie within a<br />

practicable sphere, the more duly capable it will be of self<br />

government." 10 1 Madison explained that to secure the public good and<br />

private rights from the dangers of factions (i.e. special interests) ruling<br />

in government, it was necessary to<br />

leixtend the sphere, and you take in a greater variety of parties and<br />

interests; you make it less probable that a majority of the whole will<br />

have a common motive to invade the rights of other citizens; or if such<br />

a common motive exits, it will be more difficult for all who feel it to<br />

discover their own strength, and to act in unison with each other. 0 2<br />

98 Id. (quoting Texas v. White, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 700, 725 (1868)).<br />

Not only, therefore, can there be no loss of separate and independent<br />

autonomy to the States, through their union under the Constitution, but it<br />

may be not unreasonably said that the preservation of the States, and the<br />

maintenance of their governments, are as much within the design and care<br />

of the Constitution as the preservation of the Union and the maintenance of<br />

the National Government. The Constitution, in all its provisions, looks to<br />

an indestructible Union, composed of indestructible States.<br />

Id.<br />

99 See Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997) (holding that Congress cannot<br />

commandeer state executive officials to carry out federal programs, without the officials'<br />

consents); United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995) (holding that the "Gun Free School<br />

Zone Act" exceeded congressional authority to regulate interstate commerce); New York v.<br />

United States, 505 U.S. 144 (1992) (holding generally that the Constitution does not<br />

authorize Congress to commandeer state legislatures to legislate for them).<br />

100 THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 167-68.<br />

101 Id. at 168.<br />

102 THE FEDERALIST No. 10 (James Madison), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 410.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 157 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

Moreover, not only does federalism diminish the likelihood of a<br />

tyranny by the people; as Hamilton explained, it also discourages<br />

tyranny by government.<br />

This balance between the national and the state governments ought to<br />

be dwelt on with peculiar attention, as it is of the utmost<br />

importance.-It forms a double security to the people. If one<br />

encroaches on their rights, they will find a powerful protection in the<br />

other.-Indeed they will both be prevented from overpassing their<br />

constitutional limits, by a certain rivalship, which will ever subsist<br />

between them. 103<br />

Federalism thus protects the liberty of the people from their<br />

governments by having two of them, and it protects liberty from factions<br />

of people by extending the sphere that a faction must control before it<br />

becomes potent. This is why Madison believed that in "the extent and<br />

proper structure of the Union, therefore, we behold a Republican remedy<br />

for the diseases most incident to Republican Government." 1o4 The chance<br />

for a successful republic hinges heavily on proper structure.<br />

The Court has invalidated statutes commandeering state officials<br />

because skirting the structure of federalism diminishes the<br />

accountability of Congress and of state officials. "Accountability is thus<br />

diminished when, due to federal coercion, elected state officials cannot<br />

regulate in accordance with the views of the local electorate in matters<br />

not pre-empted by federal regulation." 1 5 Both parties can "pass the<br />

buck:" Congress by having state officials implement unpopular<br />

programs, keeping congressmen "insulated from the electoral<br />

ramifications of their decision;" 10 6 and state officials by blaming Congress<br />

for passage of unpopular legislation. The people thereby have difficulty<br />

holding the responsible party accountable, defeating the purpose of a<br />

republic.1 0 7 A strict adherence to federalism prevents this occurrence.<br />

"American federalism in the end is not a trivial matter or a quaint<br />

historical anachronism. American-style federalism is a thriving and vital<br />

institutional arrangement." 10 8 As the Supreme Court has explained,<br />

103 Melancton Smith and Alexander Hamilton Debate Representation, Aristocracy,<br />

and Interests (1788), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 772.<br />

104 THE FEDERALIST No. 10 (James Madison), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 411.<br />

105 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 169 (1992).<br />

Id.<br />

106 Id.<br />

107 See United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 576-77 (1995).<br />

If, as Madison expected, the Federal and State Governments are to control<br />

each other ... and hold each other in check by competing for the affections<br />

of the people ... those citizens must have some means of knowing which of<br />

the two governments to hold accountable for the failure to perform a given<br />

function.<br />

108 Calabresi, supra note 5, at 770.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 158 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

[Federalism] assures a decentralized government that will be more<br />

sensitive to the diverse needs of a heterogeneous society; it increases<br />

opportunity for citizen involvement in democratic process; it allows for<br />

more innovation and experimentation in government; and it makes<br />

government more responsive by putting the States in competition for a<br />

mobile citizenry. 10 9<br />

Most importantly, as the Founders emphasized, federalism serves as a<br />

check on the abuse of government power, helping achieve the<br />

Constitution's main goal. 110<br />

The only question remaining is who polices the boundaries between<br />

the federal and state governments? The necessity of a policeman seems<br />

obvious. "If this 'double security' [of federalism] is to be effective, there<br />

must be a proper balance between the States and the Federal<br />

Government. These twin powers will act as mutual restraints only if<br />

both are credible. In the tension between federal and state power lies the<br />

promise of liberty.""' Once again the first principles discussed in Part A<br />

come into play. Since our written Constitution implies the federalist<br />

system, and because a State or Federal legislative branch deciding who<br />

controls what violates the rule that no man should be a judge in his own<br />

case, an impartial arbiter is needed to canvass the structure of the Great<br />

Text and decide these issues. If Congress called the shots, it would<br />

clearly be able to all but destroy the states, given the existence of the<br />

Supremacy Clause. If the State legislatures called the shots, the Federal<br />

government would become impotent, as was the case under the Articles<br />

of Confederation.<br />

The impartiality of the judiciary again plays a vital role. Some<br />

believe that federal courts will not be impartial in reality, because when<br />

they expand Congress' power, they expand their own. 112 The force of this<br />

argument is difficult to deny. However, "When we talk about the<br />

institutional competence of either the Court or Congress [or any body for<br />

that matter], we must remember that we are talking about an 'as<br />

compared to what' question .... A perfect, reliable institutional actor<br />

does not exist." 113 Congress is the institution best suited to policy-making<br />

109 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 458 (1991).<br />

110 Id.<br />

S11 Id. at 459.<br />

112 Brutus, an arch Anti-Federalist, predicted as much:<br />

Every body of men invested with office are tenacious of power.., the same<br />

principle will influence them [the judiciary] to extend their power, and<br />

increase their rights; this of it itself will operate strongly upon the courts to<br />

give such a meaning to the constitution in all cases where it can possibly be<br />

done, as will enlarge the sphere of their own authority."<br />

Brutus X/, N.Y. J., Jan. 31, 1788, reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 129,<br />

134.<br />

113 Lillian R. BeVier, Religion in Congress and the Courts: Issues of Institutional<br />

Competence, 22 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 59, 62-63 (1998).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 159 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

(Vol. 14:141<br />

because it takes the widest range of views into consideration, it can act<br />

prophylactically, and it allows for broad public debate. It is not the<br />

perfect institution of law-making, but it is the best our experience has<br />

enabled us to produce. The same argument applies to the judiciary in<br />

deciding federalism questions. An impartial actor familiar with the<br />

system of the Founders is necessary to make these decisions. Is the<br />

Court ideally impartial for the task? It probably is not, but it is the best<br />

institutional actor we have for the task. It only makes sense that<br />

"continuing vigilance of the courts in protecting states' rights is of<br />

critical importance if the state-federal balance of power so necessary to<br />

the preservation of our liberty is to be maintained." n4<br />

C. Separation of Powers and Federalism: A Seamless Web<br />

Examined individually, separation of powers and federalism are<br />

both important concepts in our constitutional scheme. Yet, we only<br />

studied them in this manner for ease of examination. In reality, the two<br />

are anything but separate. "[The Framers] used the principles of<br />

separation of powers and federalism to secure liberty in the fundamental<br />

political sense of the term, quite in addition to the idea of freedom from<br />

intrusive governmental acts." 115 In fact, federalism can be seen as part of<br />

the system of separation of powers because it separates power vertically,<br />

where division of power among the branches separates it horizontally. As<br />

Madison himself indicates,<br />

In the compound republic of America, the power surrendered by the<br />

people, is first divided between two distinct governments, and then the<br />

portion allotted to each, subdivided among distinct and separate<br />

departments. Hence a double security arises to the rights of the<br />

people. The different governments will controul each other; at the<br />

same time that each will be controuled by itself. 116<br />

Sometimes, when faced with attacks on their model of federalism,<br />

the Founders responded by pointing to the separation of powers as an<br />

additional bulwark for preserving federalism.11 7 In New York v. United<br />

States, 11 8 a federalism case, the Court cites two separation of powers<br />

114 John C. Yoo, <strong>Judicial</strong> Review and Federalism, 22 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY 197<br />

(1998). When I say "courts," in this case I refer to those both at the state and federal levels.<br />

Both exist to protect rights, thus both also exist to secure structure.<br />

115 Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417, 452 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring).<br />

116 THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 166.<br />

The reader will note the stark similarity between this point and the one made by Hamilton<br />

found in the text at note 104. The repetition is no accident, because the scheme of<br />

government was no accident. Creating "double securities" for the people against tyranny<br />

from any quadrant constantly consumed the designs of the Founders.<br />

117 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1384-85.<br />

118 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144 (1992).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 160 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

cases, Buckley v. Valeo" 1 9 and INS v. Chadha, 120 to make its point<br />

concerning the consent of state officials to congressional actions. "The<br />

constitutional authority of Congress cannot be expanded by the 'consent'<br />

of the governmental unit whose domain is thereby narrowed, whether<br />

that unit is the Executive Branch or the States." 121 All of this<br />

demonstrates that federalism and separation of powers are inextricably<br />

linked together. "Just as the separation and independence of the<br />

coordinate branches of the Federal Government serve to prevent the<br />

accumulation of excessive power in any one branch, a healthy balance of<br />

power between the States and the Federal Government will reduce the<br />

risk of tyranny and abuse from either front." 122 A dedication to one<br />

requires dedication to the other, and more important for our purposes,<br />

judicial cognizance of one demands that both be upheld to insure that<br />

the Constitution's framework is implemented in an accurate and<br />

responsible fashion.<br />

III. JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE STRUCTURAL CONSTITUTION<br />

So far, we have looked at the immense importance of the<br />

Constitution's structures for the proper working of government and<br />

protection of the people. For this article's purpose, that is only half the<br />

story. <strong>Judicial</strong> review, the greatest countermajoritarian structure in the<br />

whole constitutional scheme must be examined in detail to see when its<br />

exercise is justified. The dogmatic Anti-Federalist, Brutus, describing<br />

the Supreme Court, said:<br />

It is, moreover, of great importance, to examine with care the nature<br />

and extent of the judicial power, because those who are to be vested<br />

with it, are to be placed in a situation altogether unprecedented in a<br />

free country. They are to be rendered totally independent, both of the<br />

people and the legislature, both with respect to their offices and their<br />

salaries. No errors they commit can be corrected by any power above<br />

them, if any such power there be, nor can they be removed from office<br />

for making ever so many erroneous adjudications. 123<br />

Brutus may be guilty of some hyperbole, but makes a sound point:<br />

no other judicial body in the world had the power that is invested in the<br />

Supreme Court through the Constitution. Once again, the Founders<br />

turned political theory on its head; the common wisdom was that the<br />

people always knew best and ought not be questioned. The Founders<br />

119 Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976).<br />

120 INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983).<br />

121 New York, 505 U.S. at 182.<br />

122 Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 458 (1991).<br />

123 "Brutus"XI, N.Y. J., Jan. 31, 1788, reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 129,<br />

129. We shall visit with Brutus a few more times before the end of this section because his<br />

observations prove telling, even if exaggerated.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 161 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

agreed with this to a great extent, but not in its entirety. They believed<br />

that certain principles of the government needed firmer grounding than<br />

a simple reliance on the passions of the people. This belief sprang from<br />

the principle discussed in Section II, Part A, that people were fallible and<br />

often succumbed to their darker passions. The Founders maintained that<br />

"it is the reason of the public alone that ought to controul and regulate<br />

the government. The passions ought to be controuled and regulated by<br />

the government." 124<br />

This was one reason for a written constitution that was difficult to<br />

amend: people's darker passions must be kept from changing the<br />

Constitution each time something excited them. Our written<br />

Constitution intentionally placed certain principles beyond the ordinary<br />

reach of the people. After all, the point of a written constitution is<br />

diminished, if not obliterated, if it is constantly changed. 125 The<br />

Constitution was not intended to be entirely democratic. 126 Controlling<br />

the public's passions was also a reason behind creating an independent<br />

judicial branch with appointments that last during good behavior and<br />

untouchable salaries for the judges. The Founders wanted a branch that<br />

would handle constitutional questions in a dispassionate and reasoned<br />

way, one that would not be afraid of challenging the will of the people<br />

when extraordinary circumstances called for it. The Articles of<br />

Confederation did not provide for a judicial branch, so no venue existed<br />

to settle federal questions. No constitutional challenge to legislation<br />

could be made at the federal level. The Founders attempted to remedy<br />

these things through the creation of a body with an unprecedented<br />

power: judicial review.<br />

There is doubt, but not an immense amount of it, that the Founders<br />

intended judicial review to exist. Alexander Hamilton observes in<br />

Federalist 78, "[ln a government in which [the different departmentsl<br />

are separated from each other, the judiciary, from the nature of its<br />

functions will always be the least dangerous to the political rights of the<br />

constitution; because it will be least in a capacity to annoy or injure<br />

them."'1 27 People may chuckle when they read this, assuming that<br />

Hamilton must not have taken into account, or conceived of, the power of<br />

judicial review when he wrote this now famous text. The facts are the<br />

opposite. In the same paper, Hamilton expressed the first rationale for<br />

124 THE FEDERALIST No. 49 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 146.<br />

125 Just look at France, with its experience of the Revolution of 1789 and the ensuing<br />

Terror of 1793-1794.<br />

126 J. Clifford Wallace, The Jurisprudence of <strong>Judicial</strong> Restraint: A Return to the<br />

Moorings, 50 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1, 2 (1981).<br />

127 THE FEDERALIST, No. 78 (Alexander Hamilton), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra<br />

note 26, at 468.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 162 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

judicial review, one that John Marshall would copy later in his Marbury<br />

v. Madison 128 opinion.<br />

The complete independence of the courts of justice is peculiarly<br />

essential in a limited constitution .... Limitations of this kind can be<br />

preserved in practice no other way than through the medium of the<br />

courts of justice; whose duty it must be to declare all acts contrary to<br />

the manifest tenor of the constitution void. 1 29<br />

The argument for judicial review given here is purely structural:<br />

judicial review exists because of the fact of a written constitution and the<br />

need to keep a limited government within its proscribed boundaries.<br />

Hamilton carries the structural importance of the judiciary even further.<br />

"[Tihe courts," Hamilton says, "were designed to be an intermediate body<br />

between the people and the legislature, in order, among other things, to<br />

keep the latter within the limits assigned to their authority." 130 Hamilton<br />

was not the only Founder to explicitly argue for judicial review, 131 and<br />

each made the appeal on structural and institutional grounds, taking<br />

care to emphasize the independence of the judiciary.<br />

Brutus also predicted the existence of judicial review, but, unlike<br />

his adversaries, he did not look upon the innovation as a cause for<br />

celebration. He charged that<br />

in their decisions [the Supreme Court] will not confine themselves to<br />

any fixed or established rules, but will determine, according to what<br />

appears to them, the reason and spirit of the constitution .... This<br />

128 Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137 (1803).<br />

129 THE FEDERALIST No. 78 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 469.<br />

130 Id. at 470.<br />

131 James Wilson, second only to Madison in influence on the crafting of the<br />

Constitution, and later a justice of the Supreme Court, remarked in the Pennsylvania<br />

ratifying convention that "when [congressional legislation] comes to be discussed, before<br />

the judges-when they consider its principles, and find it to be incompatible with the<br />

superior power of the constitution, it is their duty to pronounce it void." James Wilson<br />

Replies to Findley (1787), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 820, 823.<br />

Oliver Ellsworth, a staunch Federalist and later Chief Justice of the Supreme Court<br />

for four years, described his view of the courts under the proposed constitution in the<br />

Connecticut ratifying convention:<br />

This constitution defines the extent of the powers of the general<br />

government. If the general legislature should at any time overleap their<br />

limits, the judicial department is a constitutional check. If the United<br />

States go beyond their powers, if they make a law which the constitution<br />

does not authorise, it is void; and the judicial power, the national judges,<br />

who to secure their impartiality are made independent, will declare it void.<br />

Oliver Ellsworth Defends the Taxing Power and Comments on Dual Sovereignties and<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> Review (1788), reprinted in 1 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 887, 883; see also,<br />

"Americanus" [John Stevens, Jr.] VII, DAILY ADVERTISER (N.Y.), (Jan. 21, 1788), reprinted<br />

in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at 60.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 163 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

power in the judicial, will enable them to mould the government, into<br />

almost any shape they please. 132<br />

Though some may think that this is exactly what happened, and<br />

there is ample cause to think as such, it is not what the Founders<br />

intended. "In its inception, judicial review was a limited and legalistic<br />

concept, a product of logic designed to serve a carefully defined<br />

purpose." 133 The "legalistic concept" was for the Court to serve as one of<br />

the checks on the other branches powers. As Hamilton responded to the<br />

charge,<br />

The courts must declare the sense of the law; and if they should be<br />

disposed to exercise WILL instead of JUDGMENT, the consequences<br />

would equally be the substitution of their pleasure to that of the<br />

legislative body. The observation, if it proved any thing, would prove<br />

that there ought be no judges distinct from that body [Congress]. 134<br />

Forming a government without a judiciary had already been tried<br />

under the Articles of Confederation, an abysmal failure, and so the<br />

Founders (and even more importantly the People, who ratified the<br />

Constitution) were not about to make the same mistake twice. Hamilton<br />

and other supporters of the Constitution truly believed that the judiciary<br />

would possess "neither Force nor Will, but merely judgment; and must<br />

ultimately depend on the aid of the executive arm even for the efficacy of<br />

its judgments." 135 In other words, the powers vested in the judiciary were<br />

the least susceptible to despotism, because the courts could do little or<br />

nothing without the acquiescence of at least one of the other two<br />

branches to carry out their decisions.<br />

Regardless of what the Founders intended, because of the absence of<br />

an explicit rendering in the text and its ostensible operation as an antidemocratic<br />

device, judicial review is "a deviant institution in the<br />

American democracy." 136 <strong>Judicial</strong> review is not celebrated (outside<br />

132 "Brutus" XI, N.Y. J. (Jan. 31, 1788), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26, at<br />

129, 132, 135.<br />

133 EATON, supra note 9, at 13.<br />

134 THE FEDERALIST No. 78 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 471.<br />

135 Id. at 468. Hamilton's point is buttressed by the findings of Forrest McDonald,<br />

who writes:<br />

The delegates devoted less time to forming the judiciary-and less<br />

attention to careful craftsmanship-than they had expended on the<br />

legislative and executive branches. In part the judiciary received minimal<br />

consideration because it was regarded as the least powerful and least active<br />

branch of government. In part, too . . . the delegates were in general<br />

agreement as to the principles that should be embodied in forming it.<br />

MCDONALD, supra note 82, at 253.<br />

136 ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT<br />

AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 18 (1962). It should be noted that not everyone agrees that the<br />

Court, properly understood, is a countermajoritarian device. It can be argued that when<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 164 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

narrow legal circles) for its wonderful contributions to the American<br />

political system. "The root difficulty is that judicial review is a countermajoritarian<br />

force in our system." 137 This observation by the late<br />

Professor Alexander Bickel is the chief criticism of judicial review in<br />

general and judicial activism in particular. The "counter-majoritarian<br />

difficulty" 138 is that, in general, decisions in our society are supposed to<br />

be made by the elective branches of our government. When a judge<br />

declares an act of Congress or the President void, he short-circuits the<br />

democratic process, and at the Supreme Court level, places the issue out<br />

of the reach of ordinary debate. 139 This practice can damage the very<br />

system it is designed to maintain, namely rule by the People through a<br />

government of laws. 140 Judge Bork presents the problem in a slightly<br />

different way:<br />

The central problem for constitutional courts is the resolution of<br />

the "Madisonian Dilemma." The United States was founded as a<br />

Madisonian system, which means that it contains two opposing<br />

principles that must be continually reconciled. The first principle is<br />

self-government, which means that in wide areas of life majorities are<br />

entitled to rule, if they wish, simply because they are majorities. The<br />

second is that there are nonetheless some things majorities must not<br />

do to minorities, some areas of life in which the individual must be<br />

free of majority rule. The dilemma is that neither majorities nor<br />

minorities can be trusted to define the proper spheres of democratic<br />

authority and individual liberty. To place that power in one or the<br />

other would risk either tyranny by the majority or tyranny by the<br />

minority.' 4 '<br />

the Court strikes down a law as void against the Constitution, it is simply finding in favor<br />

of the supermajority that approves of the Constitution.<br />

137 Id. at 16.<br />

138 Id.<br />

139 Overturning a decision by the Supreme Court requires either an Amendment to<br />

the Constitution or a changing of the guard on the Bench, neither of which happens easily<br />

or often.<br />

140 The great constitutional scholar James Bradley Thayer puts it thus:<br />

It should be remembered that the exercise of [the power ofjudicial review],<br />

even when unavoidable, is always attended with a serious evil, namely that<br />

the correction of legislative mistakes comes from the outside, and the<br />

people lose the political experience, and the moral education and stimulus<br />

that comes from fighting the question out in the ordinary way, and<br />

correcting their own errors. The tendency of a common and easy resort to<br />

this great function.., is to dwarf the political capacity of the people, and to<br />

deaden its sense of moral responsibility.<br />

THAYER, JOHN MARSHALL 106-07 (1920).<br />

141 ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE<br />

LAW 139 (1990).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 165 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

Bork's analysis leaves something to be desired, 142 but the major<br />

point survives: how do we adhere to rule by the People while<br />

maintaining the supremacy of the law of the Constitution? Maintaining<br />

constitutional supremacy is, after all, the chief purpose of judicial<br />

review; the government must be kept within its constituted bounds to<br />

insure that the system works properly and that the people's rights are<br />

protected.<br />

This dilemma/difficulty is chiefly solved through structural judicial<br />

activism. 143 This type of activism promotes majorities, judicial selfrestraint,<br />

and fidelity to the Constitution. The way that structural<br />

activism promotes majorities is simply through the design of the system.<br />

In federalism cases, such a judiciary chooses which majority should<br />

govern as between national majorities and state majorities .... In<br />

separation of powers cases, the federal judiciary chooses which<br />

majority should govern as between the national majority which elects<br />

the President every four years through the medium of the Electoral<br />

College and the very different national majority which selects the<br />

Congress over a six year cycle in races that go on district by district<br />

and state by state. 144<br />

In essence, where structural cases are concerned, the countermajoritarian<br />

difficulty is mitigated, if not completely resolved, because<br />

the judiciary is not choosing between a majority and a minority per se. It<br />

is choosing between two different types of majorities within our system.<br />

Both state majorities and national majorities exist in our federalist<br />

system; likewise, congressional majorities and presidential majorities<br />

exist in our separation of powers scheme. 145 Choosing one or the other is<br />

not an intolerable subversion of our system; it is precisely the way the<br />

system was intended to work, provided the Court's decision is based<br />

upon fidelity to the Constitution. Thus, structural activism singularly<br />

limits problems arising from the counter-majoritarian difficulty.<br />

Structural activism also promotes judicial self-restraint. <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

restraint means that to avoid "usurping the policymaking role of the<br />

democratically elected bodies and officials, a judge should always be<br />

142 Bork overemphasizes both the influence of Madison in creating the system and<br />

the amount of tension that actually exists in our system. Moreover, the reason we do not<br />

allow majorities to decide everything is not simply because of a fear of tyranny of the<br />

minority or majority. It is also because the nature of humanity is such that the people may<br />

not always be vigilant in protecting their freedoms. Thus, some structures are necessary to<br />

supplement the people's vigilance; this protection is part of the system as well. For a telling<br />

but not wholly accurate critique of Bork, see Jaffa, supra note 2, at 291.<br />

143 It will never fully be solved: that is the nature of the imperfect institutions we<br />

must live with; see supra note 113 and surrounding text.<br />

144 Calabresi, supra note 21, at 1383.<br />

145 This explains why we end up with "split tickets" many times at the national<br />

level, with Congress being held by one political party, and the other party holding the<br />

Presidency.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 166 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

hesitant to declare statues or governmental actions unconstitutional." 146<br />

Restraint is a beneficial trait in our judicial system because it "preserves<br />

fundamental constitutional precepts. It encourages the separation of<br />

powers, protects our democratic processes, and preserves our<br />

fundamental rights." 147 It does these things by keeping judicial hands out<br />

of the "cookie jar" of policymaking. Courts are ill-equipped to make policy<br />

for several reasons, ranging from a lack of necessary information to an<br />

inability to change its decisions in a timely fashion. 148 More pointedly,<br />

the Founders already argued about whether the Supreme Court should<br />

have a role in policymaking. At the Convention, some proposed a<br />

"Council of Revision" for legislative purposes, which would have<br />

consisted of the President, some of his Cabinet, and the Supreme Court,<br />

reviewing congressional legislation on policy grounds. The idea was<br />

rejected soundly. 149 The system kept policymaking out of the courts'<br />

hands. Given these things, the courts need to practice judicial restraint<br />

much of the time - the system assumes as much through the separation<br />

of powers, as the statements of Hamilton and others indicate. 150<br />

Self-restraint is the only real check on the judiciary, given its<br />

independent nature. 151 As the twelfth Chief Justice of the Supreme<br />

Court, Harlan Fiske Stone said, "While the unconstitutional exercise of<br />

power by the executive and legislative branches of the government is<br />

subject to judicial restraint, 152 the only check upon our own exercise of<br />

power is our own sense of self-restraint." 153 Since this is the case, and<br />

given the precarious role judicial review holds in our system, it makes<br />

sense that an active judiciary should have a proper place only on rare<br />

occasions. When the Court acts on structural bases, it is practicing<br />

restraint in the sense that it is not imputing its own preferences over<br />

those of the People; rather it is placing constitutional constraints over<br />

the preferences of the particular majoritarian institution that committed<br />

the voided act.<br />

146 Wallace, supra note 127, at 8.<br />

147 Id. at 16.<br />

148 Id. at 6. These are some of the very reasons that Congress is responsible for<br />

policymaking in the first place. See also, Edwin Meese III, Putting the Federal Judiciary<br />

Back on the Constitutional Track, 14 GA. ST. U. L. REV. 781, 784 (1998).<br />

149 MCDONALD, supra note 82, at 242.<br />

150 Wallace, supra note 127, at 8 ("The constitutional trade-off for independence is<br />

that judges must restrain themselves from the areas reserved to the otherf separate<br />

branches.").<br />

151 Senator Charles E. Grassley, Foreword to EATON, supra note 9, at xiv. It is true<br />

that judges can be impeached, but this occurs so little as to be almost no check at all. There<br />

are also the structural checks of the "case and controversy" and standing requirements, but<br />

history has shown that these can be easily manipulated by judges with little self-restraint.<br />

152 And electoral restraint.<br />

153 United States v. Butler, 297 U.S. 1, 78-79 (1936) (Stone, J., dissenting).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 167 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

This is not a conventional way of looking at restraint versus<br />

activism. Judge Justice' 54 provides the traditional view of the legal<br />

establishment: "Proponents of judicial self-restraint can also be defined<br />

in contrast to those jurists and scholars who view the court as the<br />

legitimate counter-majoritarian force in our democracy." 15 Judge<br />

Justice's view is precisely the kind of categorization I wish to refute.<br />

Believing that judicial review (of a certain kind) and self-restraint are at<br />

odds is an incorrect juxtaposition. A judge who believes in structural<br />

judicial activism still follows the standards of proper statutory<br />

interpretation. The structural activist "respects the process of democratic<br />

decisionmaking embodied in legislative enactments," 156 takes care not to<br />

embroil himself "unnecessarily in the turbulent waters of political<br />

controversy," 157 and practices what Charles Lamb calls the "maxims of<br />

restraint." 158 The structural activist does these things because, above all,<br />

the judge respects the principles upon which the Constitution is founded<br />

and the People for whom he adjudicates. For structural activists, several<br />

laws that they consider unwise or downright stupid will nonetheless be<br />

upheld as constitutional. 5 9 "We begin, of course, with the presumption<br />

that the challenged statute is valid. Its wisdom is not the concern of the<br />

courts; if a challenged action does not violate the Constitution, it must be<br />

sustained." 160 The concern is not the substantive wisdom of the<br />

legislation, but the structural impact of its provisions.<br />

Ultimately, the main concern of judicial activism should be fidelity<br />

to the Constitution, because judicial review is a legal tool so fraught with<br />

dangers in our tradition that it ought to be used in only the most<br />

justifiable, least dangerous way. "The process is justified only if it is as<br />

deliberate and conscious as men can make it."161 Structural activism is<br />

preferable because it comports best with the text and history of the<br />

Constitution. It is the least dangerous because it simply rules in favor of<br />

one majority over another, thus lessening the criticism of judicial<br />

review's counter-majoritarian nature. More importantly, structural<br />

activism finds its decisions in the foundation of the Constitution, rather<br />

154 See supra notes 16 and 17 and accompanying text.<br />

155 William Wayne Justice, The New Awakening: <strong>Judicial</strong> Activism in a Conservative<br />

Age, 43 Sw. L.J. 657, 671 (1989).<br />

156 Anderson, supra note 3, at 1561.<br />

157 ARCHIBALD Cox, THE ROLE OF THE SUPREME COURT IN AMERICAN GOVERNMENT<br />

28(1976).<br />

158 Anderson, supra note 3, at 1560.<br />

159 Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186, 270 (1962) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting) ("[Tihere is<br />

not under our Constitution a judicial remedy for every political mischief, for every<br />

undesirable exercise of legislative power. The Framers carefully and with deliberate<br />

forethought refused to so enthrone the judiciary.").<br />

160 INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 944 (1983).<br />

161 BICKEL, supra note 137, at 96.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 168 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

than the ideas of the judge. With the practice of improper judicial<br />

activism, the Constitution becomes "an authoritative occasion for, rather<br />

than a norm of, judicial interpretation." 162 Proper judicial activism aims<br />

for the latter course. It recognizes that "the Constitution is form; an<br />

appeal to 'function' is a claim that something else would be better than<br />

the Constitution, which may be true but nevertheless isn't an admissible<br />

argument about interpretation of the structure we have." 163 This<br />

formalism makes structural activism more conducive to drawing bright<br />

lines.<br />

There are three general arguments for judicial activism: (a)<br />

personal preferences; (b) natural or higher law; and (c) the nature of the<br />

regime (also known as the argument from democracy or republic). As we<br />

have seen, some judges, such as William Justice or Skelly Wright believe<br />

in the first justification, one that this article rejects as improper judicial<br />

activism. The second finds its grounding in "a belief in natural law," a<br />

sense judges have been appealing to ever since Calder v. Bull. 1 6 The<br />

third argument rests its force on the Constitution itself, on the concept<br />

that "American democracy is not simply majority rule; rather, it is a<br />

constitutional democracy. The majority rules within the bounds of the<br />

Constitution, and the limits of the Constitution only have meaning if<br />

there is somebody there to enforce those limits." 165 The difficulty among<br />

these arguments arises when attempting to tell the difference between<br />

when a judge is relying on personal preferences, which is not justified,<br />

and when he is relying on natural or higher law, which is more justified.<br />

The line is so precarious as to be almost indiscernible. 166 Given this<br />

tendency of judicial review, the only safe course is the one that is clearly<br />

the most justified: the argument from structure. Since judicial review<br />

carries with it this inherent problem, it makes sense to concentrate on<br />

the cases that present the proper role of the judiciary as jurisdictional<br />

policemen.<br />

The sense of structural judicial activism rests, as I have said, on the<br />

precarious nature of judicial review as a legal device. Thus, the power of<br />

the Court is premised on the legitimacy of judicial review. "Lacking<br />

power of the purse or the sword, the Court must rely upon the power of<br />

legitimacy - upon the capacity to evoke uncoerced assent and strong<br />

162 Russell Hittinger, A Crisis of Legitimacy, in THE END OF DEMOCRACY? THE<br />

JUDICIAL USURPATION OF POLITICS 18 (1997).<br />

163 Easterbrook, supra note 23, at 15.<br />

164 Calder v. Bull, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 386 (1798).<br />

165 Chemerinsky, supra note 8, at 30.<br />

166 Justice Iredell observed in Calder, "The ideas of natural justice are regulated by<br />

no fixed standard: the ablest and the purest men have differed upon the subject..." Calder<br />

v. Bull, 3 U.S. at 399.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 169 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

public support." 167 Such is the reason that appeals to natural law have<br />

been so prevalent by the Court over the years: it speaks to the hearts of<br />

the public. The sense of public support is bred by the belief that the<br />

Court's decisions are made based upon the law, something about which<br />

the judges presumably have special insight, as opposed to being based on<br />

simple policy preferences, on which judges possess no more expertise<br />

than the proverbial man on the street.<br />

In order to acquiesce in court decisions, and to comply with their<br />

requirements, the people must believe that the court system, and the<br />

Supreme Court especially, is governed by a rule of law, not a rule of<br />

men. We must believe that the judicial system insulates us from the<br />

whims of individual judges, from the prejudices, and from their areas<br />

of ignorance. 1 68<br />

Here the rule of law blends with the separation of powers. Courts<br />

are designed to be insulated from politics to a great degree because their<br />

decisions should be concretely grounded in the law. The other branches<br />

handle the politics; the judiciary interprets the law. l69 If it were<br />

otherwise, the warning by President Lincoln in his First Inaugural<br />

Address could come to fruition:<br />

[T]he candid citizen must confess that if the policy of the Government<br />

upon vital questions affecting the whole people is to be irrevocably<br />

fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court . . .the people will have<br />

ceased to be their own rulers, having to that extent practically<br />

resigned their government into the hands of that eminent tribunal. 1 70<br />

The People must respect judicial decisions to obey them. That<br />

respect and legitimacy come most readily when decisions are grounded<br />

in the founding document of our Government: the Constitution. Such is<br />

why nearly every opinion written in Supreme Court history dealing with<br />

a constitutional issue pays at least face-value homage to the<br />

Constitution, with each justice claiming that his or her opinion comports<br />

best with the sense of the document. "The Court is most vulnerable and<br />

comes nearest to illegitimacy when it deals with judge-made<br />

constitutional law having little or no cognizable roots in the language or<br />

design of the Constitution." 7 ' To preserve its power and legitimacy, the<br />

Court ought to focus mainly on structure, where judicial activism is<br />

167 Cox, supra note 15, at 122. See also Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186, 267 (1962)<br />

(Frankfurter, J., dissenting) ("The Court's authority-possessed of neither the purse nor<br />

the sword-ultimately rests on sustained public confidence in its moral sanction.").<br />

168 EATON, supra note 9, at 7.<br />

169 This is not, of course, to say that legal decisions have no political ramifications;<br />

they clearly do. It simply means that so far as possible, the politics of the situation should<br />

be separated from the legal question before the court.<br />

170 Abraham Lincoln, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4 1861), in INAUGURAL<br />

ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES: FROM GEORGE WASHINGTON 1789<br />

TO GEORGE BUSH 1989 at 133 (U.S. G.P.O. 1989).<br />

171 Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 194 (1986).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 170 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

concerned. The Court gains its power of judicial review from the design<br />

of the Constitution and as such should not practice that tool of last resort<br />

outside of its confines. The system's preferences for majorities, the<br />

separation of powers, judicial restraint, and the rule of law all point to<br />

practicing activism in one main way: as a jurisdictional policeman<br />

patrolling the structural boundaries of the Constitution.<br />

IV. THE CRITICS RESPOND AND ARE REJOINED<br />

Alternatives to the approach advocated in this paper vary in degree<br />

of difference and span the ideological spectrum. Perhaps the starkest<br />

contrast comes from the "political safeguards" theory of federalism. First<br />

argued by Professor Herbert Wechsler 172 in the 1950s and given its<br />

strongest voice by Professor Jesse Choper 173 in the 1980s, it argues that<br />

"the states do not need judicial protection from expansive federal<br />

legislation, because their role in the makeup and the operation of the<br />

national government provides them with sufficient means to protect<br />

their rights." 1 74 Wechsler and Choper's main reason for making this<br />

argument is that they believe the Court should "conserve judicial<br />

legitimacy for what really counts: the protection of individual rights."l?5<br />

Choper in particular argues that the Court possesses only limited<br />

authoritative capital, and that capital ought to be spent adjudicating<br />

individual rights cases. The position assumes that states are adequately<br />

represented in the national political process, so "any exercise of power by<br />

the federal government at the expense of the states therefore was ipso<br />

facto constitutional because the states . . . had given their political<br />

assent."1 76 The theory found its Supreme Court voice in Garcia v. San<br />

Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority. 77 Additionally, although its<br />

main focus is federalism, the "political safeguards" theory includes also<br />

the "separation proposal," which holds that all questions involving<br />

allocations of power between Congress and the President ought to be<br />

172 Herbert Wechsler, The Political Safeguards of Federalism: The Role of the States<br />

in the Composition and Selection of the National Government, 54 COLUM. L. REV. 543<br />

(1954).<br />

173 JESSE CHOPER, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE NATIONAL POLITICAL PROCESS: A<br />

FUNCTIONAL RECONSIDERATION OF THE ROLE OF THE SUPREME COURT (1980).<br />

174 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1312. Along essentially the same lines is Professor Herbert<br />

Hovenkamp's recent assertion that "history has made abundantly clear that the political<br />

process is quite effective at reducing federal assertions of power in favor of state<br />

prerogatives." Herbert Hovenkamp, <strong>Judicial</strong> Restraint and Constitutional Federalism: The<br />

Supreme Court's Lopez and Seminole Tribe Decisions, 96 COLUM. L. REV. 2213, 2221<br />

(1996).<br />

175 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1319.<br />

176 Id. at 1325.<br />

177 Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 U.S. 528 (1985), overruled in<br />

part by United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 171 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

non-justiciable "because of the political branches' abilities to use other<br />

tools at their disposal to resolve their differences." 178<br />

In essence, Choper's theory represents an approximately opposite<br />

view to the one presented here. Choper believes individual rights cases<br />

to be the most important on the Court's docket and thus they should<br />

receive its full attention. Federalism and separation of powers issues<br />

basically take care of themselves and so do not necessitate the Court's<br />

intervention. This theory seems reasonable, but it abounds with<br />

problems. Even assuming arguendo that political safeguards were<br />

adequate protection for the states when Weschler first proposed his<br />

theory, the situation has altered dramatically since then. Cloture is now<br />

available in the Senate by a three-fifths vote on most matters, rather<br />

than two-thirds. Rural districts are no longer "over-represented" in the<br />

House of Representatives because of the one person, one vote rule.<br />

Redistricting now is done just as much by the courts as it is by the state<br />

legislatures. Television has nationalized Senate elections. Federal grants<br />

for highways and other programs are used by Congress as carrots to pass<br />

national laws on drinking, seat belts, speeding, and so forth. 79 Even<br />

reaching back before the 1950s the state/federal equation had swung<br />

decisively over to the federal side. The state legislatures no longer select<br />

Senate members; instead, the people elect them by popular vote,<br />

eliminating what the Founders' believed to be the most important<br />

representative protection of the states in the federal government. 180 The<br />

New Deal nationalized farm relief, retirement, and poverty programs.' 8 '<br />

All of these factors add up to the conclusion that "[bloth analytically and<br />

impressionistically, the Wechsler-Choper view seems at least a little odd<br />

in the political world of today - an historical anomaly that no longer<br />

quite seems to fit."182<br />

Looking past the national level to the states, the Choper theory fails<br />

to account for the possibility that state officials have several incentives<br />

to welcome federal intervention rather than protect state interests.<br />

Justice O'Connor makes this point in New York'8 3 when discussing<br />

locations for radioactive waste disposal centers:<br />

If a state official is faced with the same set of alternativeschoosing<br />

a location or having Congress direct the choice of a locationthe<br />

state official may prefer the latter, as it may permit the avoidance<br />

of personal responsibility. The interests of public officials thus may not<br />

178 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1318-19.<br />

179 Calabresi, supra note 5, at 792-93.<br />

18o THE FEDERALIST No. 45 (James Madison), reprinted in 2 DEBATES, supra note 26,<br />

at 103.<br />

181 Yoo, supra note 46, at 1321.<br />

182 Calabresi, supra note 5, at 793.<br />

183 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144 (1992).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 172 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

coincide with the Constitution's intergovernmental allocation of<br />

authority. Where state officials purport to submit to the direction of<br />

Congress in this manner, federalism is hardly being advanced.l1 4<br />

Richard Neely observes that the "states are more interested in<br />

spending federal bucks than they are in preserving state sovereignty. To<br />

my knowledge no state (except, possibly, Arizona in one instance) has<br />

turned down federal money to stand on federalist principle!"1 8 5 Neely<br />

believes this to be a positive turn of events; regardless, it demonstrates<br />

that political safeguards are inadequate to protect the structure of<br />

federalism.<br />

More important than the fact that the Weschler-Choper theory fails<br />

on functional grounds, is that it fails on formal constitutional grounds.<br />

Choper's approach is unable even to detect "whether or not separation of<br />

powers has been maintained because it makes no attempt to define or<br />

examine it. He solves the problem of interbranch disputes by simply<br />

assuming they do not require resolution (at least not by the judiciary)."186<br />

The same criticism applies to his federalism proposal. In essence, Choper<br />

ignores the structures of the Constitution because he assumes that,<br />

functionally, things will work out to their most efficient end.<br />

Worse, and even more dangerous, is Choper's separation of<br />

individual rights from the Constitution's structure. As this article has<br />

discussed, the whole point of the structures of the Constitution is the<br />

protection of the People's liberty against tyranny. Choper's position is "a<br />

highly anachronistic view because the Bill of Rights did not appear in<br />

the Constitution when Article III first vested in the judiciary the power<br />

to adjudicate cases arising under the Constitution." 187 Finally, Choper's<br />

theory is premised on the belief that the Court can pick and choose the<br />

constitutional provisions it wants to enforce. "Nothing in the nature of<br />

the judiciary's role authorizes it effectively to repeal provisions of the<br />

Constitution." 88 In fact, the independence of the judiciary makes it<br />

especially suited to handle disputes between different levels and<br />

different branches of government. Few reasons exist to ignore completely<br />

either the structure of the Constitution or the provisions in the Bill of<br />

Rights.189<br />

184 Id. at 183.<br />

185 Neely, supra note 94, at 90.<br />

186 Redish & Cisar, supra note 29, at 493.<br />

187 Id.<br />

188 Id.<br />

189 1 have not and am not saying that substantive violations of the Constitution<br />

should not be invalidated by the Supreme Court. Thus, a statute preventing anarchists<br />

from espousing their views could and should be struck down as an obvious violation of the<br />

First Amendment. What I am saying is that these decisions by the Court should only be<br />

made in the rare cases of clear mistake or the other established rules of statutory<br />

construction. On structural issues, the Court ought to be less reticent.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 173 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

Richard Neely takes a different functional approach toward<br />

essentially the same end as Choper. He asks, "[I]f the states themselves<br />

aren't interested in [the] principle [of federalism], why should we be?" 90<br />

He contends that federalism is now simply a matter of administrative<br />

convenience, and where it interferes with governmental efficiency, its<br />

principles ought to be set aside. 191 Professor Douglas Laycock goes one<br />

step further and contends that "[Ilederalism no longer divides power in<br />

any meaningful way. Instead, federalism duplicates and multiplies<br />

power.1 92<br />

This view ignores some vital points. In the first place, according to<br />

Justice O'Connor's opinion in New York, the fact that state officials may<br />

not care about their sovereignty does not mean that the Court or the<br />

country should not care about it. Moreover, concentrating on what<br />

federalism does for the states, just as concentrating on what the<br />

separation of powers does for each of the branches, misses the larger<br />

point. "ITihe Constitution divides authority between federal and state<br />

governments for the protection of individuals. State sovereignty is not<br />

just an end in itself." 193 So, whether the states are interested in<br />

protecting themselves or not, individual freedoms still deserve to be<br />

protected by government structure. Perhaps delegated power has become<br />

more "a matter of administrative convenience than an element of<br />

sovereignty." 194 However, either the principle of delegation stands, or the<br />

Constitution falls; there is no other way around it. It defeats the whole<br />

purpose of a written Constitution to assign meaning solely on the basis<br />

of convenience or efficiency.<br />

Efficiency is emphatically not central to our Constitution; ordered<br />

liberty is the main point. "The Constitution's structure requires a<br />

stability which transcends the convenience of the moment." 195 Efficiency<br />

is not the acid test for constitutionality. "[Tihe fact that a given law or<br />

procedure is efficient, convenient, and useful in facilitating functions of<br />

government, standing alone, will not save it if it is contrary to the<br />

Constitution. Convenience and efficiency are not the primary objectives -<br />

or the hallmarks - of democratic government." 19 6 The famous saying that<br />

"at least Mussolini made the trains run on time" was not intended as a<br />

compliment: a government can be an efficient tyrant. "The choices we<br />

discern as having been made in the Constitutional Convention impose<br />

190 Neely, supra note 94, at 90.<br />

191 Id.<br />

192 Douglas Laycock, Federalism as a Structural Threat to Liberty, 22 HARv. J.L. &<br />

PUB. POL'Y 67, 80-81 (1998).<br />

193 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 189 (1992).<br />

194 Neely, supra note 94, at 90.<br />

195 Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. at 448 (Kennedy, J., concurring).<br />

196 INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 944 (1983).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 174 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

burdens on governmental processes that often seem clumsy, inefficient,<br />

even unworkable, but those hard choices were consciously made by men<br />

who had lived under a form of government that permitted arbitrary<br />

governmental acts to go unchecked." 197 If it is efficiency we want, we<br />

ought to forego the right to vote altogether: the information,<br />

campaigning, and time involved make for highly inefficient government.<br />

"With all the obvious flaws of delay, untidiness, and potential for abuse,<br />

we have not yet found a better way to preserve freedom than by making<br />

the exercise of power subject to the carefully crafted restraints spelled<br />

out in the Constitution."198 Those restraints include a Court that patrols<br />

the boundaries of delegated government power.<br />

Proponents of Choper's theory argue that defining sharp lines<br />

between executive and legislative functions or between national and<br />

local functions is too difficult for the courts. 199 This argument fails,<br />

however, because determining which fundamental rights are "implicit in<br />

the concept of ordered liberty," 200 or which rights comport with the<br />

"mystery of human life" 201 is not an easy task either. Even speaking more<br />

generically, "the line-drawing and fact-finding problems here are no<br />

more difficult than they are in the context of determining what<br />

constitutes an impermissible endorsement of religion or when . . .<br />

unprotected obscenity becomes protected pornography." 202 Professor<br />

Choper admitted as much: "A great many of the personal liberties<br />

questions that the Court decides . . . similarly subsume large policy<br />

issues with complex and debatable factual considerations." 203 To admit<br />

this in structural areas of constitutional adjudication is simply to<br />

acknowledge that several issues are not cut and dried; if they were, we<br />

would not need a court system at all. The Court should not shy away<br />

from an issue because it is difficult; rather, it should shy away if the<br />

Constitution offers no guidance. Federalism and separation of powers<br />

issues, however, are clearly within the import of the Constitution. A<br />

supporter of structural activism need not prove that all delegation of<br />

power questions will be decided correctly. What he must do is attempt to<br />

remain dedicated to the first principles of the Constitution.<br />

197 Id. at 959.<br />

198 Id.; see also Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 654 (1952).<br />

199 Hovenkamp, supra note 174, at 2220.<br />

200 Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325 (1937).<br />

201 Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992) (For the record, the<br />

actual quote is: "At the heart of liberty is the right to define one's own concept of existence,<br />

of meaning, of the universe, and the mystery of human life.") Id. Structural cases simply<br />

are not conducive to such open language.<br />

202 Calabresi, supra note 5, at 804.<br />

203 CHOPER, supra note 173, at 203.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 175 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

Dedicated pursuit of an ideal is a legitimating reality, even though the<br />

reach exceeds the grasp, provided that the people know that the effort<br />

is undertaken. And the value of the ideal is not diminished by<br />

acknowledging that its conscientious pursuit serves the utilitarian<br />

function of giving legitimacy to constitutional decisions. 20 4<br />

Criticism of the viewpoint espoused in this article could conceivably<br />

also come from the right side of the political spectrum, because of its<br />

traditionally staunch support of judicial restraint, as we have seen with<br />

President Reagan, Judge Bork, and Professor Graglia. Perhaps the<br />

strongest criticism of judicial activism came in a 1996 symposium<br />

entitled: "The End of Democracy? The <strong>Judicial</strong> Usurpation of Politics," 20 5<br />

by First Things, a conservative religious journal. It is an appeal that<br />

serves as a valuable wake-up call concerning the dangers inherent in<br />

judicial review. However, it goes overboard in establishing its case. For<br />

instance, the editors of First Things write that the "government of the<br />

United States of America no longer governs by the consent of the<br />

governed. With respect to the American people, the judiciary has in<br />

effect declared that the most important questions about how we ought to<br />

order our life together are outside the purview of 'things of their<br />

knowledge. ' "' 2 6 This article does not contend for a moment that<br />

substantive judicial activism has been good for this country. 2 7 But to say<br />

that the People no longer govern on any issues of importance borders on<br />

hyperbole. "The courts have not, and perhaps cannot, restrain<br />

themselves, and it may be that in the present regime no other effective<br />

restraints are available. If so, we are witnessing the end of<br />

democracy." 208<br />

Problems abound with that statement. In the first place, as this<br />

article reiterates, we do not have a democracy; we have a system of<br />

constitutionalism: the People rule within bounds designed to inhibit<br />

their darker passions. Secondly, the restraints on the courts are<br />

available and exist within the system. To declare the system a dismal<br />

failure after over two hundred years simply because the Supreme Court<br />

has taken on the role of "knight errant" 20 9 on some occasions throws the<br />

204 Cox, supra note 15, at 138.<br />

205 Robert H. Bork et. al, Symposium, The End of Democracy? The <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Usurpation of Politics, FIRST THINGS 18, Nov. 1996, reprinted in THE END OF DEMOCRACY?<br />

THE JUDICIAL USURPATION OF POLITICS (1997).<br />

206 Id. at 5.<br />

207 Professor Graglia puts it rather humorously when he asks, "[Wihat part of the<br />

Constitution do you think Justice Harry Blackmun was interpreting in Roe v. Wade, when<br />

he held that state restrictions on abortion violate the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth<br />

Amendment-was it the word 'due' or the word 'process?'" Graglia, supra note 14, at 297.<br />

208 Bork, Our <strong>Judicial</strong> Oligarchy, supra note 205, at 6.<br />

209 United Steelworkers of America, AFL-CIO-CLC v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 218<br />

(1979) (quoting Justice Cardozo).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 176 2001-2002


2001]<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

baby out with the bath water. The contributors to the First Things<br />

debate decry the evils of judicial activism, but they enthusiastically<br />

support the idea of natural law.210 As we saw in Part III, as well as in<br />

Part I while defining judicial activism, natural law is open to the same<br />

abuses that judicial activism engenders. In fact, several of the decisions<br />

about which First Things complains, such as Roe, ground their opinions<br />

in a kind of natural law jurisprudence. The point here is not that the<br />

editors of First Things must either support Roe v. Wade or renounce<br />

natural law - clearly their version of natural law can be different from<br />

the Court's in Roe; the point is to understand that judging inherently<br />

involves the kinds of problems that the editors declare represent the<br />

"end of democracy." The solution to those problems is not to declare the<br />

system broken, but to demand adherence to true fidelity to that system<br />

(i.e., the Constitution). And it is perfectly within the power of the People<br />

to demand this, because, as we have learned, the power of the Supreme<br />

Court is wholly dependent on its legitimacy. 21 '<br />

Obviously, several other theories of constitutional jurisprudence<br />

exist that have not been addressed. Only those that speak most directly<br />

to the position being advocated in this article have been rejoined.<br />

Structural activism is but one piece of the constitutional fabric, but it is<br />

a very important piece. It is time for advocates of both jurisprudential<br />

activism and judicial restraint to consider its validity.<br />

Having preached the virtues of judicial restraint for several<br />

generations, conservatives will have to reevaluate their position. As<br />

they did in the late 1930's, liberals and conservatives in the late 1990's<br />

will debate about whether the courts or the political process are better<br />

equipped to police the boundaries of federalism and the separation of<br />

powers. 212<br />

210 Bork, Our <strong>Judicial</strong> Oligarchy, supra note 205, at 6 ("Among the most elementary<br />

principles of Western Civilization is the truth that laws which violate the moral law are<br />

null and void and must in conscience be disobeyed.").<br />

211 Robert A. Dahl, Decision-Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a<br />

National Policy-Maker, 6 J. PUB. L. 279, 285 (1957).<br />

The fact is ... that the policy views dominant on the Court are never for<br />

long out of line with the policy views dominant among the lawmaking<br />

majorities of the United States. Consequently it would be most unrealistic<br />

to suppose that the Court would, for more than a few years at most, stand<br />

against any major alternatives sought by a lawmaking majority.<br />

Id.<br />

Of course, sadly this is part of the problem to begin with-that the<br />

Court follows policy preferences at all, when it ought to be following the<br />

Constitution. But the point here is that the Court can only get away with what<br />

we let it get away with, given a certain amount of time.<br />

212 Jeffrey Rosen, Nine Votes for <strong>Judicial</strong> Restraint, N.Y. TIMES, June 29, 1997, at<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 177 2001-2002


REGENT UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

[Vol. 14:141<br />

V. CONCLUSION<br />

In evaluating the role of the federal judiciary in our system and,<br />

more specifically, the proper place for judicial activism in the courts, it<br />

must be remembered that, with the passage of the Constitution, the<br />

Founders implemented a novus ordo seclorum: a new order for the<br />

ages. 21 3 The Founders turned the political ideas of the world on their<br />

head. Virtually everyone believed that sovereignty must reside in only<br />

one governmental body, but the Founders divided it between the Federal<br />

and State levels. Most said that the separation of powers required that<br />

the branches of government must be completely separate, but the<br />

Founders split them while providing checks and balances. Conventional<br />

wisdom held that the legislature had to have the final say in what the<br />

laws would be, but the Founders made the People the final arbiters of<br />

the law, through the Constitution. This was not a republic in any of the<br />

ordinary senses of the term. 21 4 <strong>Judicial</strong> review was part of this new<br />

order, because of the Founder's emphasis on a written Constitution. So,<br />

if it seems that judicial review is a unique tool, it is because it truly is,<br />

and like any of our tools, in the hands of corrupt man it can be misused.<br />

The Founders knew these things, and knew that if this new order was to<br />

succeed, it would require the ongoing vigilance of the government by the<br />

governed. This is why "[w]hen Americans stop arguing about legitimacy,<br />

about just government derived from the consent of the governed, and<br />

about the relationship between laws and higher law, this country will<br />

have turned out to be something very different from what the Founders<br />

intended. 215<br />

"Limiting the federal judiciary, including the Supreme Court, to its<br />

proper Constitutional role thus is a vital liberty issue." 216 This article has<br />

sought to describe some of that proper role, where it concerns the<br />

dangerous but necessary duty of judicial activism. The premise has been<br />

that the structure of the Constitution deserves and demands the main<br />

focus of the Supreme Court, because its fundamental role in our system<br />

213 MCDONALD, supra note 82, at 262.<br />

214 Id. at 287.<br />

That government defied categorization by any existing nomenclature: it<br />

was not a monarchy, nor an aristocracy, nor a democracy, neither yet was it<br />

a mixed form of government, nor yet a confederated republic. It was what it<br />

was, and if Madison was presumptuous in appropriating the word republic<br />

to describe it, he was also a prophet, for thenceforth republic would mean<br />

precisely what Madison said it meant.<br />

Id.<br />

215 Richard John Neuhaus, Preface to THE END OF DEMOCRACY, supra note 162, at<br />

ix.<br />

216 Edwin Meese III, A Return to Constitutional Interpretation from <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

Lawmaking, 40 N.Y.L. SCH. L. REV. 925, 932-33 (1996).<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 178 2001-2002


20011<br />

PROPER JUDICIAL ACTIVISM<br />

represents a primary way that judicial review can be legitimate.<br />

Excessive activism, as we have seen, produces grave consequences.<br />

First, there is concern that the Court may sacrifice the power of<br />

legitimacy that attaches to decisions within the traditional judicial<br />

sphere rendered on the basis of conventional legal criteria, and so may<br />

disable itself from performing the narrower but none the less vital<br />

constitutional role that all assign to it. Second, there is fear that<br />

excessive reliance on the courts instead of self-government through<br />

democratic processes may deaden a people's sense of moral and<br />

political responsibility for their own future, especially in matters of<br />

liberty, and may stunt the growth of political capacity that results<br />

from the exercise of the ultimate power of decision. 217<br />

This article does not seek to push judicial activism to the point that<br />

these concerns will come to fruition. Rather, it proposes a partial<br />

antidote to these problems. First, by starting with the founding<br />

principles of this republic: man is fallen; this is a government of laws,<br />

not of men; we have a written constitution; no man is allowed to be the<br />

judge in his own cause; concentration of political power means tyranny;<br />

and the recognition that no dichotomy exists between structure and our<br />

sacred rights, any temptation to place excessive reliance on the courts<br />

instead of self-government is overcome. Second, by recognition of an<br />

adherence to what are the key structures in our system: separation of<br />

powers and federalism. Adherence to these key structures prevents the<br />

courts from whittling away their legitimacy, and focuses their powers on<br />

the narrower, but vital, constitutional role assigned to them.<br />

Proper judicial activism does not threaten the republic; it emboldens<br />

it. When activism leaches into an improper sphere, as it is bound to do, it<br />

remains for us to pull it back, and to remind the judiciary that we are a<br />

government of laws, not of men. While judges may interpret the law,<br />

they are not the law themselves; and when they attempt to equate<br />

themselves to the law, as they do when basing decisions upon their<br />

consciences rather than the Constitution, it is up to us to call them on<br />

the carpet, and point them back to the Text. Respect for the system and<br />

a desire to protect liberty demand no less of us, and proper judicial<br />

activism demands no less a fidelity from judges.<br />

217 COX, supra note 157, at 103.<br />

HeinOnline -- 14 Regent U. L. Rev. 179 2001-2002


Page 112 of 115


Notes<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

Page 113 of 115


Notes<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

______________________________________________________________________________<br />

Page 114 of 115


Page 115 of 115

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!