16.12.2017 Views

Fall 2017 JPI

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

thesis that historical time is imagined.<br />

However, for Anderson, “the possibility of imagining the nation arose historically,” 4 meaning<br />

that in the genealogy of the nation, historical continuity is based on the rupture, independent of<br />

narrative, with a set of historical events. For example, settler colonialism might have imagined its<br />

legitimacy against that of the indigenous peoples, but a material rift in continuity took place as well –<br />

especially in terms land appropriation. In the genealogical method, developed by Nietzsche and later<br />

Foucault, continuity as a barrier of absolute truth is disrupted, in order to debunk essentialist<br />

identities. 5 Despite its tendency to counter historical essentialism, genealogy remains a historicized<br />

concept.<br />

ENDS OF HISTORY<br />

The disruption of imperial centers of power in the 19th century, gave birth to a Europe of<br />

nations that has continued to evolve ever since. Hegel believed that the historical justification of the<br />

nation-state came to being through a replacement of the religious community with an anonymous one,<br />

held together by calendric time invented by print capitalism. In the final chapter of his Phenomenology<br />

of the Spirit, Hegel defines the concept of absolute truth as the full historical consciousness of the<br />

subject, acquired through remembrance 6 .<br />

Hegel's universalism is primarily idealist and mostly focuses on the forging of national freedom;<br />

the historical subject is most of all a dialectical subject and does not subscribe to an anthropological<br />

or moral discourse. The “end of history,” a diachronically debated idea that humanity will attain a<br />

point of original expression in the context of a sustainable global utopia, has a limited application in<br />

Hegel’s thought. For Hegel, such an end is embodied by the state, both as a compound of the nationstate<br />

and as a motor of identity. In retrospect, Hegel's insistence on the state over the nation can be<br />

viewed as a counter to totalitarian notions of ethnically homogenous nations. Although a Europe of<br />

nations was still in the making in Hegel's time, he, as well as Metternich, hinted at a belief in<br />

internationalism or federalism as models of peace. Later writing in the Philosophy of the Right, Hegel<br />

actually saw the future of his ideas as lying in the US, representing the triumph of federalism.<br />

A second interpretation of the “end of history” is that of Alexander Kojeve, whose theories<br />

were mostly developed in the interwar years. The lectures he gave on Hegel in Paris, were attended by<br />

French intellectuals like Jacques Lacan and Maurice Merleau-Ponty and directly influenced others, like<br />

Sartre. His considerable influence on this generation of intellectuals led to a consolidation of his views,<br />

but what is more significant is the effect this consolidation had on yet another generation of French<br />

thinkers, namely, the post-structuralists.<br />

Kojeve interpreted Hegel anthropologically. Whereas in the work of Hegel the historical<br />

subject is an idea that refers to human consciousness, Kojeve placed the historical subject in the human<br />

being, thus presenting Hegel's dialectics as a history of man himself. Consequently, the “end of history”<br />

in Kojeve's thought, is a much more obscurantist and utopian notion that presents itself as the<br />

synthesis that emerged out of political conflict in first-half of 20th century Europe.<br />

Kojeve, who gave up his position as an academic to work for the French state and later helped<br />

4 Anderson, Imagined Communities, 36.<br />

5 Foucault discusses Nietzsche and explains how the genealogical method tackles the “origin” to offer alternative narratives in his lecture Nietzsche, la<br />

généalogie, l’histoire.<br />

6 Hegel, G. W. F., Phénoménologie De L'Esprit (Paris: Flammarion, 2012), 680-690.<br />

<strong>JPI</strong> <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2017</strong>, pg. 37

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!