Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church

Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church

13.12.2012 Views

INTRODUCTION 57 Maximus was breaking new ground. To do this involved thinking through what was meant by the hypostatic union, and indeed what was meant by the term hypostasis. 7 It is tempting to see a progress in one strand of Christian thought about the Incarnation from an idea that barely avoids docetism in which God appears in human form, through Apollinarianism in which the human mind is replaced by the divine mind, to the position of Orthodoxy in which the divine Son assumes a fully human nature. From such a point of view, Maximus represents the final clarification of Orthodoxy. Landmarks on the way would be St Athanasius’ assertion that ‘the Lord came not to show himself, but to heal and teach those who were suffering’, 8 and the principle enunciated by St Gregory of Nazianzus that ‘the unassumed is the unhealed, only that which is united to God is saved’. 9 From seeing Christ as God appearing in human form, theological reflection moved to seeing Christ as the Son of God living a fully human life. The great Ecumenical Councils trace this theological journey, but its starting-point is the conviction that in Christ one encounters God as person and its guiding light the growing realization that this entails that the person of the Incarnate One is the Word, the divine Son, ‘One of the Trinity’. The critical issue is: what is a person? And the heresies that litter this theological path— docetism, Apollinarianism, Eutychianism, Monenergism, Monothelitism—can be seen as the result of premature attempts to resolve this issue. (It should be said, in fairness, that many scholars would see this theological path as leading nowhere, or narrowing down to vanishing-point: but if this path does lead somewhere, then it is Maximus to whom we must attend if we want to understand where.) What is Maximus’ answer to this problem? It is guided, as will now be evident, by his ‘Chalcedoman logic’. Person is contrasted to nature: it is concerned with the way we are (the mode, or tropos), not what we are (principle, or logos). When he became incarnate— when he assumed human nature—the Word became everything that we are. But he did it in his own way, because he is a person, just as we are human in our own way, because we are persons. Maximus sometimes, as we have seen, expresses this distinction of levels by distinguishing between existence (hyparxis) or subsisting (hyphistanai, from which the noun, hypostasis) and being (ousia, or einai): persons exist, nature are. Whatever we share with others, we are: it belongs to our nature. But what it is to be a person is not some thing, some quality, that we do not share with others—as if there were an irreducible somewhat within each one of us that makes us the unique persons we are. What is unique about each one of us is what we have made of the nature that we have: our own unique mode of existence, which is a matter of our experience in the past, our hopes for the future, the way we live

58 THE DOCTRINE OF THE PERSON OF CHRIST out the nature that we have. What makes the Son of God the unique person he is is the eternal life of love in the Trinity in which he shares in a filial way. MAXIMUS’ UNDERSTANDING OF THE WILL There are several problems in the way of understanding Maximus’ conception of willing. The first is quite simply that it seems that his analysis of the human will, though it draws on earlier thought, not least that of Aristotle, is largely original. Maximus is not using an already available notion of the will, but thinking through something that appears to be quite new in the history of human thought (though Maximus was anxious not to appear to be an ‘innovator’). 10 But if, as has been suggested, Maximus virtually creates the notion of the will, 11 understanding him is compounded by the fact that this notion, so central to Maximus’ understanding of what it is to be human, is also something that much modern thought tends to take for granted. For whatever problems there are in understanding Maximus, it is certainly not the case that he has an oversimplified way of understanding human nature, but rather that we have, borne to us by the concepts and values of our Western culture that has shaped us. Maximus’ understanding of human nature is many-layered: more than some other Fathers is he free from the tendency (found in many classical philosophers, too) to oversimplify what it is to be human, and to locate the human in our intellectual, rational capacity. Rather to be human is to be a creature that loves with a love that integrates the several layers of our being, layers some of which we share with the non-rational, and even non-animal creation. In so far as it belongs to the twentieth century (and also some earlier ones) to oversimplify what it is to be human, and locate that in our will, in our (pretended) ability to do what we want, to choose between this and that, such an oversimplification makes Maximus utterly opaque to our understanding. For Maximus, what is distinctive about being human is selfdetermination (autexousios kinêsis: movement that is within one’s own power). Twice Maximus takes his definition of what is involved in selfdetermination from the fifth-century bishop, Diadochus of Photikê: ‘self-determination is the unhindered willing of a rational soul towards whatever it wishes’. 12 This self-determination is not, however, absolute: human beings are created in God’s image, and it is in their self-determination that they reflect God’s image. This selfdetermination is, then, ordered towards God: human beings are creatures whose nature finds its fulfilment in their freely turning towards the God to whom they owe their being. What is meant by

INTRODUCTION 57<br />

Maximus was breaking new ground. To do this involved thinking<br />

through what was meant by the hypostatic union, and indeed what<br />

was meant by the term hypostasis. 7 It is tempting to see a progress in<br />

one strand of <strong>Christian</strong> thought about the Incarnation from an idea<br />

that barely avoids docetism in which God appears in human form,<br />

through Apollinarianism in which the human mind is replaced by the<br />

divine mind, to the position of Orthodoxy in which the divine Son<br />

assumes a fully human nature. From such a point of view, Maximus<br />

represents the final clarification of Orthodoxy. Landmarks on the way<br />

would be St Athanasius’ assertion that ‘the Lord came not to show<br />

himself, but to heal and teach those who were suffering’, 8 and the<br />

principle enunciated by St Gregory of Nazianzus that ‘the unassumed<br />

is the unhealed, only that which is united to God is saved’. 9 From<br />

seeing Christ as God appearing in human form, theological reflection<br />

moved to seeing Christ as the Son of God living a fully human life.<br />

The great Ecumenical Councils trace this theological journey, but its<br />

starting-point is the conviction that in Christ one encounters God as<br />

person and its guiding light the growing realization that this entails<br />

that the person of the Incarnate One is the Word, the divine Son, ‘One<br />

of the Trinity’. The critical issue is: what is a person? And the heresies<br />

that litter this theological path— docetism, Apollinarianism,<br />

Eutychianism, Monenergism, Monothelitism—can be seen as the<br />

result of premature attempts to resolve this issue. (It should be said,<br />

in fairness, that many scholars would see this theological path as<br />

leading nowhere, or narrowing down to vanishing-point: but if this<br />

path does lead somewhere, then it is Maximus to whom we must<br />

attend if we want to understand where.)<br />

What is Maximus’ answer to this problem? It is guided, as will now<br />

be evident, by his ‘Chalcedoman logic’. Person is contrasted to nature:<br />

it is concerned with the way we are (the mode, or tropos), not what we<br />

are (principle, or logos). When he became incarnate— when he<br />

assumed human nature—the Word became everything that we are.<br />

But he did it in his own way, because he is a person, just as we are<br />

human in our own way, because we are persons. Maximus sometimes,<br />

as we have seen, expresses this distinction of levels by distinguishing<br />

between existence (hyparxis) or subsisting (hyphistanai, from which<br />

the noun, hypostasis) and being (ousia, or einai): persons exist, nature<br />

are. Whatever we share with others, we are: it belongs to our nature.<br />

But what it is to be a person is not some thing, some quality, that we<br />

do not share with others—as if there were an irreducible somewhat<br />

within each one of us that makes us the unique persons we are. What<br />

is unique about each one of us is what we have made of the nature<br />

that we have: our own unique mode of existence, which is a matter of<br />

our experience in the past, our hopes for the future, the way we live

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!