13.12.2012 Views

Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church

Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church

Andrew Louth - Syriac Christian Church

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

208 NOTES<br />

Faith 13 (Kotter [1973], 37). This definition of place ultimately derives<br />

from Aristotle, Physics IV.4.<br />

101 Maximus here and elsewhere (e.g. in sections 5 and 40) seems to use the<br />

third person singular imperfect of ‘to be’ (ên) in an absolute way to mean<br />

‘exists eternally’. I do not think this is a Neoplatonic usage— Plotinus<br />

regards eternity (let alone the One) as being beyond past and future<br />

tense, and characterized by an absolute use of the present tense (see<br />

Enneads III.7.3.34–6). It is, perhaps, a <strong>Christian</strong> usage, derived from<br />

John 1:1 (En archêi ên ho logos): Cyril of Alexandria, in his Commentary<br />

on St John’s Gospel, comments that ‘Used of God, the word “was”<br />

introduces the meaning of his absolute eternity, his being older than<br />

any temporal beginning, and removes the thought that he might be<br />

made’ (Book 1, c.7, on John 1:6f.: Pusey [1872], I.91, II. 5–8). It is also<br />

found in the scholia on the Corpus Areopagiticum, ascribed to Maximus<br />

(many of which are, however, by John of Scythopolis): on Divine Names<br />

5.8 (which explains how tenses apply to God), we read: ‘“He was”, and<br />

what is understood to be included in this, agrees with nothing else than<br />

God, because “he was”, considered as anterior to every beginning’ (PG 4.<br />

328A8–11), which is very close to Cyril, but not actually a citation: see<br />

also 316BC where the use of ên is justified specifically in relation to<br />

John 1:1, though it is not explained there what it means.<br />

102 Cf. Denys the Areopagite, Divine Names V.8:824A.<br />

103 From here to the end of the section Maximus engages in a complicated<br />

argument against the possibility of uncreated matter which, he argues,<br />

would possess being from itself, but not form: out of which he constructs<br />

a reductio ad absurdum.<br />

104 See n. 101, above.<br />

105 This way of speaking of an ultimate unity (the monad) and an ultimate<br />

duality (the dyad), according to Maximus derived from the monad, goes<br />

back to Pythagoras, and was current in Neoplatonic circles (influenced,<br />

as they were, by the second-century revival of Pythagoreanism).<br />

106 The text in Migne marks no division here. This is taken from Eriugena’s<br />

version.<br />

107 For this triad (ousia, dynamis, energeia) of Neoplatonic inspiration, see:<br />

lamblichus, On the Mysteries of Egypt II.1; Proclus, Elements of<br />

Theology 169; Denys the Areopagite, Celestial Hierarchy XI.2, Divine<br />

Names IV.1, 23. See also Sherwood (1955a), 103–16.<br />

108 Denys the Areopagite, On the Divine Names, 13.3. I have assimilated<br />

the text given in Migne to the text of the new critical edition: Suchla<br />

(1990), 229.<br />

109 See Denys the Areopagite, On the Divine Names, 4.4 (Suchla [1990], 148,<br />

l.15): ‘as each to its own goal’ is, in fact, an exact citation.<br />

110 The material in this section is mainly drawn from Nemesius, On human<br />

nature 42–4. John Damascene also draws on these chapters from<br />

Nemesius (apparently quite independently of Maximus) in his<br />

discussion of providence in Exposition of the Faith 43.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!