3658925934

01.05.2017 Views

assumption that society consisted of an aggregate of atomistic individuals. Whether it was John Stuart Mill, who went from this assumption to conclude that sociology could develop from the law of association combined with the basic principles of logic, 15 or the contract theorists, who presented society as a collection of formal dyadic relationships, 16 Tarde and Durkheim forcefully opposed these conclusions. In dismissing the contact theorists’ assumption that men could solve their basic needs through elaborating a series of contractual relationships, Tarde and Durkheim both emphasized the necessity of including the normative framework imposed by the broader society for any meaningful social analysis. But they did not go so far as some who chose to view society as a great organic whole. While not necessarily allied with utilitarianism—although it happened to be in the work of Herbert Spencer—the organismic analogy provided another popular basis for elaborating much of what passed for sociological theory in the second half of the nineteenth century. It was largely under the combined attacks of Tarde and Durkheim that the organismic analogy largely disappeared from informed sociological discourse after the turn of the century in France. Thus, in terms of their definition of historical antecedents of sociology, their taxonomy of sociological work, their general logic of analysis, and common opposition to certain competing currents of thought, Tarde and Durkheim overlapped significantly. But after this point, as each man began actually to lay down the essentials of his system of thought, a number of divergencies appeared. 17 Tarde held that a prerequisite for any science was the repetition of some basic measurable phenomenon. The arts were concerned with the examination and portrayal of unique, individual phenomena; science, based on generalization from a large number of cases, could only begin through observing some kind of repetition. As the object of study for sociology is man, but man in a social context, sociology must find its basic focus of inquiry, its fundamental “social fact,” in some aspect of man which is characteristically social. The aspects of man thus open to the sociologist must be distinguished from his physical and biological, as well as his “intra-mental,” or psychological, aspects. What remains are the “inter-mental” aspects of men, or man insofar as he is influenced by other men. The basic process by which this inter-mental influence takes place, and the basic social fact for sociology, Tarde holds, is imitation. Social relations are essentially imitative relationships. But sociology need be concerned with only those aspects of the psyche which are transmitted between minds. Here, the two basic psychic units, the two elementary particles of imitation, are what Tarde isolated in an early essay as “belief” and “desire,” the one cognitive, the other emotive. The final result of imitation for the individual is a “mental imprint,” an impression on the mind similar to the imprint on a photographic plate. Thus, psychology cannot be excluded from sociology as social processes consist, in the final analysis, of inter-mental relations. It was precisely at this point that Tarde and Durkheim found themselves in radical disagreement. Durkheim posited as the essentially social fact not that which was imitated, but that which was exterior to the individual and imposed on him through a sort of constraint. Firmly committed to the position elaborated by his professor, Boutroux, that sciences developed on successive emergent levels, and that the basic principles of a science must be found distinctly on its “own level,” Durkheim refused to accept that sociological principles should be grounded in psychology. Sociology as a distinctive science, he held, must take as its object of study social facts; and these social facts must find their causes as well as their consequences in other distinctly social facts. An apparently logical extension of this reasoning, which Tarde as well as Durkheim occasionally drew, was that the subject matter of sociology, being exterior to each individual, was consequently outside of all members comprising a given social group. But such a conclusion was absurd: take away all

individual members of a group, and the essential sociological characteristics remain. This was, Tarde held, the necessary consequence of Durkheim’s postulates, and it generated nothing more than the “scholastic ontology” of the medieval philosophical realists. In opposition to the doctrine that the whole is more than the sum of its parts, Tarde held that the whole is equal to no more than the sum of its parts; he labeled himself, when forced to do so, a philosophical nominalist. As a rigorous thinker who chose to drive his postluates to their extreme logical conclusions, Durkheim more than once espoused the realistic position that Tarde referred to as his “ontological Phasmagoria.” Insofar as he did so, Durkheim must be judged by subsequent sociologists as being simply wrong, and Tarde as being right. With time, however, whether as a consequence of continued empirical observation 18 or through being convinced by Tarde and others of the logical absurdity of his position, or both, Durkheim moved away from the extreme realism. This was most clearly the case in his empirical studies, 19 however, for Durkheim never explicitly contradicted his earlier pronouncements on this issue. This was unfortunate, for in subsequent years ardent disciples adhered to what had come to be defined as Durkheimian gospel, with near disastrous consequences for the development of both sociology and psychology in France. 20 Tarde, however, went so far in asserting that society was composed of no more than its individual members that he in turn underestimated the importance of certain collective influences. Nevertheless, he presented a more sophisticated view of the relationships between the individual and society than did Durkheim. Much social action, Tarde pointed out, was based not on constraint from the external imposition of social norms, but grew out of spontaneous imitation of beliefs and desires that subsequently became internalized by the individual and, through a process of learning, continued to structure his behavior. Growing largely from the commitment of Tarde to an emphasis on the autonomy of the individual and a grounding of his behavior in Spontaneity, and of Durkheim to the predominance of the collectivity and a Cartesian striving for order, the difference between the two men was reflected in several other issues. In discussing the general bases for social change, Tarde stressed the centrality of the creative individual in suggesting new lines of development which the collectivity would subsequently adopt. Durkheim preferred to emphasize the structural conditions which predisposed a given collectivity to change, minimizing the importance of individual factors. 21 To explain processes of norm formation, Tarde presented an interactionist theory similar in many ways to that associated with the name of George Herbert Mead. Durkheim, on the other hand, relied on such group conditions as heightened collective activity, but he was much less precise in this area than was Tarde (see section vii below). Tarde elaborated a theory of social control that grew out of social interaction, and was extended through larger social groupings with such developments as extensive mass communications (see section ix). Durkheim, to explain social control, focused more on the constraining influences of values and norms. Durkheim maintained at some points that the elementary social unit was the horde, to which Tarde retorted that it was the individual, or at least the household; but both men recognized that this was not a point to be resolved a priori, but through more extended study. 22 For us today, many of these positions appear more complementary than contradictory; but such was not always the case for Tarde and Durkheim. Nevertheless, their debates have helped clarify the vision of subsequent sociologists.

individual members of a group, and the essential sociological characteristics remain. This was, Tarde<br />

held, the necessary consequence of Durkheim’s postulates, and it generated nothing more than the<br />

“scholastic ontology” of the medieval philosophical realists. In opposition to the doctrine that the<br />

whole is more than the sum of its parts, Tarde held that the whole is equal to no more than the sum of<br />

its parts; he labeled himself, when forced to do so, a philosophical nominalist.<br />

As a rigorous thinker who chose to drive his postluates to their extreme logical conclusions,<br />

Durkheim more than once espoused the realistic position that Tarde referred to as his “ontological<br />

Phasmagoria.” Insofar as he did so, Durkheim must be judged by subsequent sociologists as being<br />

simply wrong, and Tarde as being right. With time, however, whether as a consequence of continued<br />

empirical observation 18 or through being convinced by Tarde and others of the logical absurdity of his<br />

position, or both, Durkheim moved away from the extreme realism. This was most clearly the case in<br />

his empirical studies, 19 however, for Durkheim never explicitly contradicted his earlier<br />

pronouncements on this issue. This was unfortunate, for in subsequent years ardent disciples adhered<br />

to what had come to be defined as Durkheimian gospel, with near disastrous consequences for the<br />

development of both sociology and psychology in France. 20<br />

Tarde, however, went so far in asserting that society was composed of no more than its individual<br />

members that he in turn underestimated the importance of certain collective influences. Nevertheless,<br />

he presented a more sophisticated view of the relationships between the individual and society than<br />

did Durkheim. Much social action, Tarde pointed out, was based not on constraint from the external<br />

imposition of social norms, but grew out of spontaneous imitation of beliefs and desires that<br />

subsequently became internalized by the individual and, through a process of learning, continued to<br />

structure his behavior.<br />

Growing largely from the commitment of Tarde to an emphasis on the autonomy of the individual<br />

and a grounding of his behavior in Spontaneity, and of Durkheim to the predominance of the<br />

collectivity and a Cartesian striving for order, the difference between the two men was reflected in<br />

several other issues. In discussing the general bases for social change, Tarde stressed the centrality of<br />

the creative individual in suggesting new lines of development which the collectivity would<br />

subsequently adopt. Durkheim preferred to emphasize the structural conditions which predisposed a<br />

given collectivity to change, minimizing the importance of individual factors. 21<br />

To explain processes of norm formation, Tarde presented an interactionist theory similar in many<br />

ways to that associated with the name of George Herbert Mead. Durkheim, on the other hand, relied<br />

on such group conditions as heightened collective activity, but he was much less precise in this area<br />

than was Tarde (see section vii below).<br />

Tarde elaborated a theory of social control that grew out of social interaction, and was extended<br />

through larger social groupings with such developments as extensive mass communications (see<br />

section ix). Durkheim, to explain social control, focused more on the constraining influences of values<br />

and norms.<br />

Durkheim maintained at some points that the elementary social unit was the horde, to which Tarde<br />

retorted that it was the individual, or at least the household; but both men recognized that this was not<br />

a point to be resolved a priori, but through more extended study. 22<br />

For us today, many of these positions appear more complementary than contradictory; but such was<br />

not always the case for Tarde and Durkheim. Nevertheless, their debates have helped clarify the<br />

vision of subsequent sociologists.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!