11.12.2012 Views

''Neither an angel nor an ant'': Emotion as an aid to bounded rationality

''Neither an angel nor an ant'': Emotion as an aid to bounded rationality

''Neither an angel nor an ant'': Emotion as an aid to bounded rationality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Abstract<br />

‘‘Neither <strong>an</strong> <strong>an</strong>gel <strong>nor</strong> <strong>an</strong> <strong>an</strong>t’’: <strong>Emotion</strong> <strong>as</strong><br />

<strong>an</strong> <strong>aid</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong><br />

Y<strong>an</strong>iv H<strong>an</strong>och *<br />

Department of Philosophy, University of Haifa, Haifa, Israel<br />

Received 30 November 2000; received in revised form 17 J<strong>an</strong>uary 2001; accepted 20 June 2001<br />

The role ofemotion <strong>as</strong> a source of<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> h<strong>as</strong> been largely ig<strong>nor</strong>ed. Following<br />

Herbert Simon, economists <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> psychologists have mainly focused on cognitive constraints<br />

while neglecting <strong>to</strong> integrate the growing body ofresearch on emotion which indicates<br />

that re<strong>as</strong>on <strong>an</strong>d emotion are interconnected. Accordingly, the present paper aims <strong>to</strong> bridge the<br />

existing gap. By establishing a link between the two domains ofresearch, emotion <strong>an</strong>d<br />

<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>, it will be suggested that emotions work <strong>to</strong>gether with rational thinking<br />

in two distinct ways, <strong>an</strong>d thereby function <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> additional source of <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>.<br />

The aim, therefore, is not <strong>to</strong> offer <strong>an</strong> alternative <strong>to</strong> <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>; rather, the purpose<br />

is <strong>to</strong> elaborate <strong>an</strong>d supplement themes emerging out of<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>. Ó 2002 Elsevier<br />

Science B.V. All rights reserved.<br />

PsycINFO cl<strong>as</strong>sification: 2360<br />

JEL cl<strong>as</strong>sification: D00<br />

Keywords: Bounded <strong>rationality</strong>; <strong>Emotion</strong><br />

1. Introduction<br />

Journal ofEconomic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

www.elsevier.com/locate/joep<br />

A survey by Lewin (1996) provides <strong>an</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical <strong>an</strong>alysis regarding economists’<br />

departure from Bentham’s original formulation of the utility construct, where emo-<br />

* Present address: Center for Adaptive Behavior <strong>an</strong>d Cognition, Max Pl<strong>an</strong>ck Institute for Hum<strong>an</strong><br />

Development, L<strong>an</strong>tzeallee 94, 14195 Berlin, Germ<strong>an</strong>y. Tel.: +49-30-82406-340; fax: +49-30-8249939.<br />

E-mail address: yh<strong>an</strong>och@mpib-berlin.mpg.de (Y. H<strong>an</strong>och).<br />

0167-4870/02/$ - see front matter Ó 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.<br />

PII: S0167-4870(01)00065-4


2 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

tions played a signific<strong>an</strong>t role, <strong>an</strong>d reli<strong>an</strong>t instead on cognitive fac<strong>to</strong>rs. Rabin’s<br />

(1998) survey ‘‘Psychology <strong>an</strong>d Economics’’ h<strong>as</strong>, on the other h<strong>an</strong>d, little <strong>to</strong> say<br />

about emotions. This is a neglect characteristic ofeconomists. Although cognitive<br />

psychology <strong>an</strong>d economics have influenced one <strong>an</strong>other <strong>as</strong> in the work ofTversky<br />

<strong>an</strong>d Kahnem<strong>an</strong> (1973, 1974), no similar exch<strong>an</strong>ge ofide<strong>as</strong> h<strong>as</strong> taken place <strong>nor</strong> h<strong>as</strong><br />

<strong>an</strong>y prominent figure arisen <strong>to</strong> establish a bond between emotion <strong>an</strong>d economic theories<br />

(Elster, 1998). As this lacuna h<strong>as</strong> only lately been acknowledged (Earl, 1986a,<br />

1990; Elster, 1999; Etzioni, 1988; Fr<strong>an</strong>k, 1988; Loewenstein, 2000), few attempts<br />

have been made <strong>to</strong> bridge the existing gap. Bounded Rationality h<strong>as</strong> been one area<br />

where little exch<strong>an</strong>ge ofide<strong>as</strong> between emotion <strong>an</strong>d economic theorists h<strong>as</strong> taken<br />

place.<br />

Simon’s (1947, 1955, 1982a), <strong>an</strong>d others’ (Conlisk, 1996; March, 1978), concept<br />

ofBounded Rationality (hereafter BR) h<strong>as</strong> received much attention ever since it<br />

w<strong>as</strong> first introduced – Simon, for example, won the Nobel Prize in economics in<br />

1978. In fact, BR h<strong>as</strong> become a prominent theory influencing m<strong>an</strong>y domains of research<br />

including economics, political science, psychology, <strong>an</strong>d artificial intelligence.<br />

One ofSimon’s main concerns in developing the concept ofBR, w<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> explain<br />

hum<strong>an</strong> re<strong>as</strong>oned thinking <strong>an</strong>d behavior. In a way, he disagreed with prevailing<br />

models ofhum<strong>an</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> <strong>an</strong>d ir<strong>rationality</strong>, arguing that they fell short in their<br />

ability <strong>to</strong> depict a realistic representation ofhum<strong>an</strong> behavior. He wrote, for example,<br />

that:<br />

We may deem behavior irrational because, although it serves some particular<br />

impulse, it is inconsistent with other goals that we may deem more<br />

import<strong>an</strong>t. We may deem it irrational because the ac<strong>to</strong>r is proceeding on<br />

incorrect facts or ig<strong>nor</strong>ing whole are<strong>as</strong> of relev<strong>an</strong>t facts. We may deem it<br />

irrational because the ac<strong>to</strong>r h<strong>as</strong> not drawn the correct conclusions from<br />

the facts. We may deem it irrational because the ac<strong>to</strong>r h<strong>as</strong> failed <strong>to</strong> consider<br />

import<strong>an</strong>t alternative courses ofaction. Ifthe action involves the future,<br />

<strong>as</strong> most action does, we may deem it irrational because we don’t<br />

think the ac<strong>to</strong>r uses the best methods for forming expectations or for<br />

adapting <strong>to</strong> uncertainty. All ofthese forms ofir<strong>rationality</strong> play import<strong>an</strong>t<br />

roles in the lives ofevery one ofus, but I think it is misleading <strong>to</strong> call<br />

them ir<strong>rationality</strong>. They are better viewed <strong>as</strong> forms of <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong><br />

(Simon, 1985, p. 297).<br />

Simon’s argument c<strong>an</strong> be divided in<strong>to</strong> two domains (March, 1978), both aimed,<br />

among other things, at bringing psychology <strong>an</strong>d economics closer <strong>to</strong>gether. The first,<br />

articulated in his paper of1955, argues that <strong>rationality</strong> is constrained, hence<br />

<strong>bounded</strong>, since we possess limited computational ability <strong>an</strong>d selective memory <strong>an</strong>d<br />

perception. The second line ofargument, developed in his paper of1956, concerns<br />

economists’ neglecting <strong>to</strong> integrate environmental fac<strong>to</strong>rs in<strong>to</strong> their consideration<br />

of<strong>rationality</strong>. He <strong>as</strong>serts that ‘‘we might hope <strong>to</strong> discover, by careful examination<br />

ofsome ofthe fundamental structural characteristics ofthe environment, some further<br />

clues <strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> the nature ofthe approximating mech<strong>an</strong>isms used in decision making’’<br />

(cf. Simon, 1956, p. 130).


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 3<br />

Simon’s focus on cognitive capabilities <strong>as</strong> the sole source of BR is in accord<br />

with the research mode in psychology <strong>an</strong>d economics. On the one h<strong>an</strong>d he maintains<br />

that ‘‘people have re<strong>as</strong>ons for what they do; they have motivations <strong>an</strong>d use<br />

re<strong>as</strong>on (well or badly) <strong>to</strong> respond <strong>to</strong> these motivations <strong>an</strong>d reach their goal’’ (cf.<br />

Simon, 1987, pp. 25–26), <strong>an</strong>d on the other h<strong>an</strong>d he argues that ‘‘re<strong>as</strong>on is wholly<br />

instrumental. It c<strong>an</strong>not tell us where <strong>to</strong> go; at best it c<strong>an</strong> tell us how <strong>to</strong> get there. It<br />

is a gun for hire that c<strong>an</strong> be employed in the service of whatever goals we have,<br />

good or bad’’ (1983, pp. 7–8). Indeed, people use re<strong>as</strong>on <strong>to</strong> respond <strong>to</strong> these motivations,<br />

but they also use emotions. What sets the stage is our emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism,<br />

while one function of re<strong>as</strong>on is <strong>to</strong> explore the possible paths <strong>to</strong> get there.<br />

That is, while ends c<strong>an</strong>not be determined logically by re<strong>as</strong>on (Hare, 1963; Popper,<br />

1962), once ends are determined, it is the role ofre<strong>as</strong>on <strong>to</strong> take us there. ‘‘In circumst<strong>an</strong>ces<br />

sufficiently known’’, Shackle (1972, p. 135) argues, ‘‘re<strong>as</strong>on may tell<br />

what action will lead <strong>to</strong> what end. But re<strong>as</strong>on will not tell what end ought <strong>to</strong> be<br />

chosen’’.<br />

Working mainly within the cognitive framework <strong>an</strong>d concentrating on ends<br />

rather th<strong>an</strong> process, it is not surprising that economists have neglected <strong>to</strong> examine<br />

the role emotions might play in BR. Aside from scattered research (Kaufm<strong>an</strong>,<br />

1999; Pieters & v<strong>an</strong> Raaij, 1988; Simon, 1967, 1982b) little h<strong>as</strong> been done <strong>to</strong> incorporate<br />

the growing body ofresearch on emotion in<strong>to</strong> the domain ofBR, <strong>nor</strong> have<br />

emotion theorist tried <strong>to</strong> integrate BR in<strong>to</strong> their discourse. Reading the literature<br />

on BR, one might suspect that emotions do not exist, or that their contribution is,<br />

at best, minimal. Indeed, Davis (1996) <strong>an</strong>d Dennard (1995) have criticized Simon’s<br />

work for portraying hum<strong>an</strong>s’ behavior in a cold m<strong>an</strong>ner, thus creating a unidimensional<br />

view. Davis writes that Simon’s depiction ofthe supremacy of<strong>rationality</strong> ig<strong>nor</strong>es<br />

<strong>as</strong>pects of‘‘democracy, justice, equality <strong>an</strong>d so forth’’ (1996, p. 44).<br />

Dennard, likewise, <strong>as</strong>serts that ‘‘neo-Darwinists, like Simon, enamored ofskills,<br />

techniques, t<strong>as</strong>ks, <strong>an</strong>d programs, have made light ofthe very hum<strong>an</strong> need for idealism<br />

<strong>an</strong>d <strong>as</strong>piration – emotional dispositions that could lead <strong>to</strong> a more hum<strong>an</strong>e<br />

world th<strong>an</strong> which rational economics c<strong>an</strong> conceptually m<strong>as</strong>ter’’ (1995, p. 464).<br />

Adopting Simon’s work, these authors argue, presents individuals <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> inferior<br />

image ofMr. Spock – unemotional but without Spock’s information processing capacities<br />

(Earl, 2001).<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong>s, we hope <strong>to</strong> show, c<strong>an</strong> be seen <strong>to</strong> function <strong>as</strong> a vital mech<strong>an</strong>ism. We<br />

suggest that emotions operate with rational thinking in two distinct modes: (i) they<br />

restrict the r<strong>an</strong>ge ofoptions contemplated <strong>an</strong>d evaluated; (ii) they focus the agent’s<br />

attention on specific parameters or <strong>as</strong>pects ofthe information. The aim is <strong>to</strong> illustrate<br />

the junctions at which emotions <strong>an</strong>d <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> conjoin, without committing<br />

<strong>to</strong> the stronger claim that emotions have a beneficial <strong>an</strong>d/or deleterious effect.<br />

They might have both.<br />

Integrating emotions in<strong>to</strong> the BR equation might provide <strong>an</strong> additional source of<br />

expl<strong>an</strong>ation pertaining <strong>to</strong> how hum<strong>an</strong>s, despite their limited cognitive ability, function<br />

<strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> they do. The questions ofhow a person decides when <strong>to</strong> start <strong>an</strong>d/or<br />

s<strong>to</strong>p evaluating relev<strong>an</strong>t information, of which information he or she decides <strong>to</strong><br />

incorporate in<strong>to</strong> the equation, <strong>an</strong>d which bites ofinformation receive priorities still


4 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

need <strong>an</strong> adequate <strong>an</strong>swer (but see below Simon’s notion ofsatisficing). At le<strong>as</strong>t partially,<br />

however, the <strong>an</strong>swer is through emotions.<br />

2. Subjective expected utility<br />

BR h<strong>as</strong> emerged, in part, <strong>as</strong> a reaction <strong>to</strong> the Subjective Expected Utility (SEU)<br />

model (von Neum<strong>an</strong>n & Morgenstern, 1947). Researchers working in the field ofdecision-making<br />

(Zey, 1992) <strong>an</strong>d <strong>rationality</strong> (Brown, 1978; Elster, 1984) have come <strong>to</strong><br />

realize that SEU offers only limited expl<strong>an</strong>ation power. Although the theory h<strong>as</strong><br />

been beneficial in m<strong>an</strong>y ways, it does not provide <strong>an</strong> accurate description ofthe hum<strong>an</strong><br />

mind.<br />

There are several <strong>as</strong>sumptions underlying SEU. Firstly, a person is <strong>as</strong>sumed <strong>to</strong><br />

possess a well-defined utility function. Hence, it is presumed that people c<strong>an</strong> <strong>as</strong>sign<br />

values <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> indica<strong>to</strong>r oftheir preference <strong>to</strong>wards different stimuli or events in a<br />

given scenario (present <strong>an</strong>d future). Secondly, it presupposes that individuals are<br />

faced with a well-defined cluster of options from which <strong>to</strong> choose. SEU does not<br />

require the entire scenario <strong>to</strong> be a one-time occ<strong>as</strong>ion, but <strong>as</strong> Simon indicates,<br />

‘‘may entail sequences ofchoices or strategies in which each subchoice will be<br />

made only at a specified time using the information available at that time’’<br />

(1983, p. 12). Thirdly, it maintains that individuals c<strong>an</strong> provide uniform mutual<br />

probabilities distribution <strong>to</strong> all events (Macleod, 1996). Finally, it predicts that<br />

the decision-maker will pick the option, or the strategy that delivers the highest expected<br />

value, in terms ofhis utility function, ofa set ofevents consequent upon the<br />

strategy. Although the theory h<strong>as</strong> m<strong>an</strong>y problems that make it close <strong>to</strong> impossible<br />

<strong>to</strong> use in a straightforward way, it h<strong>as</strong> certainly made a major contribution <strong>to</strong> economic<br />

theory.<br />

There are four b<strong>as</strong>ic objections <strong>to</strong> SEU. The theory <strong>as</strong>sumes that the individual<br />

comprehensively examines the entire r<strong>an</strong>ge ofpossibilities; that he gr<strong>as</strong>ps the whole<br />

spectrum of options open <strong>to</strong> him at present <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> far in<strong>to</strong> the future; that he comprehends<br />

the results ofeach ofthe alternatives possible, at le<strong>as</strong>t up <strong>to</strong> the point of<br />

being able <strong>to</strong> <strong>as</strong>sign a joint probability distribution <strong>to</strong> future states of the world;<br />

<strong>an</strong>d, in Simon’s words, ‘‘that he h<strong>as</strong> reconciled or bal<strong>an</strong>ced all his conflicting partial<br />

values <strong>an</strong>d synthesized them in<strong>to</strong> a single coherent utility function that orders, by his<br />

reference for them, all these future states of the world’’ (1983, p. 13).<br />

Researchers (Arrow, 1992; Hollins & Nell, 1975; March, 1994) have presented numerous<br />

challenges <strong>to</strong> the above <strong>as</strong>sumptions. The shortcomings ofthe theory come<br />

from several fronts. Firstly, all possible alternatives are not known (Levi, 1997).<br />

Even among the known alternatives, the outcomes attached <strong>to</strong> each are not known.<br />

Secondly, some issues never reach the agent making the decision. Thirdly, Some<br />

problems that do reach the agents but are evaluated or defined <strong>as</strong> insignific<strong>an</strong>t<br />

<strong>an</strong>d irrelev<strong>an</strong>t. Finally, agents’ information may be lacking, unrelated, <strong>to</strong>o complicated,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d <strong>to</strong>o v<strong>as</strong>t.<br />

March (1978) h<strong>as</strong> raised several additional problems with SEU. He maintains that<br />

the properties oft<strong>as</strong>te (which might bear a closer relationship <strong>to</strong> emotional evaluation


ather th<strong>an</strong> <strong>to</strong> rational deliberation), <strong>as</strong> depicted in st<strong>an</strong>dard theories ofchoice, seem<br />

inconsistent with the observation ofboth individuals’ <strong>an</strong>d org<strong>an</strong>izations’ choice behavior<br />

(see also Etzioni, 1992, pp. 14–17). T<strong>as</strong>tes, according <strong>to</strong> <strong>nor</strong>mative description,<br />

are absolute, stable, consistent, precise, exogenous, <strong>an</strong>d relev<strong>an</strong>t (March, 1978, pp.<br />

595–596). Yet, individuals are not always consistent in their t<strong>as</strong>tes; t<strong>as</strong>tes tend <strong>to</strong><br />

ch<strong>an</strong>ge throughout life; choices are made without respect <strong>to</strong> t<strong>as</strong>te, <strong>an</strong>d at times are<br />

contrary <strong>to</strong> our t<strong>as</strong>tes (such <strong>as</strong> when our t<strong>as</strong>tes contradict societal <strong>nor</strong>ms or laws);<br />

t<strong>as</strong>tes are not precise, <strong>an</strong>d t<strong>as</strong>tes are partially determined endogenously (March,<br />

1978). By juxtaposing neocl<strong>as</strong>sical economics <strong>an</strong>d <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>, March not<br />

only points out the shortcoming ofSEU, but also argues that theory ofchoice must<br />

have a better underst<strong>an</strong>ding ofthe intricacy ofpreference processing. This is due <strong>to</strong><br />

the fact that ‘‘goals <strong>an</strong>d preferences are at the same time premises for <strong>an</strong>d outcomes<br />

ofhum<strong>an</strong> <strong>an</strong>d org<strong>an</strong>izational choice’’ (Augier & Kreiner, 2000, p. 675). It is not surprising,<br />

then, that Simon claims that ‘‘SEU theory h<strong>as</strong> never been applied, <strong>nor</strong> will it,<br />

by <strong>an</strong>y hum<strong>an</strong>’’ (1983, p. 14).<br />

3. Bounded <strong>rationality</strong><br />

Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 5<br />

The problems inherent in SEU have driven the search for <strong>an</strong> alternative model.<br />

One model <strong>to</strong> emerge in the late 1940s is Simon’s Bounded Rationality (cf. Simon,<br />

1947). One aim ofBR is <strong>to</strong> overcome the obstacles presented in SEU <strong>an</strong>d <strong>to</strong> introduce<br />

a model that c<strong>an</strong> more accurately describe the m<strong>an</strong>ner in which we make decisions.<br />

A b<strong>as</strong>ic notion that will be exceedingly import<strong>an</strong>t in the rest ofthe paper is<br />

that we are living in <strong>an</strong> unpredictable world, with limited knowledge ofthat world,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d with limited processing capabilities. One ofSimon’s intentions in developing BR<br />

w<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> illustrate the restricted ability we have <strong>as</strong> rational agents. He argues that ‘‘hum<strong>an</strong><br />

beings have neither the facts <strong>nor</strong> the consistent structure of values <strong>nor</strong> the re<strong>as</strong>oning<br />

power at their disposal that would be required, even in these relatively simple<br />

situations, <strong>to</strong> apply SEU models’’ (1983, p. 17).<br />

One import<strong>an</strong>t fac<strong>to</strong>r operating in the process of decision making is our effort investment.<br />

Ifone is looking in<strong>to</strong> investing a large sum ofmoney, for example, one is<br />

expected <strong>to</strong> examine the matter seriously by exploring the various options, risks, interest,<br />

etc. One must devote resources in the form of time <strong>an</strong>d effort <strong>to</strong> investigating<br />

the various <strong>as</strong>pects of that investment. After one h<strong>as</strong> gathered the relev<strong>an</strong>t information<br />

(ifone c<strong>an</strong> gather all relev<strong>an</strong>t information), one still needs <strong>to</strong> conduct <strong>an</strong> evaluation,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d perhaps re-check one’s ide<strong>as</strong>. What we are stating here is that when we<br />

are faced with a decision we have <strong>to</strong> devote m<strong>an</strong>y resources – time, money, energy,<br />

etc. – <strong>to</strong> it.<br />

BR does not <strong>as</strong>sume that one h<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> make choices that reach far in<strong>to</strong> the future,<br />

that encomp<strong>as</strong>ses the whole spectrum ofhum<strong>an</strong> values, <strong>an</strong>d in which each problem is<br />

interconnected with all the other problems in the world. On the contrary, the environment<br />

in which we live is one characterized by the unique nature ofeach problem.<br />

At different times we make decisions concerning our biological needs (e.g., hunger),<br />

physiological needs (e.g., sleep) <strong>an</strong>d psychological needs (e.g., love). Luckily, we


6 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

seldom need <strong>to</strong> resolve all these problems at once. M<strong>as</strong>low’s ide<strong>as</strong> regarding hierarchy<br />

ofneeds capitalize precisely on this point. We c<strong>an</strong>, ofcourse, be hungry <strong>an</strong>d tired<br />

at the same time, but the most urgent need must be satisfied first (Robbins, 1984, pp.<br />

114–115). You will, ifyou are starving, probably eat before you will go <strong>to</strong> bed. While<br />

we have m<strong>an</strong>y needs that at times co-occur we act <strong>as</strong> ifone is more pressing th<strong>an</strong> the<br />

other (Jauregui, 1995).<br />

In most ofthe day-<strong>to</strong>-day scenarios we encounter, we c<strong>an</strong> comprehend or <strong>as</strong>similate<br />

only a fraction of the variables or stimuli present: that is, we are limited in our<br />

information-processing capacities. We c<strong>an</strong> <strong>as</strong>similate, pay attention, focus, <strong>an</strong>d perform<br />

one, or at most a few, functions simult<strong>an</strong>eously. As Heiner (1983) pointed out,<br />

the nature ofuncertainty is imbedded in the fact that individuals c<strong>an</strong>not unravel all<br />

the complexity ofthe decision problem they face – which is one re<strong>as</strong>on they c<strong>an</strong>not<br />

choose the best option.<br />

The above description ofthe world might present, however, difficulties. We c<strong>an</strong><br />

speculate that the mech<strong>an</strong>ism for re<strong>as</strong>oning ‘‘is adaptive’’ <strong>an</strong>d w<strong>as</strong> sufficient at one<br />

point <strong>to</strong> function within the boundaries just described. The cavem<strong>an</strong>’s environment<br />

w<strong>as</strong> not saturated with information <strong>to</strong> the degree that ours is <strong>to</strong>day. Simon claims that<br />

in fact very little w<strong>as</strong> happening most of the time, although action had <strong>to</strong> be periodically<br />

taken <strong>to</strong> deal with our b<strong>as</strong>ic needs such <strong>as</strong> finding food, securing protection, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

raising children. Rational mech<strong>an</strong>isms could focus on dealing with one or with a few<br />

problems at a time, with the expectation that when other problems arose there would<br />

be time <strong>to</strong> deal with those <strong>to</strong>o. Furthermore, the argument adv<strong>an</strong>ced by Heiner builds<br />

on the notion that our simple ways ofdealing with the environment make it e<strong>as</strong>ier for<br />

others <strong>to</strong> predict our behavior. That is, ‘‘the fac<strong>to</strong>rs that st<strong>an</strong>dard theory places in the<br />

error term are in fact what is producing regularity, while optimizing will tend <strong>to</strong> produce<br />

sophisticated deviation from these patterns’’ (Heiner, 1983, p. 585).<br />

One question we c<strong>an</strong> <strong>as</strong>k is what mech<strong>an</strong>isms <strong>an</strong> org<strong>an</strong>ism needs in order <strong>to</strong> employ<br />

a re<strong>as</strong>onable kind of<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>? The first obvious <strong>an</strong>swer might be: a<br />

mech<strong>an</strong>ism which discriminates between the various types ofincoming information<br />

<strong>an</strong>d which allows one <strong>to</strong> focus one’s attention on a selective set of information. Further,<br />

we need a mech<strong>an</strong>ism endowed with the ability <strong>to</strong> generate alternatives: a large<br />

part ofour problem-solving consists ofsearching for alternatives or improvements<br />

on the alternatives we already have. The third mech<strong>an</strong>ism we might need is one with<br />

a capacity for gathering facts about the environment in which we live <strong>an</strong>d <strong>an</strong> ability<br />

<strong>to</strong> draw inferences from these observations. The l<strong>as</strong>t mech<strong>an</strong>ism <strong>an</strong> org<strong>an</strong>ism might<br />

need is a start <strong>an</strong>d s<strong>to</strong>p rule.<br />

Simon h<strong>as</strong> provided one possibility pertaining <strong>to</strong> the above questions: instead of<br />

optimizing, <strong>as</strong> suggested by SEU, people search for a ‘‘good enough’’ solution (see<br />

Radner, 1975). One should note, however, that ‘‘<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> is not the study<br />

ofoptimization in relation <strong>to</strong> t<strong>as</strong>k environment’’ (Simon, 1991, p. 35). Instead, satisficing,<br />

<strong>as</strong> Gigerenzer <strong>an</strong>d Todd argue, ‘‘is a method for making a choice from a set<br />

ofalternatives encountered sequentially when one does not know much about the<br />

possibilities ahead oftime’ (1999, p. 13). The idea is that although optimal solutions<br />

might exist (<strong>as</strong> in a game ofchess), hum<strong>an</strong> limited cognitive capacities render it close<br />

<strong>to</strong> impossible, ifnot impossible, <strong>to</strong> find them. Instead ofsearching all possible alter-


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 7<br />

natives, computing utility function for each strategy, <strong>an</strong>d memorizing all the facts,<br />

one decides according <strong>to</strong> simpler mech<strong>an</strong>ism: satisficing. Satisficing creates mental<br />

‘shortcuts’ that allows the decision maker <strong>to</strong> end the search once he or she encounters<br />

<strong>an</strong> alternative that meets or exceeds a specific <strong>as</strong>piration level (Earl, 1983, pp.<br />

78–81). Satisficing, according <strong>to</strong> March, ‘‘is less ofa decision rule th<strong>an</strong> a search rule.<br />

It specifies the conditions under which search is triggered or s<strong>to</strong>ps, <strong>an</strong>d it directs<br />

search <strong>to</strong> are<strong>as</strong> offailure’’ (1994, p. 27).<br />

4. <strong>Emotion</strong>s <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> <strong>aid</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong><br />

Research on emotions, both in theory <strong>an</strong>d in empirical finding, h<strong>as</strong> proliferated<br />

greatly in the l<strong>as</strong>t three decades (Ekm<strong>an</strong> & Davidson, 1994; Izard, 1977; Frijda,<br />

1986; Lazarus, 1991; Oatley, 1992). While emotions have traditionally been predominately<br />

judged <strong>to</strong> be disorg<strong>an</strong>ized <strong>an</strong>d irrational, more up-<strong>to</strong>-date theories have struggled<br />

<strong>to</strong> argue the opposite (De Sousa, 1987; Leeper, 1948). Indeed, emotions have, in<br />

recent years, been portrayed <strong>as</strong> rational (Lyons, 1980; Turski, 1994), <strong>as</strong> functional<br />

(Ben-Ze’ev, 2000; LeDoux, 1996), <strong>an</strong>d <strong>as</strong> a necessary <strong>to</strong>ol in decision-making (Charl<strong>an</strong>d,<br />

1998; Dam<strong>as</strong>io, 1994; Picard, 1997). In light ofthese ch<strong>an</strong>ges, the purpose ofthis<br />

study is <strong>to</strong> show that the emotions constitute a phenomenon that supplements themes<br />

arising out of<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>, <strong>an</strong>d hence satisfies Elster’s first issue concerning<br />

<strong>rationality</strong> <strong>an</strong>d the emotions (see Elster, 1999, p. 283–284). What we me<strong>an</strong> by this<br />

is that emotions function <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> information processing mech<strong>an</strong>ism with their own internal<br />

logic, working in conjunction with rational calculation. By restricting the r<strong>an</strong>ge<br />

ofoptions considered (reducing the load on short <strong>an</strong>d long term memory), by focusing<br />

on certain variables (certain stimuli receive higher r<strong>an</strong>king order), <strong>an</strong>d by initiating<br />

<strong>an</strong>d terminating the evaluation process (working <strong>as</strong> a satisficing mech<strong>an</strong>ism),<br />

emotions supplement the insufficiencies ofre<strong>as</strong>on. In other words, while hum<strong>an</strong>s’ <strong>rationality</strong><br />

is limited in its information processing capacity (Simon, 1982a, 1967), emotions<br />

serve <strong>as</strong> one ofthe <strong>to</strong>ols, designed by evolution, by which we m<strong>an</strong>age <strong>to</strong> function<br />

<strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> we do (P<strong>an</strong>ksepp, 1996; Plutchik, 1980; Tooby & Cosmides, 1990).<br />

5. <strong>Emotion</strong>s <strong>as</strong> a prioritizingmech<strong>an</strong>ism<br />

5.1. Attention <strong>as</strong> a scarce resource<br />

One ofthe problems raised by Simon is which goal <strong>an</strong> agent must attend <strong>to</strong> first,<br />

given the multiple goals we have (i.e., why goal X h<strong>as</strong> higher order r<strong>an</strong>king th<strong>an</strong> goal<br />

Y). One needs a system that will create a hierarchical order ofprioritization <strong>an</strong>d<br />

postponement. What is the mech<strong>an</strong>ism ofthat system? 1 While we acknowledge that<br />

1<br />

Ifwe had only one goal, this issue would not arise. Yet seldom, ifever, do hum<strong>an</strong>s have a single goal in<br />

mind (Or<strong>to</strong>ny, et al., 1988; Simon, 1983).


8 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

more th<strong>an</strong> one mech<strong>an</strong>ism might underline this procedure, currently we aim <strong>to</strong> deal<br />

with only one: our emotions. Following Oatley <strong>an</strong>d Johnson-Laird (1987), we propose<br />

that emotions are part ofthe arsenal available <strong>to</strong> us <strong>to</strong> find our way in a world<br />

with multiple goals – given its constraints oftime, energy, <strong>an</strong>d other resources. This<br />

l<strong>as</strong>t point, constraints on resources, h<strong>as</strong> generally been overlooked by economists.<br />

Berger (1989), following Simon (1978) <strong>an</strong>d March (1982), argues that we should treat<br />

attention <strong>as</strong> a scarce resource, <strong>an</strong>d <strong>as</strong> such, should accredit attention a more prominent<br />

place in economics. Attention playing a crucial role in coordinating behavior,<br />

in knowledge, <strong>an</strong>d in communication – is therefore import<strong>an</strong>t in all economic phenomena.<br />

Since attentional deployment ‘‘c<strong>an</strong>not be explained by recourse <strong>to</strong> calculation<br />

with respect <strong>to</strong> underlying objects constituting the economic environment’’<br />

(Berger, 1989, p. 220), we need <strong>to</strong> investigate other mech<strong>an</strong>isms that shed light on<br />

the phenomenon. Furthermore, because re<strong>as</strong>on ‘‘c<strong>an</strong>’t select our final goals, <strong>nor</strong><br />

c<strong>an</strong> it mediate for us in pure conflicts over what final goal <strong>to</strong> pursue – we have <strong>to</strong><br />

settle these issues in some other way’’ (Simon, 1983, p. 106). One other way, we<br />

maintain, is via our emotions.<br />

People tend <strong>to</strong> have, simult<strong>an</strong>eously, several goals. At times these goals contradict<br />

one <strong>an</strong>other; at times they have no relationship with each other; sometimes they have<br />

some bearing on one <strong>an</strong>other, <strong>an</strong>d at other times are the first step <strong>to</strong> achieving a higher<br />

r<strong>an</strong>king goal (e.g., <strong>to</strong> save money [subgoal 1], in order <strong>to</strong> retire comfortably [goal 1]).<br />

One way in which emotions function is <strong>to</strong> divert a particular course of action being<br />

taken in order <strong>to</strong> pursue a more urgent objective. That is, while one might be in<br />

the course ofpursuing goal X, emotional arousal c<strong>an</strong> subvert attention in order <strong>to</strong><br />

pursue goal Y. Thus, emotions c<strong>an</strong> function <strong>as</strong> a mech<strong>an</strong>ism for establishing a hierarchy<br />

ofgoals by pressing us <strong>to</strong> pursue goals that have high survival value while setting<br />

<strong>as</strong>ide less urgent ones. In the words ofSimon, ‘‘emotion c<strong>an</strong> ...distract you from<br />

your current focus of thought, <strong>an</strong>d call your attention <strong>to</strong> something else that presumably<br />

needs attention right now’’ (1983, p. 21). Focusing <strong>an</strong>d directing our attention is<br />

one ofthe fundamental roles played by our emotions. Like thirst or hunger, <strong>an</strong> emotion<br />

informs us that something in the environment needs our immediate attention <strong>an</strong>d<br />

resources.<br />

To see how the mech<strong>an</strong>ism works, the research done by LeDoux (1994) <strong>an</strong>d others<br />

(Berkowitz, 1993; P<strong>an</strong>ksepp, 1982) c<strong>an</strong> be of<strong>as</strong>sist<strong>an</strong>ce. They maintain that information<br />

processing c<strong>an</strong> occur in two different ch<strong>an</strong>nels. The first, the emotional<br />

ch<strong>an</strong>nel, is shorter though less precise (‘‘quick but dirty’’ <strong>as</strong> LeDoux terms it); the<br />

second, the rational, is slower, though more precise. Evolution h<strong>as</strong>, in a sense, given<br />

us two options: (i) act f<strong>as</strong>t, with the risk of making mistakes, or (ii) act slowly,<br />

though with more precision. There are adv<strong>an</strong>tages, ofcourse, <strong>to</strong> each option. (For<br />

a discussion on the tradeoff between accuracy <strong>an</strong>d information gathering, see Heiner,<br />

1986.) 2 But in c<strong>as</strong>es ofd<strong>an</strong>ger, <strong>as</strong> Zajonc points out, ‘‘the decision <strong>to</strong> run must be<br />

2 One should be aware that acting slowly does not guar<strong>an</strong>tee more accurate decisions for two re<strong>as</strong>ons.<br />

First, information might become outdated <strong>as</strong> the environment ch<strong>an</strong>ges; <strong>an</strong>d second, accumulation of<br />

information c<strong>an</strong> result in system overload, since the agent might not be able <strong>to</strong> <strong>an</strong>alyze the immense<br />

accumulated data.


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 9<br />

made on the b<strong>as</strong>is ofminimal cognitive engagement’’ (1980, p. 156). The ‘‘decision’’<br />

on which path <strong>to</strong> take is executed au<strong>to</strong>matically with no conscious awareness. Information<br />

is moving through each neural network simult<strong>an</strong>eously, <strong>an</strong>d depending on<br />

the me<strong>an</strong>ing attached <strong>to</strong> the information, we c<strong>an</strong> react either in a preprogrammed<br />

way (Ekm<strong>an</strong>, 1992; P<strong>an</strong>ksepp, 1982), or we c<strong>an</strong> further evaluate the information.<br />

That is, ifthe information carries with it a particular signal such <strong>as</strong> d<strong>an</strong>ger, then<br />

<strong>an</strong> emotional schema is activated, which produces a reaction; but ifthe information<br />

does not fit a preprogrammed criterion, a more elaborate deliberation c<strong>an</strong> occur. We<br />

are not, ofcourse, in control ofthe process. We c<strong>an</strong>not decide whether <strong>to</strong> activate the<br />

emotional program or <strong>to</strong> rely on our rational thinking. In a sense, the emotional system<br />

is designed <strong>to</strong> react <strong>to</strong> stimuli (i.e., preda<strong>to</strong>rs) in a schematic f<strong>as</strong>hion with ‘‘the<br />

most-likely-<strong>to</strong>-succeed behavior’’ (LeDoux, 1996, p. 175).<br />

An example might help <strong>to</strong> illustrate the above point. Imagine you are walking in<br />

the forest, enjoying the sites, smells, <strong>an</strong>d tr<strong>an</strong>quility of the surroundings. Your goal<br />

might be, say, <strong>to</strong> pick berries, or <strong>to</strong> reach the <strong>to</strong>p ofa mountain. While hiking, you<br />

suddenly see <strong>an</strong> object resembling a snake. Before you have time <strong>to</strong> think things over<br />

you jump backwards. The process ofjumping back em<strong>an</strong>ated not from rational<br />

thinking about the nature ofthe object, <strong>nor</strong> from rationally thinking about the options<br />

available <strong>to</strong> you. Rather, <strong>as</strong> LeDoux maintains (see also Darwin, 1965), the entire<br />

process is regulated <strong>an</strong>d orchestrated by our emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism. These<br />

reactions have been shaped by evolution <strong>an</strong>d occur au<strong>to</strong>matically (Griffiths, 1997).<br />

When d<strong>an</strong>ger looms, it is highly adv<strong>an</strong>tageous <strong>to</strong> respond quickly. The time saved<br />

by activating the emotional centers, rather th<strong>an</strong> waiting for rational decision,<br />

‘‘may be the difference between life <strong>an</strong>d death’’ (LeDoux, 1996, p. 166). Since rational<br />

thinking takes a longer time, deploying the emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism <strong>to</strong> govern the<br />

procedure h<strong>as</strong> the potential <strong>to</strong> save our life. Thus, while goal X (picking berries) w<strong>as</strong><br />

governing our actions, emotional arousal h<strong>as</strong> shifted the course of the pl<strong>an</strong>, <strong>an</strong>d created<br />

a new pl<strong>an</strong> or a goal: staying alive.<br />

This description, in turn, c<strong>an</strong> be viewed <strong>as</strong> a satisficing mech<strong>an</strong>ism, providing one<br />

potential response <strong>to</strong> ‘‘the infinite regress’’ problem. The infinite regress problem<br />

deals with the problem that ‘‘ifwe c<strong>an</strong> economize on economizing, th<strong>an</strong> we economize<br />

on economizing on economizing, <strong>an</strong>d so on’’ (Conlisk, 1996, p. 687).<br />

Let us consider the infinite regress problem from the following example. In c<strong>as</strong>es of<br />

d<strong>an</strong>ger (perhaps a preda<strong>to</strong>r or a suspicious figure in a dark street), the decision <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>p<br />

evaluating information (or choosing the best strategy) <strong>an</strong>d <strong>to</strong> act is activated au<strong>to</strong>matically,<br />

with no, or little, cognitive evaluation. The decision-maker does not need<br />

<strong>to</strong> consider additional information; she does not have <strong>to</strong> decide how <strong>to</strong> decide how<br />

<strong>to</strong> decide... <strong>as</strong> Lipm<strong>an</strong> (1991) h<strong>as</strong> suggested. There is simply no time <strong>to</strong> thoroughly<br />

evaluate the situation, ifone w<strong>an</strong>ts <strong>to</strong> make it home. There is no time <strong>to</strong> contemplate<br />

the precise nature ofthe object (whether the m<strong>an</strong> in the dark street is your friend or a<br />

potential killer). There is no time <strong>to</strong> gather additional information (should I wait <strong>an</strong>d<br />

look closely at his face?) – given the imprecise nature ofthe person’s perception ofthe<br />

situation, which determines the choice procedure. There is no time <strong>to</strong> calculate probabilities<br />

in order <strong>to</strong> estimate the ch<strong>an</strong>ces ofthe str<strong>an</strong>ger being a foe, or <strong>to</strong> investigate<br />

the various potential escape routes. Instead, all the decision-maker needs is a good


10 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

enough approximation or even a single cue <strong>to</strong> activate the emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism,<br />

which in turn produces reaction. One does not search for <strong>an</strong> optimal solution, for<br />

<strong>an</strong> attached cost <strong>to</strong> this search might be the agent’s life (Zajonc, 1980).<br />

In a way, one c<strong>an</strong> argue that the decision <strong>to</strong> run (or freeze) is in fact the optimal<br />

strategy. Thus it is the rational one from a <strong>nor</strong>mative perspective, where ‘‘<strong>nor</strong>mative’’<br />

here denotes the appropriate response in the given situations. The only difference is<br />

that the agent did not have <strong>to</strong> intellectually calculate or <strong>to</strong> find the best alternative,<br />

for there is <strong>an</strong> additional mech<strong>an</strong>ism that h<strong>as</strong> done the ‘‘job’’ for him: namely evolution.<br />

As Tooby <strong>an</strong>d Cosmides (2000, p. 1172) argue ‘‘natural selection retained neural<br />

structures on their ability <strong>to</strong> create adaptively org<strong>an</strong>ized relationships between information<br />

<strong>an</strong>d behavior (e.g., the sight ofa preda<strong>to</strong>r activates inference procedures that<br />

cause the org<strong>an</strong>ism <strong>to</strong> hide or flee) or between information <strong>an</strong>d physiology (e.g., the<br />

sight ofa preda<strong>to</strong>r incre<strong>as</strong>es the org<strong>an</strong>ism’s heart rate, in preparation for flight)’’.<br />

What Tooby <strong>an</strong>d Cosmides argue, we believe, is that evolution h<strong>as</strong> already done<br />

the calculation for us. It h<strong>as</strong> ‘‘found,’’ through the process of natural selection, the<br />

best procedure for dealing with d<strong>an</strong>ger. In the words of Ekm<strong>an</strong> (1999) ‘‘each emotion<br />

thus prompts us in a direction which, in the course ofevolution, h<strong>as</strong> done better th<strong>an</strong><br />

other solutions in recurring circumst<strong>an</strong>ces that are relev<strong>an</strong>t <strong>to</strong> goals’’ (p. 46).<br />

Elster (1999) <strong>as</strong>ks why the emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism h<strong>as</strong> a priority in situations ofd<strong>an</strong>ger.<br />

It is not, he maintains, that re<strong>as</strong>on c<strong>an</strong>not respond <strong>as</strong> quickly or <strong>as</strong> well, but that<br />

‘‘in reality, ofcourse, that’s not how we cope with novelty or bitter-t<strong>as</strong>ting food – not<br />

because the program is unfe<strong>as</strong>ible but because natural selection h<strong>as</strong> wired us differently’’<br />

(Elster, 1999, p. 291). The emotions carry out the operation not because they<br />

have a better adaptive mech<strong>an</strong>ism, <strong>nor</strong> a better solution th<strong>an</strong> re<strong>as</strong>on c<strong>an</strong> fathom. The<br />

re<strong>as</strong>on emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism reacts first is because we have evolved that way.<br />

5.2. <strong>Emotion</strong>, <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>, <strong>an</strong>d consumer research<br />

Thus far it might seem that emotions could set priorities only in extreme c<strong>as</strong>es of<br />

d<strong>an</strong>ger or fear. This is not the c<strong>as</strong>e. Elster (1999) h<strong>as</strong> provided <strong>an</strong> example from everyday<br />

life in which he sees the integration of emotion in<strong>to</strong> decision making. Coming<br />

back from a vacation <strong>an</strong>d sorting through his mail, Elster must decide which piece of<br />

mail <strong>to</strong> deal with first. He must have a mech<strong>an</strong>ism by which he decides whether paying<br />

his bills (<strong>as</strong> he does) should come before <strong>an</strong>swering his friends. Instead of contemplating<br />

a large set ofpossibilities, scenarios, <strong>an</strong>d their consequences, he rather<br />

follows a few rules of thumb. In deciding the order in which he will deal with the mail<br />

– old letters must be <strong>an</strong>swered first, bills must be p<strong>aid</strong>, etc. – ‘‘emotional tags <strong>an</strong>d<br />

pulls certainly play a role’’ Elster concludes (1999, p. 296).<br />

A similar c<strong>as</strong>e, regarding consumers’ decision making c<strong>an</strong> be found in the work<br />

done by Shiv <strong>an</strong>d Fedorikhin (1999). In their research, subjects had <strong>to</strong> choose between<br />

a chocolate cake <strong>an</strong>d a fruit salad. The authors argue that chocolate cake is<br />

‘‘<strong>as</strong>sociated with more intense positive affect but less favorable cognitions’’, while<br />

the fruit salad is ‘‘<strong>as</strong>sociated with less favorable affect but more favorable cognitions’’<br />

(p. 278). When subjects had little information they were more prone <strong>to</strong> choose<br />

the chocolate cake, hence indicating that affective evaluation provokes a greater im-


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 11<br />

pact on choice. The results ofthis study, according <strong>to</strong> the authors, suggest that ‘‘under<br />

conditions where the consumer does not allocate processing resources <strong>to</strong> the decision-making<br />

t<strong>as</strong>k, she/he is more likely <strong>to</strong> choose b<strong>as</strong>ed on affect rather th<strong>an</strong> on<br />

cognition’’ (1999, p. 288).<br />

The notion that emotions play a more signific<strong>an</strong>t role in decision making gain further<br />

support from research on high-risk sporting activities, where knowledge is often<br />

restricted or limited. Particip<strong>an</strong>ts in risky sport activities such <strong>as</strong> skydiving <strong>an</strong>d water<br />

rafting do not have the time or know-how <strong>to</strong> work out how <strong>to</strong> deal with the information<br />

they encounter. Decisions <strong>to</strong> make the first sky jump, for example, are often<br />

guided by emotional fac<strong>to</strong>rs rather th<strong>an</strong> on rational calculations of cost <strong>an</strong>d benefit.<br />

Research by Celsi, Rose, <strong>an</strong>d Leigh (1993) on skydiving (though the same logic, the<br />

authors maintain, c<strong>an</strong> be applied <strong>to</strong> other risky sports such <strong>as</strong> mountain climbing)<br />

indicates that explaining risky behavior requires a multidimensional perspective.<br />

Yet, what is evident from their research is that the underlining motivation <strong>to</strong> engage<br />

in such risky sports stems from emotional fac<strong>to</strong>rs rather th<strong>an</strong> rational calculation.<br />

The costs are relatively e<strong>as</strong>y <strong>to</strong> indicate prior <strong>to</strong> the jump: money, time, potential injury<br />

<strong>an</strong>d death. The benefits, however, are not only harder <strong>to</strong> qu<strong>an</strong>tify but are difficult<br />

<strong>to</strong> envision, let alone evaluate. The thrill of the free fall, the relief upon the<br />

opening ofthe c<strong>an</strong>opy, the sense ofcommunity (including the rites ofp<strong>as</strong>sage),<br />

are a few of the variables that the first-timer maybe oblivious <strong>to</strong>o. Comments such<br />

<strong>as</strong> ‘‘no one underst<strong>an</strong>ds us <strong>an</strong>d why we do it, only other people that skydive truly<br />

underst<strong>an</strong>d’’ (Celsi et al., 1993, p. 14), are not atypical <strong>to</strong> hear. That is <strong>to</strong> say, novice<br />

skydivers rarely have all the facts required <strong>to</strong> make a rational decision – at le<strong>as</strong>t one<br />

that conforms <strong>to</strong> SEU theory.<br />

Arnold <strong>an</strong>d Price (1993) report similar results from research on river rafting. Although<br />

the experience is costly, both in money <strong>an</strong>d time, ‘‘people do not appear <strong>to</strong><br />

think about it carefully’’ (p. 24). Individuals are motivated <strong>to</strong> engage in river rafting<br />

activities in order <strong>to</strong> have fun, get away from it all, <strong>an</strong>d, like first time jumpers, they<br />

are often just carried along with family members or friends. An illustrative c<strong>as</strong>e<br />

comes from a wealthy client <strong>an</strong>d his family who were disappointed <strong>to</strong> find that the<br />

water in the Green River w<strong>as</strong> not green but muddy, <strong>an</strong>d that the scenery w<strong>as</strong> not<br />

a lush forest but a desert. So disappointed w<strong>as</strong> the client that he requested a helicopter<br />

<strong>to</strong> take him <strong>an</strong>d his family out ofthere. But, at the end ofthe trip ‘‘the family w<strong>as</strong><br />

‘ecstatic’...<strong>an</strong>d later wrote that the trip had brought them <strong>to</strong>gether’’ (1993, p. 40). In<br />

fact, inexperienced cus<strong>to</strong>mers are ill-informed on most, if not all, <strong>as</strong>pects regarding<br />

such trips. Yet, the river rafting industry is growing. As in the c<strong>as</strong>e of skydiving, the<br />

decision <strong>to</strong> participate in river rafting is elicited by emotional expectations, rather<br />

th<strong>an</strong> on rational deliberation ofpros <strong>an</strong>d cons.<br />

5.3. <strong>Emotion</strong> <strong>an</strong>d ‘‘cold’’ calculated machines<br />

Elster’s example, discussed above, is but one ofm<strong>an</strong>y that we c<strong>an</strong> think of. Imagine,<br />

for example, a doc<strong>to</strong>r driving <strong>to</strong> her work at a local hospital. She h<strong>as</strong> at le<strong>as</strong>t one<br />

goal in mind: <strong>to</strong> get <strong>to</strong> work on time. While driving, however, she observes a car accident<br />

in which she suspects there might be injuries. S<strong>to</strong>pping her car <strong>an</strong>d checking


12 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

whether she is needed will probably become a higher order goal; hence, coming <strong>to</strong><br />

work on time will lose its primacy. Let us imagine further that one of the individuals<br />

involved in the accident is a h<strong>an</strong>dsome m<strong>an</strong>, one our doc<strong>to</strong>r finds very attractive. After<br />

making sure he is not hurt, <strong>an</strong>d treating the other individuals, our doc<strong>to</strong>r might<br />

ch<strong>an</strong>ge her priorities <strong>an</strong>d converse with the m<strong>an</strong>, although her tardiness will only incre<strong>as</strong>e.<br />

In this c<strong>as</strong>e, coming <strong>to</strong> work on time drops even lower down the ladder of<br />

import<strong>an</strong>ce. Her goals have ch<strong>an</strong>ged due <strong>to</strong> different emotions: care for others,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d sexual attractiveness.<br />

One might argue that our doc<strong>to</strong>r is exhibiting a perfect example of SEU. Looking at<br />

a beautiful wom<strong>an</strong>/m<strong>an</strong> might generate a certain type of intellectual thought process,<br />

yet, without emotional arousal (sexual attraction, love, desire, etc.) one h<strong>as</strong> no re<strong>as</strong>on<br />

<strong>to</strong> adv<strong>an</strong>ce <strong>to</strong>wards the wom<strong>an</strong>/m<strong>an</strong>. We are attracted <strong>to</strong> a particular person since we<br />

feel (physically or otherwise), something <strong>to</strong>wards that person. We are motivated <strong>to</strong><br />

form a relationship with that person on grounds of emotional desire (Ben-Ze’ev,<br />

2000). Of course, rational calculation c<strong>an</strong> m<strong>an</strong>ifest itself in one form or <strong>an</strong>other (<strong>as</strong><br />

in rationalizing our decision), yet the underlining motivation stems from emotions.<br />

Let us imagine, next, that our doc<strong>to</strong>r <strong>an</strong>d the m<strong>an</strong> get married. A few years down the<br />

road, the doc<strong>to</strong>r h<strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> accident in which she suffers a severe brain injury leaving her<br />

coma<strong>to</strong>se. In fact, the doc<strong>to</strong>rs treating her see no ch<strong>an</strong>ce of recovery. If the doc<strong>to</strong>r’s<br />

husb<strong>an</strong>d were <strong>to</strong> follow SEU theory, the rational thing <strong>to</strong> do might be <strong>to</strong> leave his wife<br />

<strong>an</strong>d search for a new partner. Yet in real life husb<strong>an</strong>ds <strong>an</strong>d wives, frequently not only<br />

stay with their ill spouse – defying SEU expectations – but also visit them often providing<br />

for them for m<strong>an</strong>y years. Leaving emotions such <strong>as</strong> love out of the equation<br />

would portray hum<strong>an</strong>s <strong>as</strong> cold calculating machines, <strong>as</strong> argued by Davis <strong>an</strong>d Dennard.<br />

In one ofhis papers, Simon (1967, p. 31–32) provides a theoretical computer program<br />

simulating the comm<strong>an</strong>ds needed in order <strong>to</strong> reach a destination, designated in<br />

the model <strong>as</strong> block 1400. One potential problem with Simon’s computer-generated illustration<br />

is that it does not take in<strong>to</strong> account <strong>an</strong> individual’s emotional makeup, <strong>an</strong>d,<br />

hence, all the subroutines possible (see Dennett, 1987). Ifwe were <strong>to</strong> insert our doc<strong>to</strong>r<br />

in<strong>to</strong> Simon’s computer simulation, she would have driven straight <strong>to</strong> work, not feeling<br />

the need <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>p. What that person lacks, <strong>as</strong> Charl<strong>an</strong>d (1998) h<strong>as</strong> shown in the c<strong>as</strong>e<br />

ofMr. Spock, is emotion <strong>to</strong> guide her through the labyrinth oflife. There is no doubting<br />

that the computer is better th<strong>an</strong> hum<strong>an</strong>s at certain calculations, but m<strong>an</strong>y ofthe<br />

decisions that hum<strong>an</strong>s make so effortlessly would render the biggest <strong>an</strong>d strongest<br />

computers immobile. One re<strong>as</strong>on is the ‘‘use offeelings <strong>an</strong>d intuition <strong>to</strong> guide re<strong>as</strong>oning<br />

<strong>an</strong>d decision making’’ (Picard, 1997, p. 218; italic is mine).<br />

One should note that the argument above does not consider the question of<br />

whether computers c<strong>an</strong> (or could at some point in the future) feel <strong>an</strong>d exhibit emotions.<br />

Rather, the argument is that in order for computers <strong>to</strong> accurately simulate hum<strong>an</strong><br />

behavior in general, <strong>an</strong>d decision making in particular, they must incorporate<br />

emotional abilities (Levine & Leven, 1992, p. viii).<br />

Picard’s idea might coincide with Keynes (1936) notion of‘‘<strong>an</strong>imal spirit’’ in The<br />

General Theory of Employment, Interest <strong>an</strong>d Money. He argues that not all decisions<br />

are b<strong>as</strong>ed on ‘‘a weighted average ofqu<strong>an</strong>titative benefits multiplied by qu<strong>an</strong>titative<br />

probabilities’’ (p. 161), but rather on a ‘‘spont<strong>an</strong>eous urge <strong>to</strong> action rather th<strong>an</strong> in-


action’’ (ibid.). Decisions made while facing uncertainties, such <strong>as</strong> venturing <strong>to</strong> the<br />

Moon or constructing a fac<strong>to</strong>ry, c<strong>an</strong>not be grounded solely on the precise calculation<br />

of future benefits, for support for such calculation does not exist. ‘‘It is our innate<br />

urge <strong>to</strong> activity which makes the wheels go round, our rational selves choosing between<br />

the alternatives <strong>as</strong> best we are able, calculating where we c<strong>an</strong>, but often falling<br />

back for our motive on whim or sentiment or ch<strong>an</strong>ce’’ (p. 163). Keynes’ argument<br />

w<strong>as</strong> later rephr<strong>as</strong>ed by Simon (‘‘a gun for hire’’), <strong>an</strong>d echoes Hume’s dictum that<br />

‘‘Re<strong>as</strong>on is, <strong>an</strong>d ought only be the slave ofp<strong>as</strong>sions, <strong>an</strong>d c<strong>an</strong> never pretend <strong>to</strong> <strong>an</strong>y<br />

other office th<strong>an</strong> <strong>to</strong> serve <strong>an</strong>d obey them (Hume, 1978/1740, book II, part III, section<br />

III, p. 415; but see Matthews, 1991). 3 The point we argue here (see also, Marchionatti,<br />

1999, <strong>an</strong>d references therein) is that while re<strong>as</strong>on c<strong>an</strong> be employed <strong>to</strong> search for<br />

the best alternatives, ifour ‘‘<strong>an</strong>imal spirits are dimmed <strong>an</strong>d the spont<strong>an</strong>eous optimism<br />

falters... enterprise will fade <strong>an</strong>d die’’ (Keynes, 1936, p. 162).<br />

5.4. <strong>Emotion</strong> <strong>an</strong>d imagination<br />

Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 13<br />

Shackle (1961) h<strong>as</strong> adv<strong>an</strong>ced <strong>an</strong>other line ofargument against SEU, which he<br />

terms potential surprise theory. Briefly stated, potential surprise theory argues that<br />

‘‘decisions are b<strong>as</strong>ed upon a comparison ofimagination. Expectation is thought taking<br />

place in the present but having a content labelled with future dates’’ (1969, p. 14,<br />

italics in the original). That is, instead of calculating what will happen, Shackle argues<br />

that individuals imagine what c<strong>an</strong> happen. ‘‘Only potential surprise called up<br />

in the mind, <strong>an</strong>d <strong>as</strong>sessed, in the moment when decision is made, is relev<strong>an</strong>t for<br />

the decision, <strong>an</strong>d alone c<strong>an</strong> have <strong>an</strong>y bearing or influence on it’’ (1969, p. 69).<br />

Yet, he is fully aware of the role emotion plays within this new decision theory (Augier<br />

& Kreiner, 2000). Probability, he writes, ‘‘c<strong>an</strong>not discriminate or express degrees<br />

ofpossibility. Potential surprise is, precisely, the expression, in terms of feeling, of<br />

degree ofsurprise (1969, p. 76, italics are mine).<br />

Two <strong>as</strong>pects ofShackle’s theory are ofimport<strong>an</strong>ce: surprise <strong>an</strong>d imagination.<br />

First, surprise, <strong>as</strong> Or<strong>to</strong>ny et al. (1988, p. 32, 125–127) argue, is not <strong>an</strong> emotion<br />

but a cognitive state (see also, Ben-Ze’ev, 2000, p. 56). For example, <strong>an</strong> agent might<br />

be surprised <strong>to</strong> find that there are no penguins in Engl<strong>an</strong>d, yet remain indifferent <strong>to</strong><br />

such information. On the other h<strong>an</strong>d, imagination is relev<strong>an</strong>t both for generating<br />

emotion <strong>an</strong>d for making decisions. Ben-Ze’ev (2000, Chapter 7), for example, argues<br />

that imagination is a key fac<strong>to</strong>r in generating a specific emotion <strong>an</strong>d in the intensity<br />

ofthat emotion. Fear <strong>an</strong>d hope, he argues, ‘‘entail imagining a future alternative <strong>to</strong><br />

the present one’’ (p. 191; see also Elster, 1999, on counterwishful thinking in children’s<br />

play). The work done by Peter Earl on the relationship between imagination,<br />

creativity <strong>an</strong>d decision-making by individuals (Earl, 1983) <strong>an</strong>d in the corporate environment<br />

(Earl, 1984) illustrates how imagination c<strong>an</strong> <strong>as</strong>sist decision making processes,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d how rigidity (or lack ofimagination) c<strong>an</strong> hinder perform<strong>an</strong>ce.<br />

3 According <strong>to</strong> Matthews (1991), Keynes admired Hume who h<strong>as</strong> also used the term <strong>an</strong>imal spirit,<br />

though the idea of<strong>an</strong>imal spirit is probably taken from Descartes (p. 106).


14 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

The point is that the emotional values attached <strong>to</strong> the imagined future situation<br />

c<strong>an</strong> affect the decision taken in the present moment. Schwarz <strong>an</strong>d Clore (1983,<br />

1988) have constructed a ‘‘How do I feel about it?’’ heuristic, in which they argue<br />

that people inspect their feelings in order <strong>to</strong> evaluate targets. That is, individuals<br />

do not question the emotional state they are in (good or bad) at that moment,<br />

but rather the emotional responses <strong>to</strong> a future target of decision (e.g., how do I<br />

feel about Chinese food?). Imagined scenarios involving a strong negative emotional<br />

reaction such <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong>xiety might be excluded from further consideration, while<br />

positive ones will be more likely <strong>to</strong> be entertained (Isen & Geva, 1987; Isen & Patrick,<br />

1983). For example, in trying <strong>to</strong> decide how <strong>to</strong> invest money (or move <strong>to</strong> a<br />

new job), one imagines the various risks <strong>an</strong>d benefits attached <strong>to</strong> each option.<br />

If, for inst<strong>an</strong>ce, the agent feels intense fear due <strong>to</strong> the risks involved in one option,<br />

he or she might exclude this option, while choosing a safer line of investment (for a<br />

similar perspective see Earl, 1983, pp. 165–167; 175–180; Lopes, 1987).<br />

Pham (1998) h<strong>as</strong> found that peoples’ decisions <strong>to</strong> go <strong>to</strong> the movies were heavily<br />

b<strong>as</strong>ed on their emotional attitude <strong>to</strong>wards the target, i.e., the movie. As Pham writes<br />

‘‘looking at affect <strong>as</strong> a source ofinformation helps us underst<strong>an</strong>d how consumers c<strong>an</strong><br />

use their feeling <strong>to</strong> guide their decisions’’ (1998, p. 156). Consumers, according <strong>to</strong><br />

this view, hold representations oftargets in their mind <strong>an</strong>d use the feelings that these<br />

representations generate <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> additional source ofinformation in the decision making<br />

process. Further evidence c<strong>an</strong> be derived from research on phobic behavior,<br />

where the phobia (reluct<strong>an</strong>ce <strong>to</strong> fly, for example) stems from imagining the negative<br />

outcomes <strong>as</strong>sociated with flying. As Shackle h<strong>as</strong> argued ‘‘what is action but the response<br />

<strong>to</strong> feelings? What action would there be if there were no desires, no consciousness<br />

of dissatisfaction, no longing for ‘good state of mind’? What is motive, except<br />

emotion?’’ (1972, p. 135). He concludes by saying: ‘‘We chose, <strong>an</strong>d take, action is<br />

pursuit of<strong>an</strong> end. What is <strong>an</strong> end ifnot something upon which our desire concentrates<br />

our thought <strong>an</strong>d effort? ... Re<strong>as</strong>on, logic, are in themselves purely formal,<br />

without force’’ (ibid.).<br />

An<strong>to</strong>nio Dam<strong>as</strong>io (1994) in his book, Descartes’ Error, presents compelling data<br />

indicating that emotions are vital <strong>to</strong> decision making (but see Elster, 1999). His evidence<br />

stems from work with patients who have suffered damage <strong>to</strong> their frontal<br />

lobes. Due <strong>to</strong> this damage, these patients have become ‘‘emotionally flat’’, while retaining<br />

all oftheir cognitive abilities. They do, however, exhibit one particular flaw:<br />

they lose their decision-making abilities. In a series ofexperiments, they (Bachara,<br />

Dam<strong>as</strong>io, Dam<strong>as</strong>io, & Anderson, 1994; Bachara, Dam<strong>as</strong>io, Tr<strong>an</strong>el, & Dam<strong>as</strong>io,<br />

1997) show that individuals suffering from a lesion <strong>to</strong> their frontal lobe are incapable<br />

ofmaking decisions, <strong>an</strong>d that those they do make are generally faulty. The expl<strong>an</strong>ation<br />

provided by Dam<strong>as</strong>io is that these patients are insensitive <strong>to</strong> future consequences.<br />

They are concerned with the here <strong>an</strong>d now, not reflecting on the possible<br />

outcomes oftheir actions. Not being able <strong>to</strong> <strong>as</strong>sign emotional value <strong>to</strong> future<br />

outcomes renders these outcomes me<strong>an</strong>ingless. Accordingly, outcomes that carry<br />

no emotional value, apparently c<strong>an</strong>not be part ofthe equation.<br />

In a particular incident, one patient ruminated for half <strong>an</strong> hour over when <strong>to</strong> set<br />

his next appointment. During the deliberation process, he evaluated every imagin-


able parameter: from alternative appointments times <strong>to</strong> vari<strong>an</strong>ts in weather conditions.<br />

Dam<strong>as</strong>io beliefthat his patient would have continued deliberating the pros<br />

<strong>an</strong>d cons ofeach option ad infinitum, ifhe, Dam<strong>as</strong>io, had not intervened. This patient,<br />

like the others treated by Dam<strong>as</strong>io, illustrates the limits ofpure re<strong>as</strong>on. Without<br />

emotions, one could ruminate over trivial matters until one had exhausted all<br />

possibilities. One would not be able <strong>to</strong> form a prioritizing mech<strong>an</strong>ism.<br />

L<strong>an</strong>ger (1989, pp. 199–200), describing choosing a restaur<strong>an</strong>t, poses the same difficulties<br />

<strong>as</strong> Dam<strong>as</strong>io. Should she eat in a Chinese restaur<strong>an</strong>t, <strong>an</strong>d ifso, in which one?<br />

There are adv<strong>an</strong>tages <strong>to</strong> each of the restaur<strong>an</strong>ts she thinks of: food is better in one,<br />

atmosphere in the other, one is closer, the other less expensive. The SEU model, she<br />

argues, <strong>as</strong>sumes that it c<strong>an</strong> provide the right <strong>an</strong>swer, for the decision c<strong>an</strong> be<br />

grounded on rational deliberation. But generating more options does not help, for<br />

there is no rational s<strong>to</strong>pping rule, <strong>an</strong>d, therefore, she advocates a more intuitive processing.<br />

‘‘We c<strong>an</strong> then work on making the decision right rather th<strong>an</strong> obsess about<br />

making the right decision’’ (p. 200).<br />

6. <strong>Emotion</strong>s <strong>as</strong> a focusingmech<strong>an</strong>ism<br />

6.1. <strong>Emotion</strong> <strong>an</strong>d information<br />

Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 15<br />

In making a decision, <strong>as</strong> Simon (1983) h<strong>as</strong> argued, we rarely possess all the relev<strong>an</strong>t<br />

information, <strong>nor</strong> do we hold <strong>an</strong> exhaustive, detailed, picture of all possibilities<br />

<strong>an</strong>d their probabilities. Rather, we hold a general portrait ofour life, ofwhere we<br />

would like <strong>to</strong> be, <strong>an</strong>d ofthe resources available <strong>to</strong> us.<br />

For inst<strong>an</strong>ce, when we are about <strong>to</strong> purch<strong>as</strong>e a house we have a clear idea about<br />

our fin<strong>an</strong>cial resources, the area we would like <strong>to</strong> live in, preferred residential type,<br />

etc. (see, for example, Earl, 1986a, pp. 176–178; 202–203). We might have several<br />

other criteria in mind (e.g., the view from the living room, schools in the vicinity,<br />

or the proximity ofthe nearest hospital), though we are unlikely <strong>to</strong> contemplate a<br />

broad spectrum ofpossibilities that might affect our decision. When thinking about<br />

the house we would like <strong>to</strong> purch<strong>as</strong>e, we focus our attention on issues pertaining <strong>to</strong><br />

houses, not concerning ourselves with furniture. In other words, one focuses ones<br />

attention, or mental resources, on a limited set ofvariables <strong>an</strong>d among those entertained<br />

some will have a higher value th<strong>an</strong> others.<br />

When the author ofthis paper suggested <strong>to</strong> a friend that she should re-examine<br />

her decision <strong>to</strong> purch<strong>as</strong>e a house, after a leading Israeli newspaper claimed it w<strong>as</strong> less<br />

adv<strong>an</strong>tageous th<strong>an</strong> investing in the b<strong>an</strong>k, she insisted that it w<strong>as</strong> ofno interest <strong>to</strong> her.<br />

In fact, she w<strong>as</strong>n’t willing <strong>to</strong> consider (or hear) other options such <strong>as</strong> renting <strong>an</strong>d investing<br />

her money in a more profitable enterprise. Her main concern w<strong>as</strong> with feelings<br />

ofsecurity, that is, knowing that she owns the place, <strong>an</strong>d that no one c<strong>an</strong> take it<br />

away from her, or <strong>as</strong>k her <strong>to</strong> leave on short notice.<br />

The above example – though it should be taken with caution – h<strong>as</strong> two possible<br />

ramifications. First, it c<strong>an</strong> illustrate the point adv<strong>an</strong>ced by Earl (1983, 1986b, 1992)<br />

on how cognitive disson<strong>an</strong>ce (Festinger, 1957) <strong>an</strong>d personal construct theory (Kelly,


16 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

1967) c<strong>an</strong> be applied <strong>to</strong> the economic domain (see also Etzioni, 1988). And second,<br />

<strong>as</strong> Shiv <strong>an</strong>d Fedorikhin (1999) have argued, ‘‘ifaffective <strong>an</strong>d cognitive reactions have<br />

opposite valences, then they are likely <strong>to</strong> act in opposite directions (one promoting<br />

choice, the other promoting rejection)’’ (1999, p. 281). In the example given above,<br />

the reluct<strong>an</strong>ce <strong>to</strong> even consider other alternatives (such <strong>as</strong> renting) w<strong>as</strong> blocked due<br />

<strong>to</strong> emotional considerations, namely feeling of insecurity, which c<strong>an</strong> reduce the risk<br />

ofcognitive disson<strong>an</strong>ce.<br />

6.2. <strong>Emotion</strong>, uncertainty <strong>an</strong>d creativity<br />

The world we live in presents endless possibilities, options <strong>an</strong>d variables that, in<br />

theory, c<strong>an</strong> affect <strong>an</strong>y decision we make, but generally do not. In a sense, we are living<br />

in what Simon (1983) h<strong>as</strong> called <strong>an</strong> ‘‘empty world’’. In this ‘‘empty’’ world, we<br />

discriminate between variables; we choose <strong>to</strong> focus on some while neglecting others.<br />

L<strong>an</strong>ger (1989) h<strong>as</strong> termed this phenomenon ‘‘mindlessness.’’ She presents ample evidence<br />

suggesting that people see what they w<strong>an</strong>t <strong>to</strong> see, clouding their judgments in<br />

the process. She maintains that rational ‘‘fixation’’ c<strong>an</strong> lead <strong>to</strong> mental rigidity, preventing<br />

individuals from exploring possible alternatives, reaching favorable decisions,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d being creative. March (1971) adv<strong>an</strong>ced a similar line ofargument,<br />

criticizing rational choice theories for their inflexible <strong>as</strong>sumptions regarding preferences<br />

<strong>an</strong>d goals, for they confine our ability <strong>to</strong> generate new aims <strong>an</strong>d ch<strong>an</strong>ge our<br />

preference ordering. Play, according <strong>to</strong> March, ‘‘relaxes that insistence <strong>to</strong> allow us<br />

<strong>to</strong> act ‘unintelligently’ or ‘irrationally’, or ‘foolishly’ <strong>to</strong> explore alternative ide<strong>as</strong> of<br />

possible purposes <strong>an</strong>d alternative concepts ofbehavioral consistency ...while maintaining<br />

our b<strong>as</strong>ic commitment <strong>to</strong> the necessity ofintelligence’’ (March, 1971, p. 568).<br />

These authors argue, therefore, that we should allow foolishness, playfulness, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

intuition <strong>to</strong> gain a more prominent role in decisions making, problem-solving, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

creativity (L<strong>an</strong>ger, 1989, Chapter 7; March, 1971). Schumpeter, likewise, writes that<br />

under conditions ofuncertainty ‘‘the success ofeverything depends on intuition, the<br />

capacity ofseeing things in a way which afterwards proves <strong>to</strong> be true, even though it<br />

c<strong>an</strong>not be established at the moment’’ (Schumpeter, 1934, p. 85). Intuition, therefore,<br />

c<strong>an</strong> function <strong>as</strong> a heuristic mech<strong>an</strong>ism, allowing the agent <strong>to</strong> reach a decision<br />

b<strong>as</strong>ed on minimal amounts ofinformation. For example, Simon (1983, 25–27) describes<br />

how chess m<strong>as</strong>ters c<strong>an</strong> respond with a strong move (often the best one) after<br />

looking at the board for only 5–10 seconds.<br />

Let us examine one ofL<strong>an</strong>ger’s examples where the commitment <strong>to</strong> rational decision<br />

making, <strong>as</strong> advocated by SEU, is brought <strong>to</strong> the fore. One day L<strong>an</strong>ger arrived<br />

late <strong>to</strong> a meeting of a committee formed <strong>to</strong> award a prize for teaching. The committee<br />

faced a dilemma: there were five nominees but only three <strong>to</strong> five letters of recommendation<br />

for each. The problem w<strong>as</strong> how <strong>to</strong> make a sensible decision in light of the<br />

limited information before them. L<strong>an</strong>ger, realizing the problematic nature of information<br />

gathering, formulated a series of hypothetical questions designed <strong>to</strong> show<br />

that no amount of information would, in fact, be satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry, <strong>nor</strong> that they could<br />

agree on what information should be collected. Should they examine current students,<br />

or maybe those who finished the course two years ago? Should they <strong>as</strong>k poor


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 17<br />

students or excellent students? L<strong>an</strong>ger’s point w<strong>as</strong> that decision making could hardly<br />

ever be ‘‘b<strong>as</strong>ed on enough information’’ (p. 147). Instead of searching for all relev<strong>an</strong>t<br />

information, she suggested that a rule of thumb would be used.<br />

Given that in most c<strong>as</strong>es such <strong>as</strong> the one described by L<strong>an</strong>ger there are no absolutely<br />

right or absolutely wrong criteria <strong>to</strong> choose from, one might <strong>as</strong>k how we attach<br />

values <strong>to</strong> each criterion? One mech<strong>an</strong>ism that determines the saliency of<br />

variables is, we propose, our emotions.<br />

Dam<strong>as</strong>io suggest a similar line ofre<strong>as</strong>oning in which he argues the following:<br />

Imagine that before you apply <strong>an</strong>y kind of cost/benefit <strong>an</strong>alysis <strong>to</strong> the<br />

premises, <strong>an</strong>d before you re<strong>as</strong>on <strong>to</strong>ward the solution of the problem,<br />

something quite import<strong>an</strong>t happens: When the bad outcome connected<br />

with a given response option comes in<strong>to</strong> mind, however fleetingly, you experience<br />

<strong>an</strong> unple<strong>as</strong><strong>an</strong>t feeling. Because the feeling is about the body, I<br />

gave the phenomenon the technical term somatic state (‘‘soma’’ is Greek<br />

for body); <strong>an</strong>d because it ‘‘marks’’ <strong>an</strong> image, I called it a marker...What<br />

does the somatic marker achieve? It forces attention on the negative outcome<br />

<strong>to</strong> which a given action may lead, <strong>an</strong>d functions <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> au<strong>to</strong>mated<br />

alarm signal which says: Beware ofd<strong>an</strong>ger ahead ofyou ifyou choose<br />

the option which leads <strong>to</strong> this outcome. The signal may lead you <strong>to</strong> reject,<br />

immediately, the negative course ofaction <strong>an</strong>d thus make you choose<br />

among other alternatives (1994, p.174; italics in the original).<br />

Later on, Dam<strong>as</strong>io argues that:<br />

[S]omatic markers do not deliberate for us. They <strong>as</strong>sist the deliberation process<br />

by highlighting some options (either d<strong>an</strong>gerous or favorable), <strong>an</strong>d eliminating<br />

them rapidly from subsequent consideration. You may think of it <strong>as</strong><br />

a system for au<strong>to</strong>mated qualification of predictions, which acts, whether<br />

you w<strong>an</strong>t it or not, <strong>to</strong> evaluate the extremely diverse scenarios ofthe <strong>an</strong>ticipated<br />

future before you. Think of it <strong>as</strong> a b<strong>as</strong>ic bi<strong>as</strong>ing device (ibid.).<br />

Consider the following example. In deliberating whether <strong>to</strong> agree <strong>to</strong> Joe’s proposal<br />

ofmarriage, J<strong>an</strong>e h<strong>as</strong> m<strong>an</strong>y questions <strong>to</strong> consider (see also Gigerenzer &<br />

Todd, 1999, pp. 7–8). Is Joe the right one? Will he be a good father? Will he satisfy<br />

her psychological <strong>an</strong>d sexual needs? One c<strong>an</strong> e<strong>as</strong>ily come up with numerous additional<br />

questions, which will hamper <strong>an</strong>y system trying <strong>to</strong> figure out <strong>an</strong>swers <strong>to</strong><br />

these questions. J<strong>an</strong>e, obviously, c<strong>an</strong>not provide a definitive <strong>an</strong>swer <strong>to</strong> m<strong>an</strong>y of<br />

the potential questions. She must make a choice by deliberating on a few, maybe<br />

a minimal set, ofquestions. She must decide which parameters are ofimport<strong>an</strong>ce<br />

<strong>to</strong> her, <strong>an</strong>d which c<strong>an</strong> be ig<strong>nor</strong>ed. But how does the system m<strong>an</strong>age <strong>to</strong> reduce the<br />

number ofquestions <strong>as</strong>ked? (e.g., is providing psychological <strong>an</strong>d sexual needs more<br />

import<strong>an</strong>t th<strong>an</strong> being a good father?) In other words, what is the mech<strong>an</strong>ism by<br />

which the system reduces its load, so that it c<strong>an</strong> both function <strong>an</strong>d provide me<strong>an</strong>ingful<br />

<strong>an</strong>swers?<br />

Since there are no right or wrong <strong>an</strong>swers <strong>to</strong> the question ofwhich parameters are<br />

more import<strong>an</strong>t – one might w<strong>an</strong>t money, the other babies – one way in which we


18 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

generate a value system is via our emotions. 4 Etzioni, for example, offers a Normative/Affective<br />

theory ofdecision making in which emotions play precisely that role.<br />

He says that:<br />

the majority ofchoices people make, including economic ones, are completely<br />

or largely b<strong>as</strong>ed on <strong>nor</strong>mative-affective considerations not merely<br />

with regard <strong>to</strong> selection ofgoals but also ofme<strong>an</strong>s, <strong>an</strong>d that the limited<br />

zones in which other, logical empirical (L/E), considerations are paramount,<br />

are themselves defined by N/A fac<strong>to</strong>rs that legitimate <strong>an</strong>d otherwise<br />

motivate such decision-making (1988, p. 126).<br />

Without emotions <strong>to</strong> generate both values <strong>an</strong>d preferences, re<strong>as</strong>on – <strong>as</strong> shown by<br />

Dam<strong>as</strong>io’s patients – is <strong>an</strong> arbitrary mech<strong>an</strong>ism lost in a sea oftheoretical possibilities<br />

<strong>an</strong>d consequences. Intellectual re<strong>as</strong>oning without emotions, then, seems <strong>to</strong> be next <strong>to</strong><br />

impossible (Charl<strong>an</strong>d, 1998). That is why De Sousa (1996, p. 331) argues that ‘‘without<br />

the ability <strong>to</strong> care about the [future or hypothetical] situations evoked by the re<strong>as</strong>oning,<br />

the values involved never get <strong>to</strong> move the agent in accord with his ‘knowledge’ ’’.<br />

Similar ide<strong>as</strong> are expressed in the research conducted by Isen <strong>an</strong>d her colleagues<br />

(Isen & Levin, 1972; Isen, Shalker, Clark, & Karp, 1978; Isen, Me<strong>an</strong>s, Patrick, & Nowicki,<br />

1982). She argues, for example, that good mood facilitates problem-solving in several<br />

ways. It ‘‘reduces the load on working memory: <strong>to</strong> reduce the complexity of<br />

decision situations <strong>an</strong>d the difficulty oft<strong>as</strong>ks, by adopting the simplest strategy possible,<br />

considering the fewest number of alternatives possible, <strong>an</strong>d doing little or no checking<br />

ofinformation, hypotheses, <strong>an</strong>d tentative conclusions’’ (Isen et al., 1982, p. 258).<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong>s, by attaching values <strong>to</strong> each variable, restrict the r<strong>an</strong>ge ofoptions entertained.<br />

Parameters receiving low emotional values are ig<strong>nor</strong>ed, for they have no<br />

(or less) signific<strong>an</strong>ce for the evalua<strong>to</strong>r, while parameters receiving high emotional<br />

values are brought <strong>to</strong> the front of our attention. Those, <strong>an</strong>d only those, variables<br />

which reach the final round are inserted in<strong>to</strong> the equation.<br />

Etzioni (1988) considers the question ofhow we decide what <strong>to</strong> eat for dinner. The<br />

typical Americ<strong>an</strong> teenager will chose hamburger over snails 5 every day, since she<br />

4 Gigerenzer <strong>an</strong>d Todd (1999) adv<strong>an</strong>ce a slightly different expl<strong>an</strong>ation. They propose that love serves ‘‘<strong>as</strong><br />

a powerful s<strong>to</strong>pping rule that ends the current search for a partner’’ (p. 31). In other words, falling in love<br />

serves <strong>as</strong> a sufficient condition <strong>to</strong> committing oneself. One needs not evaluate the entire spectrum of<br />

options or conduct a cost–benefit <strong>an</strong>alysis. One only needs a single cue: <strong>to</strong> fall in love.<br />

5 That is, unless the individual is a vegetari<strong>an</strong>. People decision <strong>to</strong> adopt a vegetari<strong>an</strong> diet poses <strong>an</strong>other<br />

difficulty for SEU theory. Research by Beardsworth <strong>an</strong>d Keil’s (1992) show how prior <strong>to</strong> shifting in<strong>to</strong> a<br />

vegetari<strong>an</strong> diet, individuals lack a definite knowledge in several domains. Individuals are not sure how<br />

family, friends, <strong>an</strong>d co-workers will react (some are hostile while others welcome the dietary ch<strong>an</strong>ge), how<br />

<strong>to</strong> deal with criticism (e.g., how come you are wearing leather shows?), <strong>an</strong>d what <strong>to</strong> have for dinner. Their<br />

findings indicate that this lack ofknowledge is responsible, at le<strong>as</strong>t partially, for the gradual conversion<br />

patterns. Furthermore, conversion in<strong>to</strong> vegetari<strong>an</strong>ism varies from moral beliefs (cruelty <strong>to</strong> <strong>an</strong>imals),<br />

nutritional beliefs (meat is bad for you), <strong>to</strong>o social fac<strong>to</strong>rs (their spouse made the ch<strong>an</strong>ge). In either c<strong>as</strong>e,<br />

rational deliberation w<strong>as</strong> not a major influencing force. In their concluding remark, the authors argue that<br />

‘‘the adoption ofvegetari<strong>an</strong>ism, in whatever form is appropriate <strong>to</strong> each individual’s unique concern <strong>an</strong>d<br />

predicament, would seem <strong>to</strong> be at root <strong>an</strong> exercise in the m<strong>an</strong>agement of<strong>an</strong>xiety’’ (Beardsworth & Keil,<br />

1992, p. 290; see also, Kalof, Dietz, Stern, & Guagn<strong>an</strong>o, 1999).


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 19<br />

loves hamburgers, while snails are disgusting. We would expect a French teenager <strong>to</strong><br />

make a different selection. Similar logic, Etzioni argues, c<strong>an</strong> explain why Americ<strong>an</strong>s<br />

choose <strong>to</strong> work in the US, <strong>an</strong>d not, for example, in C<strong>an</strong>ada. Wages <strong>an</strong>d tax rates are<br />

not the only parameters entering in<strong>to</strong> the equation; patriotism may also be a fac<strong>to</strong>r.<br />

Our choice, in these c<strong>as</strong>es, is restricted by emotional evaluation: high emotional<br />

r<strong>an</strong>king me<strong>an</strong>s a possibility, while low emotional r<strong>an</strong>king is not considered. Our<br />

Americ<strong>an</strong> teenager does not have <strong>to</strong> ‘‘think’’ about all the possible foods available<br />

<strong>to</strong> her. She only h<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> think about the food she loves. It does not matter how m<strong>an</strong>y<br />

rational arguments one offers Americ<strong>an</strong> children regarding the merits ofspinach <strong>an</strong>d<br />

broccoli. They are unlikely <strong>to</strong> replace hamburgers from the <strong>to</strong>p of their list.<br />

Ritzer (1993), following Max Weber’s work on formal <strong>rationality</strong>, adds a sociological<br />

perspective. In his book, The McDonaldization of Society, he <strong>an</strong>alyses a diverse<br />

spectrum of Americ<strong>an</strong> institutions: universities, f<strong>as</strong>t-food chains, the<br />

au<strong>to</strong>mobile industry, hospitals, b<strong>an</strong>ks, amusement parks, etc. He shows that their<br />

commitment <strong>to</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> in the form of efficiency, predictability, <strong>an</strong>d qu<strong>an</strong>tifiable<br />

me<strong>as</strong>ures h<strong>as</strong> had dire consequences.<br />

Firstly, it dehum<strong>an</strong>izes workers <strong>an</strong>d cus<strong>to</strong>mers alike. The <strong>as</strong>sembly line presents a<br />

clear notion of the conditions in which f<strong>as</strong>t food <strong>an</strong>d car m<strong>an</strong>ufacture employees<br />

work; <strong>an</strong>d produces, therefore, the sense of alienation that exists in such work environments.<br />

The feeling of alienation leads, among other things, <strong>to</strong> high employee<br />

turnover (the typical worker in a f<strong>as</strong>t food restaur<strong>an</strong>t l<strong>as</strong>ts only four months), workers’<br />

retaliation, <strong>an</strong>d low productivity levels. Feelings ofalienation are not restricted<br />

<strong>to</strong> those who work on the <strong>as</strong>sembly line. Carr (1994) reports similar findings, where<br />

m<strong>an</strong>agement pressure <strong>to</strong> incre<strong>as</strong>e productivity <strong>an</strong>d efficiency (in the name of<strong>rationality</strong>)<br />

in the education sec<strong>to</strong>r in Australia, h<strong>as</strong> led <strong>to</strong> ‘‘emotional fallout’’. This<br />

‘‘emotional fallout’’ included <strong>an</strong> array of symp<strong>to</strong>ms such <strong>as</strong> high levels of <strong>an</strong>xiety,<br />

stress, <strong>an</strong>d depression.<br />

The second point argued by Ritzer is that commitment <strong>to</strong> <strong>rationality</strong> c<strong>an</strong> lead <strong>to</strong><br />

irrational behavior. Rationality, in the form advocated <strong>an</strong>d exercised by the McDonaldization<br />

process, often leads <strong>to</strong> ‘‘inefficiency, unpredictability, incalculability, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

loss ofcontrol’’ (1993, p. 121). Ritzer illustrates that the ‘‘promise’’ ofspeed, efficiency,<br />

cheapness, <strong>an</strong>d controllability is often <strong>an</strong> illusion rather th<strong>an</strong> a reality, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

that cold, calculated <strong>rationality</strong> c<strong>an</strong> lead <strong>to</strong> dis<strong>as</strong>trous consequences. In one wellknown<br />

c<strong>as</strong>e, the au<strong>to</strong> m<strong>an</strong>ufacture’s Ford rushed the production of the Pin<strong>to</strong> because<br />

of competition from small foreign car m<strong>an</strong>ufactures, ‘‘despite the fact that production<br />

tests had indicated that its fuel system would rupture e<strong>as</strong>ily in a rear-end collision’’ (p.<br />

144). Since the <strong>as</strong>sembly-line machinery w<strong>as</strong> already in place, they decided <strong>to</strong> go<br />

ahead <strong>an</strong>d produce the car without the safety alterations. Ford’s decision w<strong>as</strong> b<strong>as</strong>ed<br />

on a qu<strong>an</strong>titative comparison between fixing the defective fuel system <strong>an</strong>d the lives<br />

that would be lost. ‘‘They estimated that the defects would lead <strong>to</strong> 180 deaths <strong>an</strong>d<br />

about the same number ofinjuries. Placing a value, or rather a cost, <strong>to</strong> them of<br />

$200,000 per person, Ford decided that the <strong>to</strong>tal cost from these deaths <strong>an</strong>d injuries<br />

would be less th<strong>an</strong> the $11 per car it would cost <strong>to</strong> repair the defect’’ (ibid.).<br />

Macleod (1996) offers a similar idea <strong>to</strong> the one suggested by Etzioni’s. Macleod<br />

maintains that in the morning, when deciding what <strong>to</strong> wear, we seldom ifever evaluate


20 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

the entire spectrum ofdress options. We eliminate rather quickly m<strong>an</strong>y ofthe alternatives<br />

available <strong>to</strong> us <strong>an</strong>d pick the ones that ‘‘look right.’’ Otherwise, dressing in the<br />

morning would be a close <strong>to</strong> impossible t<strong>as</strong>k, taking us days <strong>to</strong> decide what <strong>to</strong> wear.<br />

What Macleod suggests, we <strong>as</strong>sume, is that the ‘‘look right’’ criterion c<strong>an</strong> be viewed<br />

<strong>as</strong> a satisficing mech<strong>an</strong>ism. It is one kind ofa s<strong>to</strong>pping rule, indicating <strong>to</strong> the decision<br />

maker that article A is satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry, hence there is no need <strong>to</strong> further evaluate other<br />

dress options.<br />

Rook’s (1985) work on ritual behavior provides additional support. In his study,<br />

where hair care activities figure prominently (on hairstyle choice, see also Parsons,<br />

2000, p. 143), subjects’ grooming behavior w<strong>as</strong> examined. His findings indicates, that<br />

while respondents were most satisfied with their hair (compared <strong>to</strong> other body parts),<br />

fixing one’s hair w<strong>as</strong> the most frustrating activity (p. 259). The discrep<strong>an</strong>cy between<br />

his subjects’ responses is indicative ofthe emotional import<strong>an</strong>ce attached <strong>to</strong> one’s<br />

hair. For young adults, grooming is more th<strong>an</strong> just a cle<strong>an</strong>ing procedure. It reflects<br />

on their identity <strong>as</strong> determined by peer pressure <strong>an</strong>d the need <strong>to</strong> look just right. In<br />

fact, when subjects were <strong>as</strong>ked <strong>to</strong> write creative s<strong>to</strong>ries about two pictures, most<br />

ofthe s<strong>to</strong>ries were loaded with emotional (good <strong>an</strong>d bad) connotations, yet reflected<br />

little rational deliberation. Drawing from Erikson’s work – which interprets ritual<br />

behavior <strong>as</strong> stemming from, among other things, feeling of shame, guilt, inferiority,<br />

confusion <strong>an</strong>d isolation – Rook concludes that grooming behavior ‘‘contr<strong>as</strong>ts<br />

sharply with the various static <strong>an</strong>d naive behavioral models that depict consumers<br />

<strong>as</strong> rational <strong>an</strong>d constructive attribute maximizers’’ (1985, p. 262).<br />

One should note that the suggestions by Etzioni <strong>an</strong>d Macleod adopted here are<br />

not intended <strong>to</strong> reflect probabilities but matters oft<strong>as</strong>te <strong>an</strong>d emotional preference.<br />

The possibilities contemplated are not <strong>to</strong> be unders<strong>to</strong>od <strong>as</strong> having higher probabilities.<br />

Ifthe menu contains both hamburger <strong>an</strong>d broccoli or one’s wardrobe contains<br />

both yellow <strong>an</strong>d black shirts, both options are <strong>as</strong> probable. We do not me<strong>an</strong> that the<br />

decision making h<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> compute the probabilities oftheir occurrence, rather that<br />

r<strong>an</strong>king should be unders<strong>to</strong>od <strong>as</strong> reflecting the agent’s subjective emotional evaluation.<br />

In other words, emotions do not compute probabilities, re<strong>as</strong>on does.<br />

That is not <strong>to</strong> say that parameters with low emotional values are ofno import<strong>an</strong>ce.<br />

The import<strong>an</strong>ce attached <strong>to</strong> each stimulus is, by it’s nature, a subjective not<br />

<strong>an</strong> objective one – which is one re<strong>as</strong>on why emotions have been viewed <strong>as</strong> irrational.<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong>s create a personal <strong>an</strong>d subjective set ofvalues that differ from one person <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>an</strong>other. Furthermore, at certain times, negative emotional reactions c<strong>an</strong> be overcome<br />

<strong>an</strong>d choices made contrary <strong>to</strong> emotional evaluation.<br />

7. Conclusion<br />

‘‘In order <strong>to</strong> have a complete theory ofhum<strong>an</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>, we have <strong>to</strong> underst<strong>an</strong>d<br />

the role emotion plays in it’’ (Simon, 1983, p. 29). Not m<strong>an</strong>y economists have p<strong>aid</strong><br />

enough attention <strong>to</strong> the above <strong>as</strong>sertion. In fact, it seems <strong>as</strong> if m<strong>an</strong>y have completely<br />

ig<strong>nor</strong>ed it. The general tendency <strong>to</strong> focus on cognitive abilities <strong>an</strong>d functions <strong>an</strong>d <strong>to</strong><br />

ig<strong>nor</strong>e the played role by emotion h<strong>as</strong> given us a one-sided picture. In this paper I


have tried <strong>to</strong> make the first steps <strong>to</strong>wards integrating emotion in<strong>to</strong> the field of<br />

<strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>. By arguing that our emotional mech<strong>an</strong>ism processes information<br />

along with rational thinking, I suggest that it <strong>aid</strong>s mental deliberation in two<br />

ways. This is not <strong>to</strong> argue that emotions are necessarily involved in all ofthe cognitive<br />

functioning. It is possible <strong>to</strong> remember, imagine, <strong>an</strong>d make calculations without<br />

<strong>an</strong>y emotional involvement. The condition under which there is positive <strong>an</strong>d/or negative<br />

‘‘co-operation’’ between mental deliberation <strong>an</strong>d emotions remain <strong>to</strong> be empirically<br />

investigated. What seems <strong>to</strong> be the c<strong>as</strong>e thus far is that emotions play a vital<br />

role in supplementing our limited computational abilities. Further evidence might<br />

suggest that the role emotions play in decision making, for example, is much more<br />

signific<strong>an</strong>t th<strong>an</strong> h<strong>as</strong> previously been acknowledged.<br />

Finally, ifThaler’s prediction is correct, ‘‘that economists will devote more attention<br />

<strong>to</strong> the study of emotions’’ (cf. Thaler, 2000, p. 139), th<strong>an</strong> economists must familiarize<br />

themselves with psychological, neurological <strong>an</strong>d philosophical research<br />

on emotion. This is one area where, by utilizing existing research <strong>an</strong>d findings, economists<br />

c<strong>an</strong> economize.<br />

Acknowledgements<br />

I wish <strong>to</strong> th<strong>an</strong>k Aaron Ben-Ze’ev, Peter Earl, Joe Nugent, Ofer Rab<strong>an</strong>, <strong>an</strong>d two<br />

<strong>an</strong>onymous reviewers for critical comments <strong>an</strong>d helpful suggestions.<br />

References<br />

Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 21<br />

Arnold, E. J., & Price, L. L. (1993). River magic: Extraordinary experience <strong>an</strong>d extended service<br />

encounter. Journal of Consumer Research, 20, 24–45.<br />

Arrow, K. J. (1992). Rationality ofself<strong>an</strong>d others in <strong>an</strong> economic system. In M. Zey (Ed.), Decision<br />

making: Alternatives <strong>to</strong> rational choice models (pp. 63–77). Newbury Park: Sage.<br />

Augier, M., & Kreiner, K. (2000). Rationality, imagination <strong>an</strong>d intelligence: Some boundaries in hum<strong>an</strong><br />

decision-making. Industrial <strong>an</strong>d Corporate Ch<strong>an</strong>ge, 9, 659–681.<br />

Bachara, A., Dam<strong>as</strong>io, A. R., Dam<strong>as</strong>io, H., & Anderson, S. (1994). Insensitivity <strong>to</strong> future consequences<br />

following damage <strong>to</strong> hum<strong>an</strong> prefrontal cortex. Cognition, 50, 7–12.<br />

Bachara, A., Dam<strong>as</strong>io, A., Tr<strong>an</strong>el, D., & Dam<strong>as</strong>io, A. R. (1997). Deciding adv<strong>an</strong>tageously before knowing<br />

the adv<strong>an</strong>tageous strategy. Science, 275, 1293–1295.<br />

Beardsworth, A., & Keil, T. (1992). The vegetari<strong>an</strong> option: Varieties, conversions, motives <strong>an</strong>d careers.<br />

The Sociological Review, 40, 253–293.<br />

Ben-Ze’ev, A. (2000). The subtlety of the emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Berger, L. A. (1989). Economics <strong>an</strong>d hermeneutics. Economics <strong>an</strong>d Philosophy, 5, 209–233.<br />

Berkowitz, L. (1993). Towards a general theory of<strong>an</strong>ger <strong>an</strong>d emotional aggression: Implications ofthe<br />

cognitive neo<strong>as</strong>sociationistic perspective for the <strong>an</strong>alysis of <strong>an</strong>ger <strong>an</strong>d other emotions. In R. S. Wyer, &<br />

T. K. Srull (Eds.), Adv<strong>an</strong>ces in social cognition (pp. 1–46). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.<br />

Brown, H. I. (1978). On being rational. Americ<strong>an</strong> Philosophical Quarterly, 14, 241–248.<br />

Carr, A. N. (1994). The ‘‘emotional fallout’’ of the new efficiency movement in public administration in<br />

Australia: A c<strong>as</strong>e study. Administration <strong>an</strong>d Society, 26, 344–358.<br />

Celsi, R. L., Rose, R. L., & Leigh, T. W. (1993). An exploration ofhigh-risk leisure consumption through<br />

skydiving. Journal of Consumer Research, 20, 1–23.


22 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

Charl<strong>an</strong>d, L. C. (1998). Is Mr. Spock mentally competent? Competence <strong>to</strong> consent <strong>an</strong>d emotion.<br />

Philosophy, Psychiatry <strong>an</strong>d Psychology, 5, 67–81.<br />

Conlisk, J. (1996). Why <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>? Journal of Economic Literature, 34, 669–700.<br />

Dam<strong>as</strong>io, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: <strong>Emotion</strong>, re<strong>as</strong>on, <strong>an</strong>d the hum<strong>an</strong> brain. New York: Putnam.<br />

Darwin, C. (1965). The expression of the emotion in m<strong>an</strong> <strong>an</strong>d <strong>an</strong>imals (1872). Chicago: University of<br />

Chicago Press.<br />

Davis, C. R. (1996). The administrative rational model <strong>an</strong>d public org<strong>an</strong>izational theory. Administration<br />

<strong>an</strong>d Society, 28, 39–60.<br />

Dennard, L. F. (1995). Neo-Darwinism <strong>an</strong>d Simon’s bureaucratic <strong>an</strong>tihero. Administration <strong>an</strong>d Society,<br />

26, 464–487.<br />

Dennett, D. C. (1987). Cognitive wheels: The frame problem in AI. In Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.), The Robot’s<br />

dilemma: The frame problem <strong>an</strong>d other problems of holism in artificial intelligence. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.<br />

De Sousa, R. (1987). The <strong>rationality</strong> of emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

De Sousa, R. (1996). A review ofDescartes’ Error: <strong>Emotion</strong>, re<strong>as</strong>on <strong>an</strong>d the hum<strong>an</strong> brain. Cognition <strong>an</strong>d<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong>, 10, 329–333.<br />

Earl, P. (1983). The economic imagination: Towards a behavioral theory of choice. Brigh<strong>to</strong>n: Wheatsheaf.<br />

Earl, P. (1984). The corporate imagination: Howbig comp<strong>an</strong>ies make mistakes. Brigh<strong>to</strong>n: Wheatsheaf.<br />

Earl, P. (1986a). Lifestyle economics: Consumer behavior in a turbulent world. Brigh<strong>to</strong>n: Wheatsheaf.<br />

Earl, P. (1986b). A behavioral <strong>an</strong>alysis ofdem<strong>an</strong>d el<strong>as</strong>ticities. Journal of Economic Studies, 13, 20–37.<br />

Earl, P. (1990). Economics <strong>an</strong>d psychology: A survey. The Economic Journal, 100, 718–755.<br />

Earl, P. (1992). On the complementarity ofeconomic applications ofcognitive disson<strong>an</strong>ce theory <strong>an</strong>d<br />

personal construct psychology. In S. E. G. Lea, P. Webley, & B. M. Young (Eds.), Newdirections in<br />

economic psychology: Theory, experiment <strong>an</strong>d application (pp. 49–65). H<strong>an</strong>ts: Edward Elgar.<br />

Earl, P. (2001). The legacy of Herbert A. Simon in economic <strong>an</strong>alysis’ (Vol. 2). Cheltenhma: Edward Elgar.<br />

Ekm<strong>an</strong>, P. (1992). An argument for b<strong>as</strong>ic emotions. Cognition <strong>an</strong>d <strong>Emotion</strong>, 6, 169–200.<br />

Ekm<strong>an</strong>, P. (1999). B<strong>as</strong>ic <strong>Emotion</strong>s. In T. Dalgleish, & M. J. Power (Eds.), H<strong>an</strong>dbook of cognition <strong>an</strong>d<br />

emotion (pp. 45–60). Chichester: Wiley.<br />

Ekm<strong>an</strong>, P., & Davidson, R. (1994). The nature of emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Elster, J. (1984). Ulysses <strong>an</strong>d the sirens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Elster, J. (1998). <strong>Emotion</strong>s <strong>an</strong>d economic theory. Journal of Economic Literature, 36, 47–74.<br />

Elster, J. (1999). Alchemies of the mind: Rationality <strong>an</strong>d the emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Etzioni, A. (1988). Normative–affective fac<strong>to</strong>rs: Toward a new decision-making modal. Journal of<br />

Economic Psychology, 9, 125–150.<br />

Etzioni, A. (1992). Socio-economics: Select policy implications. In S. E. G. Lea, P. Webley, & B. M.<br />

Young (Eds.), Newdirections in economic psychology: Theory experiment <strong>an</strong>d application (pp. 13–27).<br />

H<strong>an</strong>ts: Edward Elgar.<br />

Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive disson<strong>an</strong>ce. St<strong>an</strong>ford: St<strong>an</strong>ford University Press.<br />

Fr<strong>an</strong>k, R. (1988). P<strong>as</strong>sions within re<strong>as</strong>on. New York: Nor<strong>to</strong>n.<br />

Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Gigerenzer, G., The ABC Research Group & Todd, M. P. (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart.<br />

New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are. Chicago: University ofChicago Press.<br />

Hare, R. M. (1963). Freedom <strong>an</strong>d re<strong>as</strong>on. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Heiner, R. A. (1983). The origin ofpredictable behavior. Americ<strong>an</strong> Economic Review, 73, 560–595.<br />

Heiner, R. A. (1986). The economics of information when decision are imperfect. In A. J. MacFadyen, &<br />

H. W. MacFadyen (Eds.), Economic psychology: Intersections in theory <strong>an</strong>d application (pp. 293–350).<br />

Amsterdam: Elsevier.<br />

Hollins, M., & Nell, E. J. (1975). Rational economic m<strong>an</strong>: A philosophical critique of neo-cl<strong>as</strong>sical<br />

economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Hume, D. (1978). A treatise on hum<strong>an</strong> nature (1740). Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Isen, M. A., & Patrick, R. (1983). The effect ofpositive feelings on risk taking: When the chips are down.<br />

Org<strong>an</strong>izational Behavior <strong>an</strong>d Hum<strong>an</strong> Decision Process, 31, 194–202.


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 23<br />

Isen, M. A., & Geva, N. (1987). The influence ofpositive effect on acceptable level ofrisk: The person with<br />

a large c<strong>an</strong>oe h<strong>as</strong> a large worry. Org<strong>an</strong>izational Behavior <strong>an</strong>d Hum<strong>an</strong> Decision Process, 39, 145–154.<br />

Isen, M. A., & Levin, P. F. (1972). The effects offeeling good on helping: Cookies <strong>an</strong>d kindness. Journal of<br />

Personality <strong>an</strong>d Social Psychology, 21, 384–388.<br />

Isen, M. A., Me<strong>an</strong>s, B., Patrick, R., & Nowicki, G. (1982). Some fac<strong>to</strong>rs influencing decision-making<br />

strategy <strong>an</strong>d risk taking. In M. S. Clark, & S. Fiske (Eds.), Affect <strong>an</strong>d cognition (pp. 243–261). Hillsdale,<br />

NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.<br />

Isen, M. A., Shalker, T. E., Clark, M., & Karp, L. (1978). Affect, accessibility ofmaterial in memory, <strong>an</strong>d<br />

behavior: A cognitive loop? Journal of Personality <strong>an</strong>d Social Psychology, 36, 1–12.<br />

Izard, C. A. (1977). Hum<strong>an</strong> emotions. New York: Plenum Press.<br />

Jauregui, J. A. (1995). The emotional computer. Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Kalof, L., Dietz, T., Stern, P. C., & Guagn<strong>an</strong>o, G. A. (1999). Social psychological <strong>an</strong>d structural influences<br />

on vegetari<strong>an</strong> beliefs. Rural Sociology, 64, 500–511.<br />

Kaufm<strong>an</strong>, B. E. (1999). <strong>Emotion</strong>al arousal <strong>as</strong> a source of <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>. Journal of Economic<br />

Behavior <strong>an</strong>d Org<strong>an</strong>ization, 38, 135–144.<br />

Kelly, H. H. (1967). Attribution theory in social psychology. In D. Levine (Ed.), Nebr<strong>as</strong>ka symposium on<br />

motivation (pp. 192–241). Lincoln, NE: University ofNebr<strong>as</strong>ka Press.<br />

Keynes, J. M. (1936). The general theory of employment, interest <strong>an</strong>d money. London: Macmill<strong>an</strong> Press<br />

(References are <strong>to</strong> Vol. VII ofthe Collected Writings ofJohn Maynard Keynes).<br />

L<strong>an</strong>ger, E. J. (1989). Mindfulness. Reading, MA: Merloyd Lawrence.<br />

Lazarus, R. S. (1991). <strong>Emotion</strong> <strong>an</strong>d adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

LeDoux, J. (1994). <strong>Emotion</strong>, memory <strong>an</strong>d the brain. Scientific Americ<strong>an</strong>, 270, 32–39.<br />

LeDoux, J. (1996). The emotional brain. New York: Simon <strong>an</strong>d Schuster.<br />

Leeper, R. W. (1948). A motivational theory ofemotion <strong>to</strong> replace ‘‘emotion <strong>as</strong> disorg<strong>an</strong>ize response’’.<br />

Psychological Review, 44, 2–21.<br />

Levi, I. (1997). The coven<strong>an</strong>t of re<strong>as</strong>on. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Levine, D. S., & Leven, S. J. (1992). Preface. In D. S. Levine, & S. J. Leven (Eds.), Motivation, emotion,<br />

<strong>an</strong>d goal direction in neural network (pp. vii–xvi). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.<br />

Lewin, S. B. (1996). Economics <strong>an</strong>d psychology: lessons for our own day from the early twentieth century.<br />

Journal of Economic Literature, 34, 1293–1323.<br />

Lipm<strong>an</strong>, B. L. (1991). How <strong>to</strong> decide how <strong>to</strong> decide how <strong>to</strong>...: Modeling limited <strong>rationality</strong>. Econometrica,<br />

59, 1105–1125.<br />

Loewenstein, G. (2000). <strong>Emotion</strong>s in economic theory <strong>an</strong>d economic behavior. The Americ<strong>an</strong> Economic<br />

Review, 90, 426–432.<br />

Lopes, L. L. (1987). Between hope <strong>an</strong>d fear: The psychology of risk. Adv<strong>an</strong>ces in Experimental Psychology,<br />

24, 255–295.<br />

Lyons, W. (1980). <strong>Emotion</strong>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Macleod, B. W. (1996). Decision, contract, <strong>an</strong>d emotion: Some economics for a complex <strong>an</strong>d confusing<br />

world. C<strong>an</strong>adi<strong>an</strong> Journal of Economics, 4, 788–810.<br />

March, J. M. (1971). The technology offoolishness. In J. G. March (Ed.), The pursuit of org<strong>an</strong>izational<br />

intelligence (1988). B<strong>as</strong>il Blackwell: Oxford.<br />

March, J. M. (1978). Bounded <strong>rationality</strong>, ambiguity, <strong>an</strong>d the engineering ofchoice. The Bell Journal of<br />

Economics, 9, 587–608.<br />

March, J. M. (1982). Theories ofchoice <strong>an</strong>d making decisions. Society, 20, 29–39.<br />

March, J. M. (1994). A primer on decision making. New York: The Free Press.<br />

Marchionatti, R. (1999). On Keynes’ <strong>an</strong>imal spirits. Kyklos, 52, 415–439.<br />

Matthews, R. (1991). Animal Spirits. In T. G. J. Meeks (Ed.), Thoughtful economic m<strong>an</strong>: Essays on<br />

<strong>rationality</strong>, moral rules <strong>an</strong>d benevolence (pp. 103–125). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Oatley, K. (1992). Best l<strong>aid</strong> schemes: The psychology of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Oatley, K., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1987). Towards a cognitive theory ofemotions. Cognition <strong>an</strong>d<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong>, 1, 29–50.<br />

Or<strong>to</strong>ny, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.


24 Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25<br />

P<strong>an</strong>ksepp, J. (1982). Towards a general psychological theory ofemotion. Behavioral <strong>an</strong>d Brain Science, 5,<br />

407–467.<br />

P<strong>an</strong>ksepp, J. (1996). Affective neuroscience: a paradigm <strong>to</strong> study the <strong>an</strong>imate circuits ofhum<strong>an</strong> emotion.<br />

In R. Kav<strong>an</strong>augh, B. Zimmerberg, & S. Fein (Eds.), <strong>Emotion</strong>: Interdisciplinary perspective (pp. 29–60).<br />

Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.<br />

Parsons, S. D. (2000). Shackle <strong>an</strong>d the project ofthe Enlightenment: Re<strong>as</strong>on, time <strong>an</strong>d imagination. In P.<br />

E. Earl, & S. F. Frowen (Eds.), Economics <strong>as</strong> <strong>an</strong> art of thought: Essays in memory of GLS shackle (pp.<br />

124–148). London: Routledge.<br />

Pham, M. T. (1998). Representativeness, relev<strong>an</strong>ce, <strong>an</strong>d the use offeelings in decision making. Journal of<br />

Consumer Research, 25, 144–159.<br />

Picard, S. (1997). Affective computing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Pieters, R. G. M., & v<strong>an</strong> Raaij, W. F. (1988). The role ofaffect in economic behavior. In R. G. M. Pieters,<br />

& W. F. v<strong>an</strong> Raaij (Eds.), H<strong>an</strong>dbook of economic psychology (pp. 109–142). Netherl<strong>an</strong>ds: Kluwer<br />

Academic Publishers.<br />

Plutchik, R. (1980). A psychoevolutionary synthesis. New York: Harper & Row.<br />

Popper, K. (1962). Conjectures <strong>an</strong>d refutations. London: Routledge & Keg<strong>an</strong> Paul.<br />

Rabin, M. (1998). Psychology <strong>an</strong>d economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 36, 11–46.<br />

Radner, R. (1975). Satisficing. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 2, 153–162.<br />

Ritzer, G. (1993). The McDonaldization of society. California: Pine Forge Press.<br />

Robbins, L. (1984). An essay on the nature <strong>an</strong>d signific<strong>an</strong>ce of economic science. London: Macmill<strong>an</strong>.<br />

Reprinted in D. M. Hausm<strong>an</strong> (Ed.), The philosophy of economics (pp. 113–140). Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Rook, D. W. (1985). The ritual dimension ofconsumer behavior. Journal of Consumer Research, 12, 251–264.<br />

Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1983). Mood, misattribution, <strong>an</strong>d judgment ofwell-being: Informative <strong>an</strong>d<br />

directive functions of affective states. Journal of Personality <strong>an</strong>d Social Psychology, 45, 513–523.<br />

Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1988). How do I feel about it? The informative function of affective states. In<br />

K. Fiedler, & J. Forg<strong>as</strong> (Eds.), Affect, cognition, <strong>an</strong>d social behavior (pp. 44–62). Toron<strong>to</strong>: Hogrefe.<br />

Schumpeter, J. A. (1934). Theory of economic development. London: George Allen & Unwin.<br />

Shackle, G. L. S. (1961). Decision, order <strong>an</strong>d time in hum<strong>an</strong> affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Shackle, G. L. S. (1972). Epistemics <strong>an</strong>d economics: A critique of economic doctrines. Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Shiv, B., & Fedorikhin, A. (1999). Heart <strong>an</strong>d mind in conflict: The interplay ofaffect <strong>an</strong>d cognition in<br />

consumer decision making. Journal of Consumer Research, 26, 278–292.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1947). Administrative behavior. New York: Macmill<strong>an</strong>.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model ofrational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69, 99–118.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice, <strong>an</strong>d the structure ofthe environment. Psychological Review, 63,<br />

129–138.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1967). Motivational <strong>an</strong>d emotional controls ofcognition. Psychological Review, 74, 29–39.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1978). Rationality <strong>as</strong> process <strong>an</strong>d <strong>as</strong> product ofthought. Americ<strong>an</strong> Economic Review, 68, 1–16.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1982a). Models of <strong>bounded</strong> <strong>rationality</strong>. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1982b). Comments. In M. S. Clark, & S. Fiske (Eds.), Affect <strong>an</strong>d cognition. Hillsdale, NJ:<br />

Lawrence Erlbaum.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1983). Re<strong>as</strong>on in hum<strong>an</strong> affairs. St<strong>an</strong>ford, CA: St<strong>an</strong>ford University Press.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1985). Hum<strong>an</strong> nature in politics: The dialogue ofpsychology with political science.<br />

Americ<strong>an</strong> Political Science Review, 79, 293–304.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1987). Rationality in psychology <strong>an</strong>d economics. In R. M. Hogarth, & M. W. Reder (Eds.),<br />

Rational choice: The contr<strong>as</strong>t between economics <strong>an</strong>d psychology (pp. 25–40). Chicago: University of<br />

Chicago Press.<br />

Simon, H. A. (1991). Cognitive architectures <strong>an</strong>d rational <strong>an</strong>alysis: Comment. In K. V<strong>an</strong>Lehn (Ed.),<br />

Architectures for intelligence (pp. 25–39). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Thaler, R. H. (2000). From homo economicus <strong>to</strong> homo sapiens. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14, 133–<br />

141.


Y. H<strong>an</strong>och / Journal of Economic Psychology 23 (2002) 1–25 25<br />

Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990). The p<strong>as</strong>t explains the present: <strong>Emotion</strong>al adaptations <strong>an</strong>d the structure<br />

of<strong>an</strong>cestral environment. Ethology <strong>an</strong>d Sociobiology, 11, 375–424.<br />

Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2000). Toward mapping the evolved functional org<strong>an</strong>ization of mind <strong>an</strong>d<br />

brain. In M. S. Gazz<strong>an</strong>iga (Ed.), The newcognitive neurosciences (pp. 1167–1270). Cambridge, MA:<br />

MIT Press.<br />

Turski, W. G. (1994). Toward a <strong>rationality</strong> of emotions. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.<br />

Tversky, A., & Kahnem<strong>an</strong>, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency <strong>an</strong>d probability.<br />

Cognitive Psychology, 4, 207–232.<br />

Tversky, A., & Kahnem<strong>an</strong>, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristic <strong>an</strong>d bi<strong>as</strong>es. Science, 185,<br />

1124–1131.<br />

von Neum<strong>an</strong>n, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games <strong>an</strong>d economic behavior. Prince<strong>to</strong>n, NJ:<br />

Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press.<br />

Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling <strong>an</strong>d thinking: Preferences need no Inferences. Americ<strong>an</strong> Psychologist, 2, 151–<br />

175.<br />

Zey, M. (1992). Criticism ofrational choice theory. In M. Zey (Ed.), Decision making: Alternatives <strong>to</strong><br />

rational choice model (pp. 9–31). Newbury Park: Sage.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!