phainomena

PHAINOMENA-98-99_e-verzija PHAINOMENA-98-99_e-verzija

psychscientists
from psychscientists More from this publisher
03.01.2017 Views

PHAINOMENA XXV/98-99 THE HORIZONS OF EMBODIMENT “Every perspectival appearance implies that the embodied perceiver is herself the experiential zero-point, the indexical ‘here’ in relation to which every appearing object is oriented” (Gallagher/Zahavi 2008: 142). The very starting point for particular phenomenological analyses of egocentric space (with reference to Husserl) also introduces the more general, fundamental phenomenological account of a “basic pre-reflective experiential subjectivity” (Zahavi 2012: 148). However, bearing in mind that “what-it-is-likeness is properly speaking what-it-is-like-for-me-ness” (Zahavi/Kriegel: 2016: 36), the “essential constitutive aspect of experience”, which is most relevant to the present concern, is not the “what it is like” quality aspect, but the distinct for-the-subject aspect, the subjective aspect of for-me-ness. 78 “Whatever their character, whatever their object, all experiences are subjective in the sense that they feel like something for somebody. They are subjective in the sense that there is a distinctive way they present themselves to the subject or self whose episodes they are. It could consequently be claimed that anybody who denies the for-me-ness or mineness of experience simply fails to recognize an essential constitutive aspect of experience. Such a denial would be tantamount to a denial of the first-person perspective. (Zahavi 2012: 149–150)” This implicit “primitive form of self-referentiality or for-me-ness” (Gallagher/Zahavi 2008: 50) characterizes the fact that experiences are nonanonymously something for the subject in question. This has some rather obvious but significant implications for dismissing the Consciousness Challenge. Since Baker’s distinction between consciousness and self-consciousness requires the distinction between two stages of the first-person perspective (in her terms), and to the extent that her description of the rudimentary stage is not sufficient for a proper characterization of the first-person perspective, the “mere consciousness” account of nonlinguistic beings is also called into question. The upshot of this discussion is that for-me-ness as implicit but conscious self-reference to the subject of any first-person perspective is “explicitly” important enough to be properly called pre-reflective self-awareness. Far from

PETER KAISER being merely a terminological consideration, to argue that consciousness as such entails a primitive form of self-awareness might indeed prove “to make the strongest case possible for the existence of prelinguistic and nonconceptual forms of self-awareness” (Zahavi 2002: 18). Therefore, in addition to DeGrazia’s (Bodily) Self-Awareness Arguments, the phenomenological analysis can consistently support and substantiate his – and indeed anybody else’s – case for considering the most basic forms of “mere” bodily awareness as entailing pre-reflective self-awareness. I hope that this may serve to demonstrate that there is a good chance that the resources to be found both in analytical approaches to animal cognition as well as in phenomenological conceptions of embodiment and self-awareness can substantially contribute to the philosophy of animal minds. In terms of prospects for future research, I opt for optimism. Taking bodily self-awareness in animals seriously is a significant starting point in order to broaden the horizons of embodiment for future investigations into corporeality in animals. 79 9. Bibliography Allen, Colin (1999): “Animal Concepts Revisited: The Use of Self- Monitoring as an Empirical Approach”, Erkenntnis 51, 33–40. Allen, Colin and Bekoff, Marc (2013): “Animal Minds, Cognitive Ethology, and Ethics”, in: Animal Minds & Animal Ethics. Connecting Two Separate Fields, Klaus Petrus and Markus Wild (eds.), 249–268. Bielefeld: Transcript. Anderson, Alun and Kacelnik, Alex (2004): “Don’t call me Bird-Brain”, New Scientist 12, 46–47. Andrews, Kristin (2015): The Animal Mind. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition, London, New York: Routledge. Baker, Lynne R. (2012): “From Consciousness to Self-Consciousness”, Grazer Philosophische Studien 84, 19–38. Baker, Lynne R. (2013): Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bermúdez, José Luis (1998): The Paradox of Self-Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

PHAINOMENA XXV/98-99<br />

THE HORIZONS OF EMBODIMENT<br />

“Every perspectival appearance implies that the embodied perceiver is herself<br />

the experiential zero-point, the indexical ‘here’ in relation to which every<br />

appearing object is oriented” (Gallagher/Zahavi 2008: 142).<br />

The very starting point for particular phenomenological analyses of<br />

egocentric space (with reference to Husserl) also introduces the more general,<br />

fundamental phenomenological account of a “basic pre-reflective experiential<br />

subjectivity” (Zahavi 2012: 148). However, bearing in mind that “what-it-is-likeness<br />

is properly speaking what-it-is-like-for-me-ness” (Zahavi/Kriegel: 2016:<br />

36), the “essential constitutive aspect of experience”, which is most relevant to<br />

the present concern, is not the “what it is like” quality aspect, but the distinct<br />

for-the-subject aspect, the subjective aspect of for-me-ness.<br />

78<br />

“Whatever their character, whatever their object, all experiences are<br />

subjective in the sense that they feel like something for somebody. They<br />

are subjective in the sense that there is a distinctive way they present<br />

themselves to the subject or self whose episodes they are. It could<br />

consequently be claimed that anybody who denies the for-me-ness or<br />

mineness of experience simply fails to recognize an essential constitutive<br />

aspect of experience. Such a denial would be tantamount to a denial of<br />

the first-person perspective. (Zahavi 2012: 149–150)”<br />

This implicit “primitive form of self-referentiality or for-me-ness”<br />

(Gallagher/Zahavi 2008: 50) characterizes the fact that experiences are nonanonymously<br />

something for the subject in question. This has some rather<br />

obvious but significant implications for dismissing the Consciousness Challenge.<br />

Since Baker’s distinction between consciousness and self-consciousness<br />

requires the distinction between two stages of the first-person perspective (in<br />

her terms), and to the extent that her description of the rudimentary stage<br />

is not sufficient for a proper characterization of the first-person perspective,<br />

the “mere consciousness” account of nonlinguistic beings is also called into<br />

question.<br />

The upshot of this discussion is that for-me-ness as implicit but conscious<br />

self-reference to the subject of any first-person perspective is “explicitly”<br />

important enough to be properly called pre-reflective self-awareness. Far from

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!