28.10.2016 Views

gender differential paper IJCRB

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ijcrb.webs.com<br />

JUNE 2011<br />

INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF CONTEMPORARY RESEARCH IN BUSINESS VOL 3, NO 2<br />

winning $Y will be accepted if Ln(99)+Ln(109+Y) ≥ 2Ln(109) if Y ≥ 1,211.11. Thus for the<br />

utility function and with a starting wealth level of $109, the individual will turn down the 50-50<br />

chance of losing $10 and winning $11, but will accept a bet of losing $100 and winning any<br />

amount Y in excess of $1,211.11.<br />

Watt (2002) explained that for someone with a very high initial level of wealth, this bet<br />

poses very little risk, and so turning it down requires an extraordinarily high level of risk<br />

aversion. But if the person has an extraordinarily high level of risk aversion in turning down the<br />

bet for even moderate stakes, then the person will also have an extraordinarily high level of risk<br />

aversion in turning down bets for large stakes. Using Pratt’s approximation, Watt showed that<br />

absolute risk aversion at wealth w is approximately equal to [2(w+E(L)-C(L, w]/V(L) where L<br />

denotes a lottery with expected value E(L), variance V(L) and certainty equivalent at wealth w of<br />

C(L,w). The rejection of the 50-50 bet of gaining $105 and losing $100, with the initial wealth<br />

$350,000 implies that relative risk aversion would have to be greater than 166.57. Watt<br />

concluded that for a person with a high level of wealth to turn down a bet of moderate stakes that<br />

has a positive expected value would require either an unreasonably high level of risk aversion, or<br />

some other unusual peculiarity in the utility function. Otherwise, the individual will not reject<br />

both large-scale bets and moderate-scale bets. Therefore, the Expected utility theory certainly<br />

faces its share of problems in explaining certain kinds of empirical evidence, as do other<br />

competing theories.<br />

3.2 Qualitative<br />

3.2.1 Reference Level<br />

How psychological findings suggest modifying the utility function that economists<br />

employ through years. Researchers have identified a pervasive feature of reference dependence.<br />

In a wide variety of domains, people are significantly more averse to losses than they are<br />

attracted to same-sized gains (Kahneman et al., 1990). One realm where such loss aversion plays<br />

out is in preferences over wealth levels. Tversky and Kahneman (1992) suggest that in the<br />

domain of money (and in others where the size of losses and gains can be measured), people<br />

value modest losses roughly twice as much as equal-sized gains. That the displeasure from a<br />

monetary loss is greater than the pleasure from same-sized gain is also implied by a concave<br />

utility function, which typically use as the explanation for risk aversion. But loss aversion says<br />

that the value function abruptly changes slope at the reference level, so that people prefer their<br />

status quo to a 50/50 bet of losing $10 or gaining $11. The standard concave-utility-function<br />

explanation for risk aversion is simply not a plausible explanation of such risk attitude.<br />

Mehra and Prescott (1985) and Esptein and Zin (1990) have, for instance, observed that<br />

the utility-function framework cannot simultaneously explain both small-scale and large-scale<br />

risk attitudes implied by macro data. Rabin (2000) also supported this claim by providing a<br />

“calibration theorem” that indeed show that no concave utility function can simultaneously<br />

explain plausible small-scale and large-scale risk attitudes.<br />

4. Conclusion<br />

We have focused on some of the major theories of economic behavior towards risks and<br />

its efficiency of explanation toward large risks and small risks. Due to the inability of the<br />

expected utility theory to provide a plausible account of risk aversion over modest stakes, we<br />

also discuss the possibilities that may cause an ambiguous explanation of modest-scale risk<br />

aversion. This is crucial especially for the research methods that rely extensively on the expected<br />

utility interpretation.<br />

COPY RIGHT © 2011 Institute of Interdisciplinary Business Research 1029

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!