11.12.2015 Views

Fall 2015

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

JPI<br />

<strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong><br />

Journal of Political Inquiry<br />

<strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong><br />

New York University<br />

19 University Pl. New York,<br />

NY


TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

Citizenship in Colonial Africa 4<br />

An Overview of British and French Repertoires.<br />

Mark Sizwebanzi Mngomezulu<br />

A New Colonialism for Africa? 12<br />

Towards An Understanding of China-Africa Relations<br />

Karim Dewidar<br />

Conflict Escalation, Signaling and Screening 22<br />

Compatibility or Competition?<br />

Kazumichi Uchida<br />

Bordered Citizenship 32<br />

Why Distributive Justice Requires Republic Citizenship<br />

Ji Min Kim<br />

Issues of Legality and Legitimacy 43<br />

The Responsibility to Protect and NATO’s intervention in Libya<br />

Lesley Connolly<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 2


EDITORIAL BOARD<br />

MIREIA TRIGUERO ROURA Editor-in-chief<br />

XING LU Managing Editor<br />

JOSEPH LAVICKA Managing Editor<br />

JIMIN KIM Managing Editor<br />

CLARE CHURCH Editor<br />

LESLEY CONNOLY Editor<br />

HAORAN HE Editor<br />

DYLAN HEYDEN Editor<br />

ESME HELEN MONTGOMERY Editor<br />

DENA MOTEVALIAN Editor<br />

EUNSEONG OH Editor<br />

BRYNNAN PARISH Editor<br />

MORGAN QUINN Editor<br />

SUNGMI SONG Editor<br />

BRITTANY STUBBS Editor<br />

WILLIAM DE WOLFF Editor<br />

ZAINAB ZAHEER Editor<br />

KHOBAIB ZOHAIR Editor<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 3


Citizenship in Colonial<br />

Africa<br />

An Overview of British and<br />

French Repertoires.<br />

Mark Sizwebanzi Mngomezulu<br />

O<br />

ne of the leading characteristics of<br />

the British and French colonial<br />

experience in Africa in the 20th<br />

century—a period often referred to as late<br />

colonialism—was the systematic imposition<br />

of colonizing interests on the territory, and<br />

the institutionalized separation of master and<br />

colonial subject. This meant that the majority<br />

of native Africans, under the auspices of the<br />

British and French empires, did not enjoy the<br />

same rights to citizenship as European-born<br />

or African-born whites. This resulted in a<br />

form of bifurcated citizenship that confined<br />

the majority of the population to second-class<br />

citizenship. However, between the two<br />

empires, there are important differences of<br />

citizenship conceptualization that ultimately<br />

led to diverging local experiences between<br />

British and French Africa.<br />

This paper aims to understand why<br />

the French and British empires applied the<br />

concept of citizenship differently in their<br />

African colonies. Scholars often argue that<br />

most Africans were denied citizenship in the<br />

French and British colonies for economic,<br />

political and social reasons. This reasoning is<br />

insufficient because the experiences within<br />

each empire are different. I argue instead, that<br />

historical experience led to distinct ways of<br />

understanding and deciding who was, or was<br />

not a citizen—producing a unique result in<br />

British and French African colonies. Chief<br />

among these historical experiences was the<br />

French revolution of 1789 that purported to<br />

equalize the rights of people before the law,<br />

and the lack of an experience of similar<br />

pretensions in Britain. This and other<br />

experiences had wider ramifications than<br />

could have been anticipated.<br />

Definition of Citizenship and Theoretical<br />

Framework<br />

Barbalet argues that citizenship<br />

“defines those who are, and who are not,<br />

members of a common society.” 1 This infers<br />

that citizenship is an exclusive concept.<br />

Waters further argues, “It allows one to<br />

participate in a community while enjoying<br />

certain rights and obligations.” 2<br />

To be a citizen of a country entails an<br />

individual’s recognition by the relevant<br />

authorities, as such. The status extends certain<br />

protections over the person granted<br />

citizenship; be it social, political and economic<br />

protections. In exchange for that, the citizen<br />

must abide by the rules of the constituted<br />

authority—the state 3 . The sharp distinction of<br />

who belongs, also entails defining those who<br />

do not belong to a particular state and these<br />

“outsiders may be defined and identified<br />

informally through the use of tacit and<br />

internalized classification schemes” and also<br />

formally through specific documentation, as is<br />

the case in modern states 4 .<br />

This understanding of citizenship has<br />

its genesis in Western Europe. It rose<br />

concomitantly, with the overarching theory of<br />

popular sovereignty in the 17 th Century—<br />

challenging the unchecked rule of monarchs<br />

and emperors, and advocating for the<br />

1 Barbalet (1988) cited in Ndegwa, S.<br />

“Citizenship and Ethnicity. An Examination of<br />

Two Transition Movements in Kenyan Politics,”<br />

American Political Science Review 91.3 (1997),<br />

599.<br />

2 Waters (1989), 160, as cited in Ndegwa, S.<br />

“Citizenship and Ethnicity. An Examination of<br />

Two Transition Movements in Kenyan Politics,”<br />

599.<br />

3 Young, C., “Nation, Ethnicity, and Citizenship:<br />

Dilemmas of Democracy and Civil Order in<br />

Africa,” in Making Nations, Creating Strangers:<br />

States and Citizenship in Africa, ed P. Nugent, et<br />

al. (Boston: Brill Academic Publishers, 2007). <br />

4 Brubaker, R., Citizenship and Nationhood in<br />

France and Germany (Boston: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1992), 30.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 4


inclusion of common people in decisionmaking.<br />

Burbank and Cooper assert that there<br />

was never a clean break between the rule of<br />

empires, and the ushering in of nation-states<br />

and popular sovereignty, with the latter’s<br />

attendant principles of citizenship being<br />

extended to the vast majority of people.<br />

Nation-states and popular sovereignty were<br />

competing ideas in a world that was ruled by<br />

empires. 5 These novel ideas brought to the fore<br />

certain questions. One of which, as Burbank<br />

and Cooper note, was: “Would citizenship be<br />

‘national’—focused on a people who<br />

represented themselves as a single linguistic,<br />

cultural, and territorial community—or would<br />

it be “imperial,” embracing diverse peoples<br />

who constituted the population of a state?” 6<br />

Such a question was important in colonial<br />

Africa, as the French and British empires tried<br />

to assert their authority over vast expanses of<br />

land on the continent.<br />

History was to determine some of the<br />

answers to these questions. Writing on the<br />

salience of history in politics Marx, in the<br />

Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, explains<br />

“Men make their own history, but they do not<br />

make it as they please; they do not make it<br />

under self-selected circumstances, but under<br />

circumstances existing already, given and<br />

transmitted from the past. The tradition of all<br />

dead generations weighs like a nightmare on<br />

the brains of the living.” This highlights that<br />

every nation calls upon a collective memory to<br />

determine rules and norms.<br />

The methods that colonial powers<br />

used in Africa to subdue populations were not<br />

new. They had been used previously, and in a<br />

sense part of the repertoire of each empire, as<br />

Burbank and Cooper note. But the<br />

idiosyncrasies of British and French methods<br />

can each be traced back to a complex yet<br />

unique historical trajectory, from which they<br />

5 Burbank, J and F. Cooper, Empires in World<br />

History: Power and the Politics of Difference<br />

(New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2010).<br />

6 Ibid., 220.<br />

are selected. It is through this framework—a<br />

framework that privileges historical<br />

grounding— that the question of citizenship<br />

in the former colonies of France and Britain<br />

becomes clear.<br />

COLONIALISM IN AFRICA<br />

Historians often describe European<br />

colonization of the African continent in the<br />

late 19 th and early 20 th centuries as a “scramble<br />

for Africa”. Ushered in by the Berlin<br />

Conference, a meeting in which<br />

representatives of western powers gathered in<br />

Berlin to determine the colonial future of<br />

Africa, this era of colonialism was marked by<br />

competition among the industrializing west<br />

for land and resources. To accomplish their<br />

goal, western colonizers employed a regime of<br />

domination over indigenous people.<br />

Cooper 7 cautions against assuming<br />

colonialism in Africa as the natural step that<br />

Western Europe had to take toward Africa.<br />

He argues that there were competing ideas of<br />

how empires should extend their rule in<br />

colonies. Colonialism became a favored<br />

option because it had support from wellconnected<br />

individuals in the metropolis.<br />

Powerful entities in the metropolis, such as<br />

private companies, saw virgin territory as a<br />

bastion of natural resources to be extracted<br />

and an abundance of cheap labor for<br />

production.<br />

For Mamdani, colonialism in Africa<br />

was concerned about the “native question”;<br />

that is, “how can a tiny and foreign minority<br />

rule over an indigenous majority?” 8 Both<br />

empires looked into their repertoires for<br />

suitable strategies of domination. At the core<br />

of both became the de-humanization of the<br />

7 Cooper, F., Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present (United Kingdom: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 2002).<br />

8 Mamdani, M., Citizen and Subject.<br />

Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late<br />

Colonialism (New Jersey: Princeton University<br />

Press, 1996), 16.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 5


African including the institutionalization of<br />

negative racial stereotypes.<br />

Cooper states that:<br />

Colonial empires differed from other forms<br />

of domination by their efforts to reproduce<br />

social and cultural difference. At some level,<br />

conquest implied incorporation: the loser<br />

had to be taught who the boss was and<br />

behave accordingly. But colonial conquest<br />

emphasized that the conquered remain<br />

distinct; he or she might try to learn and<br />

master the ways of the conqueror but would<br />

never quite get there 9 .<br />

Here we see that order—as conceived by the<br />

colonial power—was an important principle<br />

in the colonies. And the distinction by skin<br />

color and ethnicity played a great role in both<br />

French and British colonialism.<br />

Both empires saw the goal of citizenship as<br />

the preservation of the status quo balance of<br />

power that placed white European races on<br />

top of the social order. As the case study<br />

section will show, native Africans were later<br />

included, begrudgingly, as citizens—in a<br />

piecemeal strategy. The British, and to a<br />

greater extent the French, would eventually<br />

open the door for Western-educated Africans,<br />

but still a majority of uneducated Africans<br />

would remain excluded from legal citizenship<br />

status 10 .<br />

Events beginning after World War I<br />

and through World War II changed the<br />

course of history. After the first war—having<br />

gallantly participated in the war on the side of<br />

the allied forces—many African soldiers<br />

returned to Africa believing they had earned<br />

the right to become citizens. They began to<br />

demand the social, economic and political<br />

benefits of citizens, the majority of whom, at<br />

the time, were white 11 . Paralleling this were<br />

9 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present.<br />

10 Mamdani, Citizen and Subject. Contemporary<br />

Africa and the Legacy of Late Colonialism.<br />

11 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present.<br />

the rising voices of educated Africans<br />

criticizing the colonial system and its<br />

institutionalization of citizenship based on<br />

skin-color. In their demand for equal rights,<br />

particularly in French Africa, native Africans<br />

in the colonies would pull from ideas initially<br />

planted in each empire’s past, and seeking to<br />

avoid past mistakes, imperial powers pursued<br />

different appeasement techniques.<br />

CITIZENSHIP IN FRANCOPHONE<br />

AFRICA: ASSIMILATION<br />

The French revolution of 1789 was a<br />

watershed in the French empire because the<br />

assembly passed the Declaration of the Rights<br />

of Man and Citizen. This declaration “stressed<br />

equality before the law and representative<br />

government.” 12<br />

However, it was unclear how far<br />

equality of men, and by extension citizenship,<br />

should extend to colonial holdings, and the<br />

criteria that would be used to determine who<br />

qualified and who was not. The arguments<br />

ranged from theories of how citizenship did<br />

not apply to Africans and Asians, while others<br />

took a more inclusive stance, arguing that<br />

colonization was an indefensible practice 13 .<br />

Several years later, the revolution in<br />

the French colony, St. Domingue (now Haiti),<br />

complicated matters for the empire when<br />

black slave-owners toppled the French<br />

colonial structure and gained independence<br />

under the reasoning that “citizenship…should<br />

not be restricted by color.” 14 The events in St.<br />

Domingue resulted in “the 1795 constitution<br />

in France the colonies an ‘integral part’ of<br />

France. France became, for a time, an empire<br />

of citizens.” 15 Pandora’s Box had been<br />

opened.<br />

12 Burbank and Cooper, Empires in World<br />

History: Power and the Politics of Difference,<br />

224.<br />

13 Burbank and Cooper, Empires in World<br />

History: Power and the Politics of Difference.<br />

14 Ibid., 226.<br />

15 Ibid., 227.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 6


Such events in the history of France<br />

influenced its colonial policy in Africa in the<br />

early to mid-twentieth century, especially<br />

when Africans began to demand their rights<br />

as citizens in the empire. They invoked the<br />

Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen,<br />

arguing they should be recognized as<br />

citizens—their voices bolstered by other<br />

critics of colonial rule.<br />

The French empire found itself in a<br />

conundrum because it desperately needed its<br />

colonies at this time to rejuvenate its economy<br />

that had been devastated by the wars,<br />

especially World War II. To maintain control,<br />

France appeased native African populations<br />

by offering them legal citizenship that was<br />

devoid of any rights that European French<br />

citizens enjoyed. As Young says, “the<br />

assimilative elements in French…colonial<br />

ideologies extended nominal citizenship to all,<br />

but not its full substance.” 16 The essence of<br />

the strategy was appeasement instead of<br />

recognition of Africans as citizens. However,<br />

this did not mean that Africans would not<br />

take such an advantage and use it to its fullest<br />

potential.<br />

By the 1940s, there were already<br />

African deputies representing the colonies in<br />

the French legislature. Most notable among<br />

them, was Leopold Senghor of Senegal, who<br />

was instrumental in the abolishment of<br />

“forced labor and separate administrative<br />

justice.” 17 One idiosyncrasy of the French<br />

conception of citizenship is that the Africans<br />

agitated for inclusion as citizens in the French<br />

empire, as opposed to charting a path<br />

independent of the metropole. Political<br />

realities and perceived economic gains played<br />

a major role in such a course of action. The<br />

idea of African colonies as provinces of one<br />

16 Young, C., “Nation, Ethnicity, and Citizenship:<br />

Dilemmas of Democracy and Civil Order in<br />

Africa,” 254.<br />

17 Cooper, F. (2011), “Restructuring Empire in<br />

British and French Africa,” Past and Present, 10,<br />

Supplement 6, 200.<br />

French empire, whose emphasis had increased<br />

over the years succeeding the Haitian<br />

Revolution, had influence on the thinking and<br />

strategizing of African natives in the colonies.<br />

Thus even though colonial rule was highly<br />

exploitative of natives, they still chose to be<br />

part of the empire. In addition, the colonies’<br />

politics were intimately tied with that of<br />

France, as has been mentioned before that<br />

African deputies sat in the French legislature.<br />

This was unique because, as it will be<br />

observed in the British case, citizenship<br />

debates were territorially bound and rule was<br />

more indirect. Indeed, Cooper contends that<br />

it is historical experience that shaped the<br />

actions of the players at the time. 18<br />

Elkins argues, “France hoped to<br />

restore its international prestige and resist<br />

subordination to an emerging Anglo-<br />

American alliance through closer integration<br />

with its colonies.” 19 Its colonies presented the<br />

chance to counterbalance the ever-growing<br />

economic power of the British especially in<br />

world affairs. This further explains the<br />

nominal citizenship that France extended to<br />

residents of its African colonies: appeasement<br />

for the sake of buffering British power.<br />

Moves toward greater assimilation were<br />

reflected in the French constitution of 1946,<br />

which “proclaimed that inhabitants of all of<br />

these entities would now have ‘qualities’ of<br />

French citizens.” 20 AS Elkins writes, “The<br />

assimilationist principles upon which it (the<br />

French empire) was originally established” 21<br />

reaffirmed France as one with its colonies<br />

abroad. Yet, notwithstanding a constitution<br />

18 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present.<br />

19 Elkins, C., “Race, Citizenship, and<br />

Governance: Settler Tyranny and the End of<br />

Empire,” in Settler Colonialism in the Twentieth<br />

Century: Projects, Practices, Legacies, ed. C.<br />

Elkins, and S Pedersen (Kentucky: Routledge,<br />

2012), 211.<br />

20 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 200.<br />

21 Elkins, “Race, Citizenship, and Governance:<br />

Settler Tyranny and the End of Empire,” 211.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 7


extending citizenship to virtually all peoples of<br />

the French empire, there was ambiguity as to<br />

the full extent of the law and its practicality.” 22<br />

Again, we come to see how the<br />

French revolution and the early years after it<br />

led to a series of events that profoundly<br />

impacted France’s rule of its African colonies<br />

well into the mid-20 th Century. Burbank and<br />

Cooper capture the effects by emphasizing<br />

that: “In 1946, an African political leader,<br />

elected to serve in the French legislature in<br />

Paris, Leopold Senghor, invoked the moment<br />

150 years earlier when France recognized the<br />

citizenship of black slaves. He was trying to<br />

return to the promise of revolutionary France<br />

and make all subjects in the colonies into<br />

citizens, with the same rights as those of<br />

European France.” 23 Here, the values<br />

elucidated in the Declaration of the Rights of<br />

Man and Citizen were recalled and repurposed<br />

to advocate for the rights of French-Africans.<br />

Of course, granting citizenship to<br />

black subjects en masse had social<br />

implications that threatened the stability of<br />

the empire at the time, which is why the<br />

colonial authorities were circumspect in their<br />

policies. This was seen in the extension of<br />

nominal citizenship to native Africans and<br />

especially those in the cities. Increasing the<br />

number of citizens implied the extension of<br />

welfare programs to an unsustainable number<br />

of people. There was also the problem of<br />

whether “citizens of European or African<br />

France could quickly set aside habits and<br />

expectations of privilege and authority, of<br />

discrimination and denigration, built up in<br />

decades of colonial rule.” 24 Citizenship entails<br />

an ‘us-them’ dichotomy, and extending it to<br />

groups that had been historically<br />

disadvantaged, threatens the privilege of those<br />

22 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 201.<br />

23 Burbank and Cooper, Empires in World<br />

History: Power and the Politics of Difference,<br />

229.<br />

24 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 201.<br />

who are citizens at the time. Most of the time,<br />

the latter resist such efforts.<br />

SUBJECTS OF THE BRITISH MONARCH:<br />

INDIRECT RULE<br />

The foremost difference between the<br />

British Empire’s conception of citizenship as<br />

applied to their African colonies and that of<br />

the French, was that Britain never considered<br />

granting citizenship to native Africans within<br />

its colonies 25 . Instead there was a preference<br />

for indirect rule—the strategy of ruling<br />

through chiefs. The British did not invent this<br />

strategy—having been employed by other<br />

empires in the past. 26<br />

Mamdani argues that indirect rule was<br />

not a benevolent process of respecting the<br />

customs of African ethnic groups, or letting<br />

them develop in their own way either. The<br />

African was seen as a “tribesperson” subject<br />

to “customary law.” Such a process of<br />

separate administration for Africans<br />

effectively meant that they had separate rights<br />

from Europeans, and existed in a different<br />

society from that of the British.<br />

One important reason for this<br />

fundamental difference in the techniques<br />

employed by the French colonial rule was that<br />

Britain never experienced a revolution that<br />

claimed to equalize the rights of people before<br />

the law. The only revolution that comes close<br />

is the Glorious Revolution of 1688, but this<br />

was mainly a tussle between Parliament and<br />

the monarchy concerning who was to wield<br />

more power. Hence, the British historical<br />

narrative did not have universal natures of<br />

freedom on which native Africans could base<br />

a case for demanding citizenship. This is not<br />

to argue that ideas of the Enlightenment<br />

period in the 20 th Century—popular<br />

sovereignty, equality, amongst others—did<br />

not affect the British Empire, but that it<br />

25 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present.<br />

26 Burbank and Cooper, Empires in World<br />

History: Power and the Politics of Difference.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 8


ationalized such arguments differently, and in<br />

turn translated into unique colonial strategies.<br />

The notion of citizenship in British<br />

colonies is captured by Cooper, when he<br />

mentions that the, “ruling fiction was ‘selfgovernment’:<br />

each territory would follow its<br />

own path; there would be no representation<br />

of Africans in the London parliament.” 27 The<br />

authorities channeled African political activity<br />

in territorially bounded institutions, thus<br />

avoiding any calls for citizenship equality of<br />

natives and white people, since territories<br />

were “independent.”<br />

The fact that the British never<br />

considered Africans in the colonies to be<br />

citizens of Britain did not snuff out debates<br />

for equality and citizenship. Rather, it<br />

channeled them differently, especially after<br />

World War I through World War II.<br />

The British, unlike the French, never<br />

envisioned a possibility of Africans becoming<br />

citizens even nominally—let alone citizens<br />

with equal footing to the European settlers in<br />

the colonies, or those in the metropole.<br />

Mazrui disparages the British in these words:<br />

“I hope it is only a coincidence that the<br />

Anglo-Saxons….have been the worst<br />

offenders among the Westerners in<br />

institutionalized racism. The Anglo-Saxons<br />

were the architects of lynching and Jim<br />

Crow.” 28 The importance of racial thought in<br />

the mind of the colonial administrator was a<br />

great barrier.<br />

The aforementioned can help us<br />

understand the different policies of both the<br />

French and the British. Assimilation, at the<br />

basic level, means acceptance—a capitulation<br />

to inclusiveness. On the other hand, indirect<br />

rule evokes aloofness, a preference for<br />

separation among peoples. And that is what<br />

the British did. British culture was seen as<br />

almost naturally inaccessible to the native.<br />

Whereas in the French empire, an African<br />

could, with education and consumption of<br />

French culture, become a French citizen, the<br />

British had no such thing.<br />

Like their French counterparts, the<br />

British also faced the real problem of trying to<br />

retain its empire because of its economic<br />

importance. As Cooper states: “attempts to<br />

get educated Africans to focus their ambitions<br />

on local government quickly failed. The focus<br />

was not London…but the center of each<br />

territory.” The result was that ambition for<br />

equality by most African leaders followed the<br />

avenue opened by the master: “political<br />

parties in colony after colony demanded full<br />

participation in each territory’s legislative and<br />

executive institutions,” without demanding to<br />

sit in London. 29<br />

After having served in the European<br />

wars—World War I and World War II—most<br />

returnee Africans of British colonies flocked<br />

to urban centers and began lives that<br />

depended to a larger extent on Western<br />

goods. Their bad experience in the cities,<br />

stemming from repressive colonial policies,<br />

fueled their demands for a better life 30 . Also,<br />

the newly-formed educated class saw the<br />

contradictions of the colonial state—that it<br />

oppressed Africans in their native land and<br />

extracted its resources—and sought to<br />

challenge that.<br />

Instead of an incorporation of<br />

Africans as citizens in the empire, the British<br />

suggested a possibility of self-government in<br />

its separate colonies, in the future. To this<br />

end Cooper argues that, “the Nationalities Act<br />

of 1948 created something of an echo of what<br />

the French were doing—a second tier<br />

Commonwealth citizenship, derivative of the<br />

primary citizenship of the Dominions, but<br />

27 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present, 49.<br />

28 Mazrui, A., “Who are the Africans?” in Who is<br />

an African? Identity, Citizenship and the Making<br />

of Africa-Nation, ed. J. Adibe (London: Adonis &<br />

Abbey Publishers Ltd.: 2009), 32.<br />

29 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 202.<br />

30 Cooper, Africa since 1940: The Past of the<br />

Present.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 9


applied to colonies as well.” 31 This only<br />

allowed British Africans to gain access to<br />

British Isles—a far cry from recognition<br />

among citizens. Africans could be considered<br />

as citizens in the British Isles but not in<br />

Britain itself—an obvious hostility towards<br />

native Africans in the metropolis.<br />

In contrast to developments in the<br />

French empire around the same time, “in<br />

British Africa…the theme of equality<br />

surfaced, although without the same appeal to<br />

empire-wide citizenship and its norm of<br />

equivalence…in French Africa.” 32<br />

Such attempts by both colonial authorities to<br />

shape citizenship and the reaction of the<br />

subjects often degenerated into a violent<br />

process. This was more the case in settler<br />

colonies—colonies where Europeans were<br />

encouraged to settle in great numbers—where<br />

African populations were condemned into<br />

reserves. For example, the Mau Mau rebellion<br />

in Kenya in the around 1957 to 1960 was a<br />

reaction to the increasing brutality of white<br />

colonial settlers, as the Kikuyu people called<br />

for better treatment and rights 33 .<br />

Cooper opines that “repression may<br />

have well reflected the self-perceived<br />

openness to political reform: that some<br />

Africans rejected the political inclusion and<br />

economic development that was being offered<br />

them now struck officials as an affront, not<br />

the backward inclinations inherent in the<br />

nature of the African.” 34 Because of the power<br />

to set agenda for reform, the colonists<br />

perceived a rejection of that agenda as<br />

ungratefulness on the part of those over<br />

whom they ruled. Therefore persistence on an<br />

agenda unsanctioned by the colonial masters<br />

led to the repression of native Africans,<br />

31 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 202.<br />

32 Ibid., 205.<br />

33 Elkins, “Race, Citizenship, and Governance:<br />

Settler Tyranny and the End of Empire.”<br />

34 Cooper, “Restructuring Empire in British and<br />

French Africa,” 203.<br />

especially in the period preceding<br />

independence.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

In the late 19 th and early 20 th Century,<br />

Britain and France were among the Western<br />

European nations that decided, without any<br />

input from representatives of the continent<br />

itself, to divide Africa into colonies in support<br />

of self-interested goals of industrialization and<br />

power. While France and Britain share a<br />

common Western European identity, the<br />

historical narratives that came into effect<br />

when each nation devised and employed its<br />

colonial strategy in Africa were quite different.<br />

And while scholars often combine the<br />

colonial experiences of British and French<br />

African colonies in their analysis, this is<br />

insufficient as there are major differences<br />

between them.<br />

This paper has shown how historical<br />

experience impacted the unfolding of events<br />

relating to calls for equality in the colonies by<br />

Africans, and relating to citizenship in<br />

particular. In part, this proves the<br />

interconnectedness of historical experience.<br />

Also, the empires used tools which they saw<br />

fit for that particular time, although they<br />

could not control how events would unfold,<br />

once they had chosen their policies. The<br />

policy of assimilation pursued by the French<br />

had a lasting effect on citizenship conception<br />

in its African colonies, so much so that native<br />

Africans saw their rights as intrinsically<br />

connected with France itself. A shift towards<br />

more territorially bounded units in French<br />

Africa arises in the late 1950s, influenced to a<br />

certain extent by the reconfiguration of the<br />

Third World, which was breaking away<br />

politically from Western powers and forming<br />

new states. On the other hand, the policy of<br />

indirect rule pursued by the British channeled<br />

citizenship rights to more territorially<br />

bounded units, and it could be said that this<br />

was the model that inspired the form of<br />

statehood that now prevails in Africa.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 10


Lastly, this paper has drawn fairly<br />

broad strokes of citizenship in colonial<br />

Africa—a heuristic contribution at best. Thus<br />

it suffices to add that there are numerous<br />

potential avenues for further research in this<br />

topic. For one, this essay has hardly made<br />

mention of the variation—if any—of<br />

citizenship understanding within countries of<br />

colonized by the same power, and implication<br />

on state formation processes. Also, it has not<br />

examined the dynamics between the colonizer<br />

and the colonized in shaping citizenship, and<br />

the subsequent states. These omissions are<br />

largely a product of the essay’s scope. Thus it<br />

behooves other scholars of Africa to delve<br />

into the particularities in order to understand<br />

deeper the impact of past understandings of<br />

citizenship on the present.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 11


A New Colonialism for<br />

Africa?<br />

Towards An Understanding of<br />

China-Africa Relations<br />

Karim Dewidar<br />

T<br />

he literature on China-Africa relations<br />

today is focused on the issue of<br />

imperialism and neo-colonialism, that<br />

is, are the Chinese exploiting the African<br />

continent like Western countries have done in<br />

the past? Chinese scholars are going to great<br />

lengths to attempt to show why the<br />

relationship is a “win-win,” and that China is<br />

not exploiting the African continent.<br />

Conversely, many Western analysts are equally<br />

as eager to show that China’s policy is<br />

exploitative and simply a form of neocolonialism.<br />

However, both sides get it wrong<br />

because neither paradigm alone is a correct<br />

characterization of China-Africa relations.<br />

China’s foreign policy in the African continent<br />

is neither benign nor neo-colonial. It is a<br />

pragmatic economic and political move by<br />

China, which is seeking greater economic and<br />

political cooperation with Africa. Though, it is<br />

taking a different approach from that of the<br />

West.<br />

China’s growing prosperity and<br />

increasing role in international affairs have led<br />

to an increase in Chinese foreign direct<br />

investment all over the world. As China’s<br />

economy grows so does its energy and<br />

resource needs, Africa will invariably become<br />

an area of interest by China. Also, Africa is an<br />

increasingly lucrative market for exports.<br />

Naturally, China seeks closer political, social,<br />

and military ties as well. This is evident with<br />

China’s foreign aid to Africa, peacekeeping<br />

missions, and other social initiatives by China<br />

in Africa.<br />

Though China’s engagement with Africa is<br />

not neo-colonial, China provides development<br />

aid, often in the form of infrastructure<br />

projects. This will improve Africa’s economic<br />

self-sufficiency. Most of the Chinese firms<br />

that operate in China are private firms and<br />

small or medium sized state owned<br />

enterprises. Also, China is building on its long<br />

relationship with Africa that has not been<br />

exploitative and based on mutual recognition<br />

of sovereignty.<br />

However, China’s new relationship<br />

with Africa requires scrutiny, as there are<br />

concerns China is using its influence to<br />

exploit African countries. Many of the<br />

infrastructure projects seem to serve the<br />

interests of Chinese firms operating in Africa.<br />

There is also relatively little “aid” given by<br />

China and the bulk of the money flowing into<br />

Africa are to fund private Chinese business<br />

ventures. China’s investment tends to favor a<br />

select group of African countries. These select<br />

countries tend to be natural resource<br />

exporters, whereas China mostly imports oil<br />

and other minerals from Africa. In addition,<br />

there is a trade deficit with Chinese<br />

manufacturers seemingly flooding African<br />

markets to the detriment of African<br />

producers. There are no real indications that<br />

China’s investments are yielding benefits to<br />

Africa overall.<br />

THE MYTH OF CHINESE COLONIALISM<br />

IN AFRICA<br />

Given the disparity between China’s<br />

economy and those of the various African<br />

countries it is investing, it has been accused of<br />

perpetuating conditions of neo-colonialism in<br />

Africa. The essence of neo-colonialism is that,<br />

“The State which is subject to it is, in theory,<br />

independent and has all the outwards<br />

trappings of international sovereignty. In<br />

reality its economic and thus its political<br />

policy is directed from outside.” 35<br />

Even though countries of Africa won<br />

their independence in the second half of the<br />

20 th century, the former European imperialist<br />

powers and other Western states like the U.S.<br />

35 Kwame Nkrumah, Neo-Colonialism: The Last<br />

Stage of Imperialism (New York: International<br />

Publishers, 1974), 4.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 12


have retained elements of old colonial<br />

arrangements. Many Western companies<br />

dominate the key African industries of<br />

mineral extraction and agriculture. Also, many<br />

African states remain dependent on aid and<br />

investment from Western countries just to<br />

provide basic services. Much of this aid places<br />

conditions on the recipients such as policies<br />

of economic and political liberalization. One<br />

of the most famous example being the<br />

“structural readjustment policies” that the<br />

International Monetary Fund imposes on<br />

African states that receive supports. Most<br />

former colonies rely solely on natural resource<br />

exports and cannot make the leap to more<br />

developed and self-sufficient economies. The<br />

end result is that former colonies, despite<br />

being “free,” remain no more independent<br />

now than as colonies.<br />

China’s interest in Africa is not new<br />

and has never included colonialism in the<br />

traditional sense. There are records of<br />

Chinese-African trading dating back to the<br />

Tang Dynasty (A.D. 618-907), but it was<br />

under the Ming Dynasty in the 13th century<br />

that saw Chinese penetration of the African<br />

continent. 36 Admiral Zheng led expeditions to<br />

Africa’s east coast on various occasions,<br />

primarily parts of modern day Somalia and<br />

Kenya. 37 These “Treasure Fleets,” which the<br />

Chinese emperor used to project China’s<br />

wealth and power. The early Chinese diaspora<br />

came neither as conquerors nor immigrants. 38<br />

Contemporary China-Africa relations are built<br />

upon these early interactions, which are<br />

36 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012), 17.<br />

37 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 30.<br />

38 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman, China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012), 22.<br />

relatively benign when looking at European<br />

settlement of Africa.<br />

During the Cold War, China’s policies<br />

were guided both by their geopolitical struggle<br />

with the Soviet Union and a genuine interest<br />

in “south-south” solidarity. In the 1950’s<br />

China went on a “charm offensive,” which<br />

was guided by its 5 Principles of Peaceful<br />

Coexistence. Though at its core, China’s<br />

diplomacy emphasized the sovereignty of<br />

African nations that were targets for U.S. and<br />

Soviet Cold War interventions. Having<br />

suffered from foreign occupations during the<br />

Century of Humiliation, China especially<br />

sympathized with Africa, which was still<br />

largely colonized. By the 1960s, with the<br />

creation of the Afro-Asian Solidarity<br />

Organization, the continent had become an<br />

essential part of Chinese foreign policy. 39 All<br />

throughout the Cold War, China supported<br />

independence movements and revolutions<br />

such as: Algeria’s FLN, the Mozambique<br />

Liberation Front, and Angola’s UNITA<br />

(National Union for the Total Independence<br />

of Angola) in Angola. China’s foreign policy<br />

also included economic assistance. Egypt was<br />

offered a $5 million trade credit during the<br />

Suez Crisis 40 and in 1964 provided an $80<br />

million interest-free loan to cover the cost of<br />

Chinese goods and services. 41 China also<br />

funded the construction of a railway<br />

connecting Tanzania and Zambia in 1976. 42<br />

China’s African policies were not only<br />

motivated by ambition to overtake the Soviet<br />

Union as the leader of the Communist<br />

Revolution, but also by the desire to help<br />

liberate the oppressed. In 2006, President Hu<br />

Jintao articulated China’s Principles for<br />

engagement with Africa and is almost no<br />

39 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman, China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement, 34.<br />

40 Ibid, 35.<br />

41 ibid, 230.<br />

42 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 48.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 13


different than the 5 Principles articulated by<br />

Premier Zhou Enlai in 1955.<br />

The winding down of the Cold War<br />

led to the U.S. and the Soviet Union to shift<br />

their attention away from the Sub Saharan<br />

region and more towards the Middle East. In<br />

1996, President Jiang Zemin visited Ethiopia<br />

and laid out China’s African policy approach.<br />

It was a 21 point proposal, but the key themes<br />

for China’s engagement with Africa were:<br />

respecting sovereignty, seeking of mutually<br />

beneficial economic development, promoting<br />

African cooperation-unity, and building a long<br />

term friendship. 43 In 2000, China’s Ministry<br />

of Foreign Affairs created the Forum on<br />

China-Africa Cooperation (FOCAC) as a<br />

mechanism for facilitating this new<br />

relationship. 44<br />

Contrary to popular belief, the<br />

majority of Chinese firms that invest or trade<br />

abroad are privately owned and thus they are<br />

not just arms of the Chinese state that can be<br />

used to affect geopolitics. About 70% of<br />

China’s total outward foreign direct<br />

investments consist of joint ventures;<br />

collaborations between Chinese firms and<br />

private foreign firms. 45 That is, all the trade<br />

and commercial activities taking place are<br />

being facilitated predominantly by private<br />

firms on both ends. According to China’s<br />

Export-Import Bank, of the 800 large<br />

companies operating in Africa in 2006, 85%<br />

are privately owned. 46 Rather than collaborate<br />

43 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 47.<br />

44 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014), 20.<br />

45 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 112.<br />

46 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012), 129.<br />

to implement a grand strategy for China on<br />

the African continent, the interests of private<br />

firms vary as they compete for market share.<br />

Those accusing China of trying to dominate<br />

the African continent presume its trade is<br />

being carried out by large state owned<br />

enterprises. This assumption is wrong because<br />

most of the Chinese firms in Africa are “small<br />

and medium sized enterprises,” both private<br />

and government owned. 47 Companies run by<br />

provincial and local jurisdictions also invest in<br />

Africa. 48 Although encouraged by the central<br />

government’s “going out strategy” in the 90’s,<br />

these state owned firms are not merely pawns<br />

for the central government. They compete<br />

with other smaller state owned firms and<br />

ultimately are out to make money; they are<br />

not concerned with wider geopolitical<br />

objectives of the China central government. 49<br />

This fragmented and competitive<br />

environment for SMEs is a stark contrast<br />

from the perception that many have of<br />

Chinese enterprise in Africa, namely large oil<br />

companies like Sinopec. Chinese firms in<br />

Africa do not constitute a monolithic bloc of<br />

state owned enterprises.<br />

Another mischaracterization of China-<br />

Africa relations is the Chinese diaspora, often<br />

used to support the argument that China is<br />

undertaking some colonial venture in Africa.<br />

There are about one million Chinese natives<br />

in Africa today, many of them having come<br />

over during the last decade. 50 Although some<br />

are wealthy businesses owners or<br />

professionals, the majority are petty<br />

merchants, shopkeepers, and farmers. 51 They<br />

predominantly come from interior provinces<br />

47 ibid.<br />

48 Ibid.<br />

49 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 236.<br />

50 Howard French, China’s Second Continent:<br />

How A Million Migrants Are Building a New<br />

Empire in Africa (New York City: Vintage Books,<br />

2014), 4.<br />

51 ibid .<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 14


like Henan or from coastal areas with tough<br />

job markets like Fujian and Guangdong. 52<br />

Many of those interviewed by journalist<br />

Howard French, who traversed Africa seeking<br />

to learn more about the Chinese diaspora,<br />

complained about being squeezed out of<br />

China, both economically and socially. 53<br />

French remarks that they are like ambitious<br />

frontiersmen. There is no evidence either to<br />

show that this is the result of a policy by the<br />

central government to encourage travel to<br />

Africa.<br />

IS CHINA’S RELATIONSHIP WITH<br />

AFRICA REALLY A “WIN-WIN?”<br />

To decipher what China’s intentions<br />

are on the African continent, the Chinese<br />

policy of giving “aid” needs to be<br />

distinguished from its foreign direct<br />

investment. Both Chinese officials and<br />

Western critics alike talk about the two<br />

interchangeably, but they are distinct. Foreign<br />

aid, which comes from China’s Central<br />

government, has always been part of China-<br />

Africa relations. China officially provides 8<br />

types of foreign aid: complete projects, goods<br />

and materials, technical cooperation, human<br />

resource development cooperation, medical<br />

assistance, emergency humanitarian aid,<br />

volunteer programs, and debt relief. 54<br />

The problem is that the amount of aid<br />

given is relatively small. In 2012 alone, the<br />

U.S. provided $7.08 billion in development<br />

assistance to African countries. 55 This does<br />

not even include World Bank financing. As of<br />

2009, the cumulative-historical aid given to<br />

African countries by China was no more than<br />

52 ibid 25.<br />

53 ibid 31.<br />

54 ibid.<br />

55 George Ingram, “U.S. Development<br />

Assistance and Sub-Saharan Africa,” Brookings,<br />

3/20/2014,<br />

http://www.brookings.edu/research/reports/2013/<br />

04/us-development-assistance-engagementafrica-ingram.<br />

$25 billion. 56 Between 2001 and 2007 alone,<br />

China invested $15.6 billion in Sub Saharan<br />

Africa’s oil and mineral sector. 57 To cover the<br />

economic imperative of its relationship with<br />

Africa, China frequently highlights its aid<br />

programs instead. Indicative of China’s<br />

tendency to pass off lucrative commercial<br />

endeavors as a form of aid are Special<br />

Economic Zones. These are geographic areas<br />

equipped with infrastructures and liberalized<br />

business laws to attract foreign investment. 58<br />

These privately managed free trade zones<br />

often cater to the needs of Chinese firms<br />

more than anything else. 59<br />

A misperception perpetuated by China<br />

is that it is interested in trading and with the<br />

entire African continent. Chinese policy in<br />

Africa is presented as an endeavor to benefit<br />

to Africa as whole. Take for example a 2006<br />

white paper on China’s African policy. One of<br />

the objectives it stated is, “Mutual benefit,<br />

reciprocity and common prosperity. China<br />

supports African countries endeavor for<br />

economic development and nation building,<br />

carries out cooperation in various forms in<br />

economic and social development, and<br />

promotes common prosperity of China and<br />

Africa.” 60<br />

Though in reality, trade is highly<br />

concentrated with just a few countries.<br />

China’s top African trading partners are:<br />

56 Fred Dews, “8 facts about China’s<br />

investments in Africa,” Brookings, 3/20/2014,<br />

http://www.brookings.edu/blogs/brookingsnow/posts/2014/05/8-facts-about-chinainvestment-in-africa.<br />

57 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) .<br />

58 Robert Rotberg, China into Africa: Trade, Aid,<br />

and Influence (Cambridge: Brookings Institution<br />

Press, 2008), 137.<br />

59 ibid 141.<br />

60 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 50.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 15


Angola, South Africa, Sudan, Nigeria, and<br />

Egypt. 61 About 75% of China’s total imports,<br />

namely oil and minerals, come from Angola<br />

and South Africa alone. 62 Over 40% of<br />

China’s exports go to just three African<br />

countries: Egypt, Nigeria, and South Africa. 63<br />

The much-discussed Special Economic Zones<br />

are being set up in just 7 countries: Zambia<br />

[which is getting 2], Mauritius, Egypt, Zambia,<br />

Nigeria, Tanzania, and Ethiopia. 64 Thus,<br />

China’s trading partners make a small portion<br />

of the continents 54 countries.<br />

China has vigorously argued that it is<br />

not primarily interested in Africa’s natural<br />

resources, namely oil, though the numbers<br />

make a compelling case against them. By 2009<br />

80% of China’s imports from Africa consisted<br />

of petroleum products and metals, for<br />

example, copper. 65 Not surprisingly, 4 of<br />

Africa’s top 5 exporters to China primarily<br />

export oil and other minerals. Though oil<br />

makes up the largest proportion, accounting<br />

for 64% of China’s total imports from<br />

Africa. 66 China used to be an energy selfsufficient<br />

country, but in 1993 it became a net<br />

61 Christopher Alessi and Beina Xu, “China in<br />

Africa,” Council on Foreign Relations, 4/27/<strong>2015</strong>,<br />

http://www.cfr.org/china/china-africa/p9557 .<br />

62 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014) ,29.<br />

63 ibid<br />

64 Robert Rotberg, China into Africa: Trade, Aid,<br />

and Influence (Cambridge: Brookings Institution<br />

Press, 2008),143-149,<br />

David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China and<br />

Africa: A Century of Engagement (Philadelphia:<br />

University of Pennsylvania Press, 2012) , 136-<br />

137.<br />

65 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 117.<br />

66 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014), 30.<br />

importer of oil as its economy expanded. 67<br />

China is now the second largest consumer of<br />

petroleum and is projected to become the<br />

largest consumer by 2030, at which point it<br />

will be importing 60-70% of its crude oil<br />

supply. 68 Currently, China imports about 23%<br />

of its oil from Africa and this is expected to<br />

increase as it continues to secure more oil<br />

concessions and invests more in exploration.<br />

Although private business and SMEs<br />

are ostensibly overseeing China’s economic<br />

reproach to the African continent, the central<br />

government still plays an important role by<br />

financing and promoting Chinese-African<br />

business ventures. The central government<br />

provides aid such as concessional loans and<br />

grants to various African countries. This is<br />

done via China’s Central Bank and<br />

government funds such as: the China Export-<br />

Import Bank, China-Africa Development<br />

program, and the Agricultural Development<br />

Bank of China. 69 Beyond financial<br />

institutions, China’s Ministry of Commerce<br />

and its Ministry of Foreign Affairs are vital to<br />

the process as well; they liaise with African<br />

heads of state. Through loans, grants, and<br />

construction projects these agencies open up<br />

channels of investment and trade in African<br />

countries. The foreign aid offered at this part<br />

of the process, “to grease the wheels,” is what<br />

gets so much attention. This includes: loans<br />

for infrastructure projects, medical assistance<br />

programs, and grants.<br />

Perhaps China is not solely interested<br />

in extracting natural resources from Africa,<br />

but also the access to them. It has been part<br />

67 Christopher Alessi and Beina Xu, “China in<br />

Africa,” Council on Foreign Relations, 4/27/<strong>2015</strong>,<br />

http://www.cfr.org/china/china-africa/p9557.<br />

68 ibid<br />

69 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 134.<br />

Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 108.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 16


of arrangements made with various African<br />

countries that were offered aid and<br />

development finance. The Chinese like to<br />

emphasize their “no strings attached” aid to<br />

Africa, which is in contrast to Western<br />

countries that provide aid, but have<br />

conditions imposed on the recipient. Though<br />

not agreed to openly, there is actually “tacit<br />

conditionality,” that comes with aid given to<br />

African countries. Often, it is concessionsaccess<br />

to oil or minerals. 70 This is what<br />

Chinese-African analysts have named the<br />

“Angola Model.” In 2004 Angola broke off<br />

negotiations with the IMF and turned to<br />

China for financial assistance, securing a $2<br />

billion loan with quite a generous interest<br />

rate. 71 By 2007 Angola had become China’s<br />

second largest oil supplier in Sub Saharan<br />

Africa. 72 Angola agreed to repay the loan in<br />

oil to China at a price not subject to market<br />

change. 73 In 2006, China’s state oil firm<br />

Sinopec won the bid for a lucrative offshore<br />

oil concession, “Block 18”. Later that year<br />

when China’s Premier Wen Jiabao visited<br />

Sudan he announced a supplemental $2 billion<br />

dollar loan. 74 This is not unique to Angola<br />

and this form of payment in resources is<br />

common as well for other African-Chinese<br />

agreements.<br />

China is quick to point out that their<br />

relations with Africa are not a colonial or neocolonial<br />

endeavor because it has no significant<br />

military installments in Africa to speak of.<br />

Strictly speaking, China does not have military<br />

bases, but it has a growing presence on the<br />

African continent. Estimates of PLA forces in<br />

Africa are as high as 5,000 and China has<br />

high-level military engagements with 43<br />

70 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 138.<br />

71 Robert Rotberg, China into Africa: Trade, Aid,<br />

and Influence (Cambridge: Brookings Institution<br />

Press, 2008),119.<br />

72 ibid 118.<br />

73 ibid 119.<br />

74 ibid 120.<br />

African countries. 75 It is increasingly<br />

common for military personnel from various<br />

African countries to go train and study in<br />

Chinese defense colleges. 76 Now, China has<br />

an extensive network of defense attaché<br />

offices, used to coordinate military contacts,<br />

in 1 out of 3 African countries. 77 These<br />

offices are most concentrated in African<br />

countries where China has significant<br />

commercial interests such as: Angola, South<br />

Sudan, Ghana, Nigeria, and South Africa. 78<br />

China is set to begin building its first military<br />

base in the key coastal country of Djibouti. 79<br />

China’s military presence is also marked by<br />

their growing peacekeeping force, which are<br />

found in: South Sudan, Sudan (Darfur), the<br />

Democratic Republic of the Congo, Liberia,<br />

Western Sahara, and the Ivory Coast. 80<br />

China’s intentions need to be called<br />

into question despite the modest size and<br />

benign disposition of its armed forces in<br />

Africa. What Beijing does not mention is that<br />

China is also the largest arms supplier to Sub<br />

Saharan Africa, particularly small arms. 81 A<br />

75 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 253.<br />

76 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014), 43.<br />

77 Ibid.<br />

78 Marcus Power, et al, China’s Resource<br />

Diplomacy in Africa: Powering Development?<br />

(Great Brittan: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 253.<br />

79 AFP,”China ‘Negotiates military base in<br />

Djibouti,” Al Jazeera, 5/10/<strong>2015</strong>,<br />

http://www.aljazeera.com/news/africa/<strong>2015</strong>/05/1<br />

50509084913175.html.<br />

80 Mohsan Ali, “U.S. vs. China: Footprints in<br />

Africa,” Al Jazeera, 6/2/2013,<br />

http://www.aljazeera.com/indepth/features/2013/<br />

07/20137117422885596.html.<br />

81 Colum Lynch, “China’s Arms Exports Flooding<br />

Sub-Saharan Africa,” The Washington Post,<br />

3/16/15,<br />

https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/nationalsecurity/chinas-arms-exports-flooding-sub-<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 17


steady flow of small arms into Africa over the<br />

years has fueled countless conflicts. China has<br />

no qualms about selling arms to questionable<br />

regimes either. China provides arms to<br />

Equatorial Guinea, a notoriously corrupt and<br />

cruel regime, even by Sub Saharan<br />

standards. 82 China has also been investing<br />

heavily in oil exploration in Equatorial<br />

Guinea. It even provided arms to South<br />

Sudan as it was carrying out its genocide in<br />

Darfur 83 and in 2011 they offered the Gaddafi<br />

regime weapons to help fight U.S.-NATO<br />

forces.<br />

ASSESSING CHINA’S INVESTMENT:<br />

LOOKING AT SOME FIGURES<br />

Both the Chinese and many of the<br />

their African partners claim their new<br />

relationship will help the African continent<br />

prosper, but the numbers show a complicated<br />

picture. Average annual growth was 5.7%<br />

from 2000-2010, when China began trading<br />

and investing substantially more with Africa.<br />

Average annual growth for the African<br />

continent over the last 2 decades has been<br />

4.4% according to the World Bank. 84 Most<br />

growth over the last decade has been mainly<br />

by oil and mineral exporters such as Angola:<br />

10.8% (2004-2013), Ghana: 7.6% (2004-2013),<br />

and Zambia: 7.1% (2005-<strong>2015</strong>). 85 For others<br />

that are not primarily oil exporters growth has<br />

not been spectacular despite being key trade<br />

saharan-africa/2012/08/25/16267b68-e7f1-11e1-<br />

936a-b801f1abab19_story.html.<br />

82 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014), 47.<br />

83 Mark Caldwell, “SIPRI: ‘China’s Arms Trade<br />

With Africa At Times Questionable,” Deutsche<br />

Welle, 3/16/<strong>2015</strong>, http://www.dw.de/sipri-chinas-<br />

arms-trade-with-africa-at-times-questionable/a-<br />

18319346.<br />

84 World Bank, Poverty and Equity: Sub Saharan<br />

Africa, World Bank<br />

http://povertydata.worldbank.org/poverty/region/<br />

SSA.<br />

85 Ibid.<br />

partners with China. During the last decade or<br />

so, growth for South Africa has been on<br />

average under 5% and for Egypt around<br />

4.3%. 86 However, poverty trends indicate<br />

modest improvements. In 1990, 56.6% of<br />

Africans were living under the poverty line<br />

subsisting on $1.25 or less per day. As of 2011<br />

it had decreased to 46.8%. 87<br />

EMERGING TRENDS AND HOW TO<br />

MAKE SENSE OF CHINA-AFRICA<br />

RELATIONS<br />

Chinese leaders have stressed that<br />

investments being made in the African<br />

continent are not just handouts, but rather for<br />

the purpose of helping to build up Africa’s<br />

capacity. China’s commercial investment and<br />

aid projects were supposed to offer both<br />

physical and human capital to the African<br />

continent. The FDI China provides is<br />

supposed to build up the African economy<br />

and increase self-sufficiency. Contrary to the<br />

claims of Chinese officials, the investments by<br />

design seem to perpetuate the conditions of<br />

Africa’s human and physical infrastructure<br />

that keep the continent impoverished.<br />

China’s policies have not helped<br />

employ or train Africans, nor provide the<br />

necessary infrastructure. Most firms, even<br />

those in low pay, low skill sectors such as<br />

construction or mining, are hesitant to hire<br />

Africans. 88 They claim that the locals are not<br />

qualified and they do want to train them<br />

either. Instead, contract laborers are brought<br />

in from China at 10 times the cost. 89 The<br />

86 World Bank: Africa Overview 2014,<br />

http://www.worldbank.org/en/region/afr/overview<br />

#1.<br />

87 World Bank,Poverty and Equity: Sub Saharan<br />

Africa, World Bank<br />

http://povertydata.worldbank.org/poverty/region/<br />

SSA .<br />

88 Howard French, China’s Second Continent:<br />

How A Million Migrants Are Building a New<br />

Empire in Africa (New York City: Vintage Books,<br />

2014), 54.<br />

89 Ibid.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 18


Chinese firms are going out of their way to<br />

not hire Africans. As noted previously, little<br />

of China’s investment in Africa constitutes<br />

aid, thus there are less resources spent on<br />

educational and vocational training. Since the<br />

first FOCAC meeting in 2000, total number<br />

of job and education initiatives pledged are in<br />

the tens of thousands. 90 This does not put a<br />

dent into the hundreds of millions in Africa<br />

that are unemployed or are seeking<br />

opportunities to acquire new skills for higher<br />

paying jobs, at least $2 day.<br />

Many question if the infrastructure<br />

being developed is really intended for the<br />

benefit of Africa. It seems that the<br />

infrastructure built so far is just to help<br />

Chinese companies import their cheap goods<br />

for sale in Africa and for state owned<br />

companies to move natural resources out. 91<br />

China’s aid mainly finances the building of<br />

roads, railways, and ports that mostly serve<br />

the needs of Chinese firms. What Africa<br />

really needs are telecommunications and<br />

energy infrastructure --Electricity is a pressing<br />

social and economic need; according to<br />

USAID 70% of people in Sub Saharan Africa<br />

are without adequate power. 92 However,<br />

these kinds of projects are costly and do not<br />

provide fast returns for developers. Also,<br />

Chinese investment has been used to build<br />

lavish public buildings and sports arenas.<br />

These “white elephants” serve no practical<br />

purposes, but are popular and help politicians<br />

score political points. 93 It also remains to be<br />

90 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 210,213.<br />

91 Robert Rotberg, China into Africa: Trade, Aid,<br />

and Influence (Cambridge: Brookings Institution<br />

Press, 2008), 73.<br />

92 About Power Africa, USAID,<br />

http://www.usaid.gov/powerafrica/about-powerafrica.<br />

93 Rachel Will, “China’s Stadium Diplomacy,”<br />

World Policy Institute, 2012,<br />

http://www.worldpolicy.org/journal/summer2012/<br />

chinas-stadium-diplomacy.<br />

seen how the Special Economic Zones are<br />

going to help, which are mainly in being set<br />

up near ports and resource extraction points.<br />

It is not clear what description best<br />

portrays contemporary China-African<br />

relations, but it is certain that it cannot be<br />

considered strictly exploitative and neocolonialism.<br />

Yes, China is interested in<br />

Africa’s natural resources, but China is<br />

purchasing it from African countries and even<br />

providing social assistance as well. This is<br />

distinctly different from European countries<br />

that robbed Africa of its resources and<br />

inhabitants. Furthermore, China does not<br />

exploit African labor, as Chinese firms go to<br />

great lengths to avoid using African workers.<br />

What we do know is that it is not a<br />

“win-win” relationship between China and the<br />

African continent. China has been adamant<br />

about respecting the sovereignty of its African<br />

partners, but the relationship it will have with<br />

its African partners is extremely asymmetrical.<br />

We must disaggregate our view of Africa. All<br />

54 African countries do not work together<br />

and coordinate their foreign policy with<br />

China. Rather, they all have varying amounts<br />

of resources and forms of leverage when<br />

dealing with China. However, ultimately<br />

China will get its way. This is not to say China<br />

will be exploitative, but it is hard to say no to<br />

China. Very few African governments, even<br />

those getting a raw deal, will push back. In<br />

2012, South African president Jacob Zouma<br />

spoke out about the asymmetry in trade with<br />

China. 94 South Africa has a large trade deficit<br />

with China and its textile industry has been<br />

decimated by cheap Chinese imports over the<br />

last decade. But little has changed and trade<br />

continues.<br />

Despite some incidents of social<br />

unrest, there are no pervasive feelings of a<br />

94 Ed Cropley and Michael Martina, “Insight: In<br />

Africa’s Warm heart, a Cold Welcome for<br />

Chinese,” Reuters, 9/18/2012,<br />

http://www.reuters.com/article/2012/09/18/usafrica-china-pushbackidUSBRE88H0CR20120918.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 19


“China problem” by Africans. There is little<br />

research on how Africans feel about the<br />

Chinese, but there is no evidence to support<br />

the claims by Western media and Chinese<br />

officials that anti-Chinese sentiments are<br />

common. 95 A 2007 study by Barry Suatman<br />

and Yan Hairong based on polling of<br />

university students in various African<br />

countries, showed that favorability of the<br />

Chinese varied markedly by country, that<br />

there was no “African consensus.” 96 Though,<br />

economic relations seem to be a good<br />

barometer for support. Polls show that those<br />

in African countries that have a trade deficit<br />

with China will more likely express anti-<br />

Chinese sentiments and vice versa. 97<br />

Although China’s economic influence<br />

in Africa has increased markedly over the last<br />

decade, it is still quite modest compared to the<br />

West. This needs to be considered when<br />

assessing whether or not Africa is becoming<br />

China’s colony. In 1990, trade with China<br />

represented just 0.75% of Africa’s total trade<br />

and today it less than 14%. 98 For China, trade<br />

with Africa accounts for less than 3% of its<br />

total trade. 99 China did not surpass the U.S.<br />

to become Africa’s largest trading partner<br />

until 2009, and even then, the total stock of<br />

Chinese commercial investments in Africa<br />

was $1 billion, compared to the U.S.’s $96<br />

95 Julia Strauss and Martha Saavedra, China<br />

and Africa: Emerging Patterns in Globalization<br />

and Development (United Kingdom: Cambridge<br />

University Press), 179.<br />

96 Julia Strauss and Martha Saavedra, China<br />

and Africa: Emerging Patterns in Globalization<br />

and Development (United Kingdom: Cambridge<br />

University Press), 186.<br />

97 Larry Hanauer and Lyle Morris, Chinese<br />

Engagement In Africa: Drivers, Reactions, and<br />

Implications for U.S. Policy (Washington, D.C. :<br />

Rand Corporation, 2014),61.<br />

98 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 116.<br />

99 ibid.<br />

billion. 100 China’s numbers for foreign direct<br />

investment are quite low as well. China is<br />

investing on average $1.5 billion in Africa<br />

annually, but this is less than 3% of their total<br />

global FDI. 101 To put that in context, about<br />

70% of its FDI goes to Asia and 15% to Latin<br />

America. 102<br />

CONCLUSION-LOOKING FORWARD<br />

China’s contemporary engagement<br />

with the African continent is without<br />

precedent and it is too soon to tell how it will<br />

pan out. There are, however, some parts of<br />

the relationship that can have a significant<br />

impact down the line. China claims to adhere<br />

to a policy of “non-interference.” Though, its<br />

increasing military and peacekeeping presence<br />

is testing the limits of this policy. Another<br />

thing to watch for is the growing debt being<br />

accumulated by various African countries.<br />

Even mineral rich countries like Angola may<br />

have problems paying back debts if<br />

commodity prices drop. So far no evidence<br />

exists that they are too burdensome, but the<br />

historical precedence of African countries<br />

being indebted to foreign creditors is hard to<br />

ignore. What will China do then?<br />

It is hard to draw a parallel between<br />

China’s resource trade with Africa today and<br />

the resource extraction undertaken by<br />

European empires throughout history that<br />

colonized Africa. This was done through<br />

slavery of the indigenous population and<br />

appropriation of natural resources without<br />

any compensation. Though at the same time<br />

we must also recognize that China’s interest in<br />

Africa’s natural resources is exploitative and<br />

self-serving.<br />

100 Dorothy-Grace Guerrero and Firoze Manji,<br />

China’s New Role in Africa and the South: A<br />

Search for a New Perspective (Nairobi, Kenya:<br />

Fahamu-Networks for Social Justice),93.<br />

101 David Shinn and Joshua Eisenman , China<br />

and Africa: A Century of Engagement<br />

(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

2012) , 133.<br />

102 ibid .<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 20


Moreover, China is trying to highlight<br />

its differences from its Western predecessors,<br />

attempting to avoid the replication of the<br />

paternalistic view the West has of Africa. For<br />

centuries the West has been trying different<br />

strategies to civilize, modernize, and develop<br />

Africa. Investing in Africa and developing the<br />

continent’s infrastructure should be seen as a<br />

means by China to help increase Africa’s selfsufficiency.<br />

China does not seem to be<br />

interested in trying to export its politicaleconomic<br />

model or to “sinify” Africa.<br />

Ultimately, it is seeking an economic<br />

partnership with Africa that is based on their<br />

long history of solidarity.<br />

This phase of Chinese-African relations is still<br />

quite new and the mixed signals economic<br />

indicators give make it hard to gauge the<br />

impact of China’s investments. It is and will<br />

continue to be difficult to decipher China’s<br />

motives for providing aid and assistance to<br />

Africa. Though, if this relationship does yield<br />

mutual economic benefit and increasing<br />

political cooperation then does China’s<br />

motives really matter? Further research on the<br />

impact all this investment and cooperation is<br />

having on Africa is needed.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 21


Conflict Escalation,<br />

Signaling and Screening<br />

Compatibility or Competition?<br />

Kazumichi Uchida<br />

INTRODUCTION<br />

W<br />

hat is the cause of war under<br />

conditions of asymmetric<br />

information?Some argue that<br />

war is caused by states’ failure in<br />

deterrence of preemptive attacks, while others<br />

argue that it is caused by states’ fear of other<br />

states’ intention. By focusing on how states<br />

exchange their resolves to resort to military<br />

forces designed to prevent preemptive attacks,<br />

this study explores the causes of war under<br />

conditions of asymmetric information.<br />

States need to deter its neighbors<br />

from aggressive actions; however, they also<br />

need to relieve them at the same time. If a<br />

state puts too much stress on deterrence, it<br />

may frighten the neighbors, which encourages<br />

them to attack preemptively. Thus, it is<br />

difficult for all states to declare their<br />

intentions in a proper manner under<br />

conditions of asymmetric information.<br />

The Gulf War in 1990-91 provides a<br />

good example of the central issues. Before<br />

invading Kuwait, Iraqi President Saddam<br />

Hussein made a variety of demands of<br />

Kuwait. 103 However, neither Kuwait nor the<br />

United States ever tried to determine the<br />

concession point at which Saddam would<br />

have been satisfied by making increasingly<br />

generous offers. 104 As a result, they failed to<br />

deter Saddam’s invasion. In this sense, the war<br />

was caused by their failure of deterrence.<br />

In the meantime, Washington also<br />

failed to reassure Saddam through the<br />

103 Janice Gross Stein, “Deterrence and<br />

Compellence in the Gulf, 1990-91: – A Failed or<br />

Impossible Task?,” International Security, 17<br />

(1992): 147-7.<br />

104 Ibid, 159-60.<br />

signaling of benign intentions. In those days,<br />

Saddam regarded America as an imperialist<br />

power bent on economic warfare against the<br />

Arab world. Washington, however, sent<br />

ineffective signals that increased Saddam’s<br />

suspicion of the United States’ intention. 105 As<br />

a result, the United States failed to reassure<br />

Saddam and encouraged him to invade<br />

Kuwait. In this sense, the war was caused by<br />

their failure of reassurance.<br />

Today, states have developed a<br />

variety of techniques to overcome asymmetric<br />

information. Some might declare their<br />

determination by taking costly actions such as<br />

arms buildups, while some might test their<br />

neighbors’ limits by making proposals. The<br />

most important point of those techniques is<br />

to interchange their resolution with each other<br />

in a proper manner. This paper seeks to<br />

clarify under what condition states can<br />

transmit their resolves effectively and address<br />

the problem, and under what condition they<br />

fail in transmission and war is likely.<br />

This article proceeds as follows.<br />

First, I review previous studies and their<br />

deficiencies, and propose ways of correcting<br />

these defects. Second, I present a basic model<br />

that makes it possible to consider the<br />

compatibility of both signaling and screening.<br />

Based on this model, I clarify several findings<br />

regarding when war is more likely and when it<br />

is less likely.<br />

THEORETICAL BACKGROUND<br />

Prevention of the Preemptive Attacks<br />

In existing literatures on the causes<br />

of war, many have argued that the main cause<br />

of war is the gap between distribution of<br />

power and distribution of benefit, meaning<br />

that the greater the disparity between<br />

distribution of power and distribution of<br />

benefit, the more likely war will occur. 106 If a<br />

105 Ibid, 161-65.<br />

106 Robert Powell, In the Shadow of Power:<br />

States and Strategies in International Politics<br />

(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999), 6;<br />

Suzanne Werner, “The Precarious Nature of<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 22


state feels that it is not getting its fair share of<br />

benefits, it has an incentive to change the<br />

status quo, and that includes use of force.<br />

The relevant diplomatic policies for<br />

the prevention of such calamities combine<br />

Deterrence and Reassurance. 107 Deterrence<br />

here is defined as the use of threats to<br />

dissuade an opponent from undertaking<br />

damaging actions in the future. 108 The origin<br />

of bargaining theory in international relations<br />

can be found in James Fearon’s Rationalist<br />

Explanations for War. 109 Assuming that a state’s<br />

resolve is based in asymmetric information,<br />

Fearon has attempted to elaborate the causes<br />

of war by observing whether it can send<br />

proper signals to deter other states. 110 Thus,<br />

war could be regarded as the failure of<br />

deterrence.<br />

In contrast, Reassurance is defined as<br />

the communication of benign and<br />

unaggressive intentions by the defender to the<br />

prospective challenger. 111 Hence, deterrence is<br />

designed to use aggressive intentions to<br />

dissuade the opponent from preemptive<br />

attack, while reassurance relies on the<br />

demonstration of benign intentions. Robert<br />

Powell’s In the Shadow of Power developed the<br />

theory by starting with the rigid assumption<br />

that the gap between the distribution of<br />

benefits and the distribution of power causes<br />

Peace: Resolving the Issues, Enforcing the<br />

Settlement, and Renegotiation the Terms,”<br />

American Journal of Political Science, 43 (1999):<br />

929.<br />

107 Richard Lebow, “Deterrence and<br />

Reassurance: Lessons from the Cold War,”<br />

Global Dialogue, 3 (2001): 128.<br />

108 Alexander George, Forceful Persuasion:<br />

Coercive Diplomacy as an Alternative to War<br />

(Washington, DC: United States Institute of<br />

Peace Press, 1991), 5.<br />

109 James D. Fearon, “Rationalist Explanations<br />

for War,” International Organization 49 (3): 379-<br />

414.<br />

110 James D. Fearon, “Signaling Foreign Policy<br />

Interests: Tying Hands versus Sinking Costs,”<br />

Journal of Conflict Resolution 41 (1): 68-90.<br />

111 Lebow, “Deterrence and Reassurance:<br />

Lessons from the Cold War,” 432.<br />

war. 112 Powell thus argued that the failure of<br />

concessions that states make to other states is<br />

the decisive cause of war. If states succeed in<br />

making concessions to other states properly,<br />

they can settle disputes. In other words, the<br />

failure of reassurance could cause a war.<br />

Asymmetric information<br />

Then, why do states fail to take those<br />

measures against preemptive attacks? The<br />

main reason is that every state has an<br />

incentive to misrepresent its resolve under<br />

conditions of asymmetric information. 113<br />

Hence, every state questions the credibility of<br />

other states’ discourses, and needs a way to<br />

make their messages credible in order to reach<br />

agreements with other states and avoid<br />

unnecessary wars becomes paramount. There<br />

are two potential means of making messages<br />

credible: Signaling and Screening. Signaling is<br />

defined as taking action to make threats to use<br />

force credible. 114 For example, if a state leader<br />

decides to expand troop numbers or to<br />

declare publicly that the state will resist if<br />

attacked, it can declare its resolution more<br />

strongly to other states. 115<br />

Screening is defined as the<br />

identification of how much degree an<br />

opponent is resolved through the use of<br />

increasingly generous proposals that facilitate<br />

112 Powell, In the Shadow of Power: States and<br />

Strategies in International Politics, 86 – 104.<br />

113 James D. Fearon, “Rationalist Explanations<br />

for War,” International Organization, 49<br />

(1995) :379- 414. Recent studies have tended to<br />

emphasize the Commitment Problem as an<br />

explanatory cause of war. However, the analysis<br />

of that factor requires a firm basis in Fearon’s<br />

first explanatory variable, Asymmetric<br />

Information, which I thus focus on as the cause<br />

of war in this study.<br />

114 Fearon, “Signaling Foreign Policy Interests:<br />

Tying Hands Versus Sinking Costs,” 69.<br />

115 James D. Fearon, “Domestic Political<br />

Audiences and the Escalation of International<br />

Disputes,” American Political Science Review,<br />

88 (1994): 577- 92.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 23


settling early with the weakly resolved types. 116<br />

For example, if a state suggests a rigorous<br />

proposal on some issue to an opponent and<br />

the opponent accepts it quickly, it can be<br />

assumed that an opponent is not resolved so<br />

Signaling Screening<br />

Deterrence Fearon (1997) ×<br />

Reassurance × Powell (1999)<br />

much to fight over the issue.<br />

Therefore, in this section, two main<br />

points could be drawn: First, states fail either<br />

in deterrence or reassurance due to<br />

asymmetric information. Second, states<br />

overcome asymmetric information by means<br />

of signaling and screening.<br />

Table 1. Diplomatic Policy and its Techniques<br />

In previous studies, many scholars<br />

have looked into conditions and success<br />

factors for either signaling or screening<br />

separately, but not together. However, wars<br />

have occurred because these two techniques<br />

have not been compatible. 117 This study<br />

assumes that it is important to examine the<br />

compatibility of signaling and screening and to<br />

find the conditions under which we can<br />

achieve both at the same time, and thus clarify<br />

the cause of war.<br />

Convergence of States’ Beliefs<br />

How can previous research be<br />

modified in order to address the problem? As<br />

mentioned, signaling and screening need to be<br />

examined in combination in order to analyze<br />

the causes of war. In addition to Powell’s,<br />

Slantchev (2003) argues that even though<br />

there is a great disparity in capability among<br />

states, a weaker state may threaten to provoke<br />

a war in order to induce a stronger state to<br />

offer better terms. 118 Therefore, expectations<br />

need to converge not only with respect to the<br />

distribution of power, but also the resolve of<br />

states, in order to prevent preemptive attacks<br />

from weaker actors.<br />

The next section will examine how<br />

and under what conditions states’<br />

expectations about both the distribution of<br />

power and the resolve of states converge. And<br />

this convergence is necessary in order to<br />

prevent preemptive attacks.<br />

THEORETICAL ANALYSIS<br />

Assume that two states in<br />

international system argue over strategic<br />

resources such as oil, coal, or territory. The<br />

total amount of resources is normalized as 1.<br />

In addition, let us assume that state 1 is a<br />

defending state, while state 2 is a challenging<br />

state.<br />

Let π ! be the expected utility of state 1, let p<br />

(0 ≤ p < 1) be the probability of winning of<br />

state 1, let v ! be the war value of state 1, and<br />

let c be the cost of war. To put it simply, I<br />

assume that if they win, they gain everything,<br />

while if they lose, they lose everything. 119<br />

π ! = v ! ∙ p ∙ 1 + 1 − p ∙ 0 − c<br />

= p ∙ v ! − c<br />

In the same fashion, we can express the utility<br />

of state 2 as,<br />

π ! = q ∙ v ! − c (where p + q = 1).<br />

Note that p also stands for the<br />

balance of power in this international system<br />

or how resources are shared among states.<br />

This is because the distribution of resources<br />

among states is determined by the probability<br />

of winning wars.<br />

116 Scott Wolford, Dan Reiter, and Clifford<br />

Carrubba, “Information, Commitment, and War,”<br />

Journal of Conflict Resolution, 55 (2011): 567.<br />

117 Branislav L. Slantchev, “The Principle of<br />

Convergence in Wartime Negotiations,”<br />

American Political Science Review, 97 (2003):<br />

626.<br />

118 Ibid. 621-32.<br />

119 This model is consistent with those of Fearon<br />

(1997) and Wagner (2000) in the sense that it<br />

takes war to be a costly lottery. Harrison<br />

Wagner, “Bargaining and War,” American<br />

Journal of Political Science, 44 (2000): 470.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 24


Figure 1. Conflict Resolution and Escalation<br />

q <br />

RESOLUTION<br />

Reaction Function of<br />

State 1<br />

q <br />

and amount to peaceful resolution. The lower<br />

bound of this range is a signaling point, while<br />

its upper bound is a screening point, and they<br />

stand respectively for the minimum and<br />

maximum bounds necessary for convergence<br />

of belief. From here forward, I deduce those<br />

two points, which must be compatible to<br />

achieve their diplomatic purposes in this<br />

model.<br />

q ∗ <br />

p ∗ <br />

p ∗<br />

Reaction Function of<br />

State 2<br />

ESCALATION<br />

Reaction Function of<br />

State 1<br />

As shown in Figure 1 above, I define<br />

the resolution of conflict as the convergence<br />

of beliefs about the probability of winning a<br />

war, while I define the escalation of conflict as<br />

the divergence of beliefs in that regard. The<br />

reason why we can define conflict as shown<br />

above is because if their beliefs converge, they<br />

have no incentive to change the status quo; if<br />

they diverge, they do have an incentive to<br />

change the status quo. The same rule is<br />

applicable to states’ resolve, according to the<br />

explanation by Slantchev (2003).<br />

There is some latitude in states’<br />

actions within which their beliefs converge<br />

p <br />

Reaction Function of<br />

State 2<br />

p <br />

q ∗<br />

Proposition 1<br />

Let p = ! v !<br />

! − 2v ! + 2α (where α is a real<br />

number).<br />

In the equilibrium, if p > p, the conflict is<br />

resolved, while if p < p, the conflict is<br />

escalated.<br />

Proof: See Appendix.<br />

This proposition has several<br />

implications. First, p stands for the signaling<br />

point, meaning the minimum amount by which<br />

state 1 should demonstrate its resolve through<br />

activities such as increasing or deploying<br />

troops in order to make its message credible.<br />

If state 1 demonstrates resolve to less than<br />

this degree, other states will think that state 1<br />

is not resolved and will be tempted to take<br />

advantage of it. Therefore, if state 1 seeks to<br />

make its signal credible, it should go at least to<br />

the degree p, which leads to conflict<br />

resolution. This is because its belief in p<br />

converges with the equilibrium point, and no<br />

other states take action.<br />

Proposition 2<br />

Let p = !<br />

! ! !! !<br />

− ! ! v ! ! + ! ! v ! ! + 2v ! v ! +<br />

v ! − β ∙ v ! .<br />

In the equilibrium, if p < p, the conflict is<br />

resolved, while if p > p, the conflict is<br />

escalated.<br />

If we let A= v ! + v ! , we can get p = ! ! A +<br />

!! !<br />

! ! !!! !!<br />

!<br />

(where β is a real number).<br />

Proof: See Appendix<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 25


This proposition also has several<br />

implications. First, p stands for the screening<br />

point, meaning the maximum degree by which<br />

state 1 should demonstrate its resolve in the<br />

effort to make its message credible. The<br />

reason for regarding the maximum point as<br />

the screening point is that it is necessary for a<br />

state to determine the maximum amount it<br />

can gain in searching for an opponent’s<br />

resolve. If it crosses the limit, other states will<br />

get cautious and take some action against it. If<br />

state 1 wants to make its discourses credible,<br />

it should go at most to this point because here<br />

beliefs in p converge.<br />

Proposition 3<br />

In the equilibrium, if p < p < p, the conflict<br />

is resolved; otherwise, it is escalated.<br />

Proof: From the two propositions above, we can<br />

deduce that this proposition is inevitable.<br />

The most striking aspect of this<br />

proposition is that just by putting p at any<br />

point within this range, state 1 can make its<br />

messages credible and conflicts among states<br />

will be resolved. This is because any point<br />

within this range is Nash Equilibria: everyone<br />

will think that state 1 has no incentive to<br />

misrepresent its resolve within this range.<br />

Now we can think about three cases.<br />

In the first case, the range between p and p<br />

expands. In this case, it becomes easier for<br />

states to put p within this range and to resolve<br />

conflicts. More formally, if p ≡ ! v !<br />

! −<br />

2v ! + 2α decreases and p ≡ ! A + !<br />

!! !<br />

! ! !!! !!<br />

increases, it becomes easier to<br />

!<br />

converge expectations. I call this area the<br />

security zone.<br />

The second case we will consider is<br />

one in which the range between p and p<br />

shrinks. In this case, it becomes more difficult<br />

for states to put p within this range and<br />

resolve conflicts. More formally, if p ≡<br />

!<br />

! v ! − 2v ! + 2α increases and p ≡ ! ! A +<br />

!! !<br />

! ! !!! !!<br />

decreases, it becomes more<br />

!<br />

difficult to converge expectations. I call this<br />

area the danger zone. I represent these two areas<br />

graphically in Figure 2 below. However, I<br />

omit two variables, α and β, from the<br />

calculation for simplicity.<br />

Figure 2. The Security Zone and the Danger<br />

Zone<br />

Finally, let us consider a case in which p goes<br />

ahead of p and there is no room for states to<br />

take any measures to prevent war. More<br />

formally, if ! ! v ! − 2v ! + 2α > ! ! A +<br />

!! !<br />

! ! !!! !!<br />

!<br />

v ! <br />

Security Zone<br />

1<br />

4<br />

0 <br />

1<br />

2<br />

Danger Zone<br />

, that is, if<br />

v ! = v !<br />

!<br />

<br />

v ! <br />

v ! = 1 2 v ! <br />

v ! < ! !! !! ! !! ! !!<br />

, ! !! !! ! !! ! !!<br />

< v<br />

!<br />

!<br />

! ,<br />

the expectations of states never converge.<br />

This indicates that if the resolve of state 1 is<br />

either too much or too little, they have no<br />

choice but to go to war.<br />

Based on this analysis, we can<br />

deduce several findings. The main finding is<br />

that war is more likely if the resolve of a<br />

challenging state exceeds half that of a<br />

defending state, while war is less likely if the<br />

resolve of a challenging state falls short of half<br />

that of a defending state. Note that ! : ! ! !<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 26


equates to 2: 1, which represents the<br />

proportion of defending states and<br />

challenging ones.<br />

In addition, war is less likely only<br />

when the resolve of both states is positive;<br />

and the resolve of defending states should be<br />

neither too high nor too low; paradoxically, if<br />

defending states are too resolved, they are<br />

significantly damaged as well.<br />

TESTS OF THE THEORY<br />

The theory above will be tested<br />

according to two criteria. 120 First, what<br />

predictions can be inferred from the above<br />

theory? Second, how much history does this<br />

theory explain?<br />

Predictions and Tests<br />

The theory’s predictions derived<br />

from its primary hypothesis. Namely, that war<br />

is more likely if the resolve of challenging<br />

states exceeds half that of defending states,<br />

while war is less likely if the resolve of<br />

challenging states falls short of half that of<br />

defending states. The following two<br />

predictions based on this theory are tested in a<br />

case study of the Gulf War of 1990-91. The<br />

outcomes vary sharply across time, creating a<br />

good setting for multiple within–case<br />

comparisons tests that contrast different<br />

periods within the same case. 121<br />

Defending states succeed in<br />

prevention of preemptive attacks if the<br />

resolve of challenging states’ does not exceed<br />

the proportion.<br />

Defending states fail in prevention of<br />

preemptive attacks if the resolve of<br />

challenging states’ exceeds the proportion.<br />

Test 1: Failure in Prevention<br />

120 Stephen Van Evera, Guide to Methods for<br />

Students of Political Science (Ithaca, NY:<br />

Cornell University Press, 1997); Stephen Van<br />

Evera, “Offense, Defense, and the Causes of<br />

War,” International Security, 22 (1998): 22.<br />

121 Stephen Van Evera, Guide to Methods for<br />

Students of Political Science, 58-63.<br />

Just before he decided to invade<br />

Kuwait, he assumed that the outcome of the<br />

Iran-Iraq war had propelled Iraq into the<br />

leadership of the Arab world in the post-Cold<br />

War era. This outcome imposed upon Iraq the<br />

duty to deter both Iranian hordes and Israeli<br />

adventurism, which spurred Iraq to<br />

reconstruct its economy and to expand its<br />

industrial-technological infrastructure. This<br />

could only be achieved by means of its oil<br />

revenues. 122<br />

At the end of May 1990, during an<br />

Arab summit meeting convened in Baghdad,<br />

Saddam denounced the Arabs of the Gulf<br />

who were keeping the price of oil artificially<br />

low by producing beyond their OPEC quotas<br />

- to such an extent that the price in certain<br />

instances had plummeted to $7 per barrel,<br />

although the agreed-upon price was $18 per<br />

barrel-, and thereby engaging in economic<br />

sabotage of Iraq. 123 In a memorandum dated<br />

July 15, addressed to the Secretary-General of<br />

the United Nations, Iraqi Foreign Minister<br />

Tariq Aziz explicitly named Kuwait and the<br />

United Arab Emirates as the two “culprits” in<br />

overproduction. 124 To make matters worse,<br />

during the hostilities with Iran, Kuwait was<br />

drawing more than its allotment from the<br />

shared northern Rumaila oil field, whose<br />

122 Walid Khalidi, “Iraq vs. Kuwait: Claims and<br />

Counterclaims” in The Gulf War Reader, ed.<br />

Micah Sifry and Christopher Cerf (Ithaca, NY:<br />

TimesBooks /Random House, 1991), 60-61.<br />

123 Janice Gross Stein, “Deterrence and<br />

Compellence in the Gulf, 1990-91 –A Failed or<br />

Impossible Task?,” International Security 17 (2):<br />

147-179; Walid Khalidi, “Iraq vs. Kuwait” in The<br />

Gulf War Reader, ed. Micah Sifry and<br />

Christopher Cerf (Ithaca, NY: TimesBooks<br />

/Random House, 1991), 63.<br />

124 Bishara A. Bahbah, “The Crisis in the Gulf: –<br />

Why Iraq Invaded Kuwait” in Phyllis Bennis and<br />

Michel Moushabeck, eds., Beyond The Storm: –<br />

A Gulf Crisis Reader (New York: Olive Branch<br />

Press, 1991), 52-3; Walid Khalidi, “Iraq vs.<br />

Kuwait,” 63.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 27


southern tip straddled the border inland from<br />

the Gulf. 125<br />

On July 16, at Saddam’s request,<br />

Aziz sent a memorandum to Kuwait<br />

demanding $2.4 billion in compensation for<br />

oil that Kuwait had pumped from the<br />

disputed Rumaila oil field; $12 billion in<br />

compensation for the depressed oil prices<br />

brought about by Kuwait’s overproduction;<br />

forgiveness of Iraq’s war debt of $10 billion;<br />

and a lease on the strategic island of Bubiyan<br />

that controlled access to Iraq’s only port,<br />

Umm Qasr. 126 Irrespective of the mediation<br />

efforts of King Fahd of Saudi Arabia,<br />

President Hosni Mubarak of Egypt, and King<br />

Hussein of Jordan, on July 24, two Iraqi<br />

armored divisions moved from their bases to<br />

positions on Kuwait’s border. 127<br />

While the crisis was intensified,<br />

Washington’s signals to Iraq were ambiguous<br />

and contradictory. 128 On July 25, Saddam<br />

asked to meet with Ambassador April Glaspie<br />

within the hour, in response to the U. S. joint<br />

military exercises with the United Arab<br />

Emirates the previous day. Glaspie assured<br />

Saddam that the United States should express<br />

no opinion on the Kuwait issue, and that the<br />

issue was not associated with them. She then<br />

asked Saddam about the intention of Iraqi<br />

troop movements to the border with Kuwait.<br />

He informed her that he had just asked<br />

President Mubarak to assure Kuwait that they<br />

would do nothing until they held meetings.<br />

125 Walid Khalidi, “Iraq vs. Kuwait,” 63.<br />

126 Janice Gross Stein, “Deterrence and<br />

Compellence in the Gulf, 1990-91 –A Failed or<br />

Impossible Task?,” International Security 17 (2):<br />

147-179.<br />

127 “Kuwait: How The West Blundered”, in The<br />

Gulf War Reader, ed. Micah Sifry and<br />

Christopher Cerf (Ithaca, NY: TimesBooks<br />

/Random House, 1991), 104; Janice Gross<br />

Stein, “Deterrence and Compellence in the Gulf,<br />

1990-91 –A Failed or Impossible Task?,” 147-<br />

179.<br />

128 Janice Gross Stein, “Deterrence and<br />

Compellence in the Gulf, 1990-91 –A Failed or<br />

Impossible Task?,” 147-179.<br />

He added that if there were any hope in<br />

negotiations, nothing would happen, while if<br />

they were unable to find a solution, it would<br />

be natural for Iraq not to accept death. 129 This<br />

statement was designed to satisfy Ambassador<br />

Glaspie. Her assumption was that the Iraqi<br />

tanks were meant to intimidate Kuwait at the<br />

negotiating table, and that they would<br />

probably succeed in doing so. She found it<br />

tolerable. 130<br />

We can assume from the<br />

appearances that the resolve of Iraq was<br />

intensified day by day, while the United States<br />

was not resolved at all, which made war more<br />

and more likely. Saddam also thought that the<br />

United States would not wage war due to their<br />

Vietnam complex and the low tolerance of the<br />

American public to U.S. causalities. 131 Early in<br />

the morning on August 2, two Iraqi armored<br />

divisions spearheaded the attack against<br />

Kuwait.<br />

Test 2: Success in Prevention<br />

At the first full National Security<br />

Council (NSC) meeting after the Iraqi<br />

invasion of Kuwait on August 2, 1991,<br />

Schwarzkopf outlined two military options for<br />

the U.S. response: (1) punitive air strikes by<br />

carrier-based aircraft, and (2) a detailed<br />

existing contingency plan, Operation Plan<br />

(OP) 90-1002, which called for deploying<br />

more than four divisions and three aircraft<br />

carriers, for a total of 100,000 to 200,000 U.S.<br />

troops. The key divide in this August 3<br />

meeting was between National Security<br />

Advisor Brent Scowcroft and Secretary of<br />

Defense Richard Cheney, who favored an<br />

expansive response, and Chairman of the<br />

Joint Chiefs of Staff General Colin Powell,<br />

129 “Kuwait: How The West Blundered”, 104-5;<br />

Janice Gross Stein, “Deterrence and<br />

Compellence in the Gulf, 1990-91 –A Failed or<br />

Impossible Task?,” 147-179.<br />

130 “Kuwait: How The West Blundered,” 105.<br />

131 Bishara A. Bahbah, “The Crisis in the Gulf,”<br />

54.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 28


who remained more cautious about<br />

committing U.S. military power and<br />

advocated the more limited goal of defending<br />

Saudi Arabia from further Iraqi aggression. In<br />

Powell’s view, which became known as the<br />

“Powell Doctrine,” the military was to be<br />

used as a last resort, and only then in an<br />

overwhelming fashion. By this time, however,<br />

President Bush had already begun to lean<br />

toward OP 90-1002, the “rollback” option<br />

over the more limited goal of<br />

“containment.” 132<br />

The official Saudi “invitation” for<br />

U.S. military intervention came on August<br />

7. 133 The next day, August 8, a Defense<br />

Intelligence Agency officer informed Prince<br />

Bandar of what had happened during the<br />

Kuwait invasion and how Saddam was<br />

massing the same elite force of eight divisions<br />

on the Saudi border. 134<br />

From then on, the U.S. was<br />

strengthening their signals to deter Iraq from<br />

invading Saudi Arabia, but at an incremental<br />

rate in order to reassure Iraq rather than<br />

encourage a preemptive attack. The first signal<br />

was sent on August 17 by U.S. officials<br />

including Defense Secretary Cheney. They<br />

intentionally leaked word to the Associated<br />

Press that the U.S. was preparing for a “long<br />

commitment” in the Gulf. 135 They also leaked<br />

the real number of troops up to 250,000 to<br />

the press. 136 The next signal was the<br />

Pentagon’s exponentially inflated troop<br />

projections needed to “defend” Saudi Arabia<br />

against an Iraqi attack. On August 22, the<br />

president called up an initial 40,000 members<br />

132 Jonathan Monten and Andrew Bennett,<br />

“Models of Crisis Decision Making and the 1990-<br />

91 Gulf War,” International Security, 19<br />

(2010):498-503.<br />

133 Steve Niva, “The Battle is Joined,” in Beyond<br />

The Storm: – A Gulf Crisis Reader, ed. Michel<br />

Moushabeck and Phyllis Bennis (New York:<br />

Olive Branch Press, 1991), 57.<br />

134 Bob Woodward, The Commanders (New<br />

York: Simon and Schuster, 1991), 278.<br />

135 Steve Niva, “The Battle is Joined,” 59.<br />

136 Bob Woodward, The Commanders, 297.<br />

of military reserve units, and by September 6<br />

the number of troops in Saudi Arabia had<br />

reached 100,000. On September 15, U.S.<br />

officials announced they had established a<br />

credible defense and were now building up<br />

their offensive capability. 137 Finally, on<br />

September 21, U.S. intelligence claimed that<br />

Saddam‘s forces were digging in, moving into<br />

even more defensive positions. This made an<br />

offensive attack by Saddam into Saudi Arabia<br />

less likely. 138<br />

In those days, when air power was<br />

not as well recognized, it was ground troops<br />

more than airstrikes what showed the<br />

governments’ resolve. Saddam had moved his<br />

eight divisions, an estimated 100,000 men, to<br />

the Saudi border while the United States went<br />

public with the concrete number of troops<br />

who would be sent to defend Saudi Arabia<br />

and then put the plan into practice. What is<br />

important in this study is the fact that when<br />

Saddam recognized that the United States put<br />

twice as many troops as his on the Saudi<br />

border, he gave up invading Saudi Arabia.<br />

This corroborates the prediction that<br />

defending states succeed in both deterrence<br />

and reassurance when their resolve exceeds<br />

twice that of challenging states’.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

This article argues that war is more<br />

likely when the resolve of challenging states<br />

exceeds twice that of defending states. With<br />

respect to the causes of war, states cannot<br />

achieve both diplomatic policies, namely,<br />

deterrence and reassurance, at the same time<br />

unless they combine the techniques of<br />

signaling and screening.<br />

Based on the assumption that war<br />

can be represented as the divergence of state<br />

beliefs about the probability of winning and<br />

state resolve, I establish the minimum and<br />

maximum points necessary for their beliefs to<br />

converge, which can be defined as signaling<br />

and screening points. I then assume that if<br />

137 Steve Niva, “The Battle is Joined,” 59.<br />

138 Bob Woodward, The Commanders, 297.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 29


those ranges expand, it becomes easy for<br />

states to determine the points that are<br />

necessary for the settling of disputes, and vice<br />

versa. This enables me to present the<br />

hypotheses mentioned above.<br />

I deduce several predictions from those<br />

hypotheses, which are tested with the case of<br />

the Gulf War of 1990-91, which is rich in<br />

both political success and failure. I then<br />

demonstrate that these predictions correlated<br />

with what happened in the Gulf.<br />

This study leaves many themes of<br />

remaining research. The first topic we need to<br />

tackle is how to deal with the influence of<br />

state growth, which is categorized as a<br />

commitment problem. In order to complete<br />

the research, we need to consider a dynamic<br />

version of this model by introducing new<br />

variables such as the growth rates of states.<br />

Some previous research has already tackled<br />

this problem with distinguished<br />

implications. 139 What we need to do next is to<br />

combine these achievements with the findings<br />

of this research in order to improve the ways<br />

in which states can achieve their diplomatic<br />

purposes, even when there is a great disparity<br />

in growth rates among states.<br />

APPENDIX<br />

Proof of Proposition 1<br />

Consider the Cournot Equilibrium.<br />

The reason why I consider the Cournot<br />

Equilibrium is because in equilibrium both<br />

actors’ beliefs about the probability of<br />

winning war are supposed to converge.<br />

Thus, I start with both actors’ reaction<br />

functions so that their beliefs will converge as<br />

a result of their profit maximizations.<br />

Assume that state 1 is a defender,<br />

and its reaction function is q = p, while state<br />

139 Robert Powell, “The Inefficient Use of Power:<br />

Costly Conflict with Complete Information,”<br />

American Political Science Review, 98 (2004):<br />

231-41; Robert Powell, “War as a Commitment<br />

Problem,” International Organization, 60 (2006):<br />

169-203.<br />

2 is a challenger, and its reaction function is<br />

q = a ∙ p + α (where α is a real number).<br />

In this case, the condition of equilibrium at<br />

point t is p ! = a ∙ p !!! + α.In addition, in<br />

equilibrium, p ∗ = a ∙ p ∗ + α .<br />

If we assume that ∆p ! ≡ p ! − p ∗ , we can get<br />

∆p ! = a∆p !!! = ⋯ = a ! ∆p ! . (where a is a<br />

real number). The important point in this<br />

equilibrium is that the condition of conflict<br />

resolution is a < 1.<br />

Because the reaction function of state 1 is<br />

q = p, we can get !! !<br />

= p − q = 0.<br />

!"<br />

Therefore, π ! = ! ! p! − q ∙ p + β = p ∙<br />

!<br />

!<br />

p − q + β (where β is a real number).<br />

Since we assume π ! = p ∙ v ! − c, we can get<br />

v ! = ! p − q. Moreover, since p + q = 1, we<br />

!<br />

can get 1 = ! p − v !<br />

!…1 .<br />

On the other hand, because the reaction<br />

function of state 2 is q = a ∙ p + α, we can<br />

get !! !<br />

= ap + α − q = 0 .<br />

!"<br />

Therefore, π ! = − ! ! q! + ap + α q + γ =<br />

q − ! q + ap + α + γ(where<br />

!<br />

γ is a real number).<br />

Since we assume π ! = q ∙ v ! − c, we can get<br />

v ! = − ! q + ap + α .<br />

!<br />

Now, since p + q = 1, we can get 1 =<br />

2a + 1 p − 2v ! + 2α…2 .<br />

Because 1 and 2 should be compatible,<br />

!<br />

p − v !<br />

! = 2a + 1 p − 2v ! + 2α .<br />

Therefore we can get<br />

a = −v ! + 2v ! − 2α<br />

2p<br />

+ 1 4 .<br />

When a ≥ 0, the condition of a < 1 is<br />

−v ! + 2v ! − 2α<br />

2p<br />

+ 1 4 < 1 .<br />

Therefore, we can get p > ! −v !<br />

! + 2v ! −<br />

2α .<br />

When a < 0, the condition of a < 1 is<br />

− −v ! + 2v ! − 2α<br />

2p<br />

− 1 4 < 1.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 30


Therefore, we can get p > ! ! v ! − 2v ! +<br />

2α .<br />

Q.E.D.<br />

Proof of Proposition 2<br />

Consider the Bertrand Equilibrium.<br />

The reason why I consider the Bertrand<br />

Equilibrium is because in equilibrium both<br />

actors’ beliefs about the war values are<br />

supposed to converge.<br />

Thus, I start with both actors’ reaction<br />

functions so that their beliefs will converge as<br />

a result of their profit maximizations.<br />

Assume that state 1 is a defender and<br />

its reaction function is v ! = v ! , while state 2<br />

is a challenger and its reaction function is<br />

v ! = a ∙ v ! + β (where β is a real number).<br />

The equilibrium at point t is v !! = a ∙<br />

v ! !!! + β, while in equilibrium, v ! ∗ = a ∙<br />

v ! ∗ + β . If we assume that ∆v !! ≡ v ! ! − v !∗ ,<br />

we can get ∆v !! = a∆v !!!! = ⋯ = a ! ∆v !" .<br />

(where a is a real number). The important<br />

point in this equilibrium is that the condition<br />

of conflict resolution is a < 1.<br />

Because the reaction function of state 1 is<br />

v ! = v ! , we can get !! !<br />

!! !<br />

= v ! − v ! = 0.<br />

Therefore, π ! = − ! ! v ! ! + v ! ∙ v ! + γ = v ! ∙<br />

− ! ! v ! + v ! + γ(γ is a real number ).<br />

Since we assume π ! = p ∙ v ! − c, we can get<br />

p = − ! ! v ! + v ! .<br />

Because S = p ∙ v ! + q ∙ v ! , we can get<br />

S = − ! ! v ! ! + v ! ∙ v ! + q ∙ v ! ・・・1<br />

(I assume that S stands for the supply of<br />

public goods provided by those states).<br />

On the other hand, the expected utility of<br />

state 2 is v ! = a ∙ v ! + β; hence, we can get<br />

!! !<br />

!! !<br />

= a ∙ v ! + β − v ! = 0. Therefore,π ! =<br />

− ! ! v ! ! + a ∙ v ! + β ∙ v ! + δ =<br />

v ! − ! ! v ! + a ∙ v ! + β + δ (where<br />

δ is a real number) .<br />

Since we assume π ! = q ∙ v ! − c, we can get<br />

q = − ! ! v ! + a ∙ v ! + β .<br />

Because S = p ∙ v ! + q ∙ v ! , we can get<br />

S = − ! ! v ! ! + a ∙ v ! + β v ! + p ∙ v ! ・・<br />

・2<br />

Now, both 1 and 2 should be compatible,<br />

such that − ! ! v ! ! + v ! v ! + q ∙ v ! =<br />

− ! ! v ! ! + a ∙ v ! + β v ! + p ∙ v ! .<br />

Therefore, we can get a = ! ! !<br />

− ! !<br />

− p ∙<br />

! ! ! ! !<br />

!<br />

+ q ∙ ! − β ∙ ! + 1 .<br />

! ! ! ! ! !<br />

When a ≥ 0, the condition of a < 1 is<br />

! ! !<br />

− ! !<br />

− p ∙ ! + q ∙ ! − β ∙ ! + 1 < 1.<br />

! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! !<br />

Therefore, we can get p > − ! ∙ v !<br />

! + ! !<br />

∙<br />

! !<br />

!<br />

v !<br />

! − q − β .<br />

When a < 0, the condition of a < 1 is<br />

− ! ! !<br />

− ! !<br />

+ p ∙ ! − q ∙ ! + β ∙ ! − 1 <<br />

! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! !<br />

1. Therefore, we can get p < !<br />

− ! v ! ! !! ! !<br />

! ! +<br />

!<br />

v ! ! ! + 2v ! v ! + v ! − β ∙ v ! .<br />

Since we need to find the upper bound of p,<br />

we should assume that a < 0.<br />

Therefore, we should also assume that a < 0<br />

in proposition 1.Q.E.D.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 31


Bordered Citizenship<br />

Why Distributive Justice<br />

Requires Republic Citizenship<br />

Ji Min Kim<br />

T<br />

he degree of permeability of state<br />

borders continues to weigh upon<br />

liberalist accounts of citizenship. The<br />

liberal value of equal moral worth of every<br />

individual promotes universal concern and<br />

respect for an individual’s well being. Then,<br />

the liberal citizenship should in theory grant<br />

freedom of movement if it enhances<br />

individuals’ autonomy and welfare. However,<br />

such notion of cosmopolitan citizenship is yet<br />

to be widely accepted by the democratic states<br />

since citizenship is traditionally defined within<br />

the context of the territorial nation-state,<br />

limiting the applicability of liberal values and<br />

obligations only to those legally recognized<br />

within the borders. The discrepancy of liberal<br />

citizenship is most problematic in the context<br />

of distributive justice, especially concerning<br />

the gross global inequality between wealthy<br />

(developed) and impoverished (or underdeveloped)<br />

states. To liberals who endorse<br />

cosmopolitan view of citizenship, erecting<br />

impermeable state boundaries is nothing short<br />

of feudalism, granting morally arbitrary 140<br />

birthright privileges to a lucky few but failing<br />

to indiscriminately protect the liberty and<br />

equality of all people.<br />

In Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open<br />

Borders, Joseph H. Carens tackles this difficulty<br />

and calls for major revisions to conventional<br />

border restrictions. He argues that our most<br />

deeply rooted liberal value, of the equal moral<br />

worth of every individual, necessitates an<br />

open border. This cosmopolitan vision of<br />

140 Carens argues that one’s natural citizenship<br />

in a wealthy democratic state is a morally<br />

arbitrary privilege since it was granted as a<br />

birthright rather than earned. In other words,<br />

one’s citizenship in a country depends on one’s<br />

luck rather than on logical moral standards.<br />

distributive justice, Carens believes, is morally<br />

required because it is the only way to<br />

guarantee equal opportunity to individuals in<br />

poor and failed states, thereby alleviating the<br />

grossly unequal wealth distribution around the<br />

world. Carens contests the claim that<br />

wealthier states owe distinct obligations to<br />

their citizens and legal aliens. By rejecting<br />

exclusive citizenship nestled by restrictive<br />

state borders, he offers one of the most<br />

inclusive accounts of transnational citizenship.<br />

In this essay, I argue that Carens’s<br />

open border policy falls short from<br />

formulating distributive justice, not only<br />

failing to solve global inequality but also<br />

endangering the guarantee of equality within a<br />

state. Contrary to the theory, only republican<br />

citizenship that depends on restrictive borders<br />

can secure distributive justice within a state.<br />

The argument does not propose that the<br />

equality of fellow countrymen is more<br />

valuable than that of outsiders; however, the<br />

political and social institutions, as well as<br />

social values, that citizens share within a<br />

nation state create a special obligation to their<br />

particular political community. In other<br />

words, the liberal principle of distributive<br />

justice is only applicable to individuals who<br />

practice republican citizenship, accepting the<br />

liabilities inherent in the coercive networks of<br />

state governance.<br />

First, I will examine Carens’s<br />

argument that transnational citizenship is<br />

necessary to foster global distributive equality;<br />

Then, I will argue that in order to achieve any<br />

kind of distributive justice, states need to<br />

adopt republican citizenship. Finally, I will<br />

argue that republican citizenship cannot be<br />

achieved with open borders.<br />

CARENS’S PROPOSAL OF OPEN<br />

BORDER<br />

Carens rejects the conventional view<br />

that a state is morally entitled to control its<br />

borders. He argues that border control is<br />

incompatible with liberal principles of basic<br />

rights and equality for all people. In<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 32


challenging the conventional view, he makes<br />

an analogy that citizenship in Western<br />

democracies is the modern equivalent of<br />

privileges in feudal society. This privilege is<br />

arbitrary granted based on birth yet greatly<br />

enhances one’s quality of life. On the other<br />

hand, less fortunate individuals born in poor<br />

or failed states are as strongly bound to their<br />

impoverishment and insecurity as serfs were<br />

bound to their lord’s estate. The inequality<br />

between these states is further aggravated by<br />

legal restrictions on mobility across their<br />

borders. Regardless of how talented they are<br />

or how hard they work, parochial borders<br />

make it extremely difficult for those born into<br />

socially and economically disadvantaged states<br />

to overcome that misfortune. Extending the<br />

analogy, Carens argues that the assumed<br />

injustice of feudal system should ring an alarm<br />

to the current conventional practice of border<br />

control that passively upholds birthright<br />

privileges.<br />

In proposing for an open border,<br />

Carens identifies three underlying interrelated<br />

assumptions:<br />

First, there is no natural social<br />

order. The institutions and<br />

practices that govern human<br />

beings are ones that human<br />

beings have created and can<br />

change, at least in principle.<br />

Second, in evaluating the<br />

moral status of alternative<br />

forms of political and social<br />

organization, we must start<br />

from the premise that all<br />

human beings are of equal<br />

moral worth. Third,<br />

restrictions on the freedom of<br />

human beings require a moral<br />

justification. 141<br />

141 Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The<br />

Case for Open Borders” in Theorizing<br />

Citizenship, Vol. 49, No. 2, ed. Ronald Beiner,.<br />

(Spring, 1987), 226.<br />

Carens believes that these basic principles<br />

claim moral legitimacy to every contemporary<br />

democratic regime. Accordingly, these three<br />

basic assumptions function as the basic pillars<br />

to Carens’s proposal for open borders. The<br />

first assumption implies that the institutions<br />

and practices that are currently in place are<br />

not an end result of an inevitable natural order<br />

but rather a dynamic social construct that can<br />

be changed. This assumption that gross global<br />

inequality is produced due to prioritization of<br />

national interests over moral obligation<br />

toward weaker states allows Carens to argue<br />

that the current world structure needs to be<br />

redressed. The inaction of the wealthier<br />

democratic states in the face of such<br />

inequality is incompatible with the deeply<br />

rooted liberal value that all human beings are<br />

of equal moral worth. Equal moral worth<br />

should render the same equality and freedom<br />

to every individual not just to the lucky few.<br />

Carens does acknowledge that states cannot<br />

be completely free from all restrictions, but he<br />

argues by the third assumption that states’<br />

practice of discretionary power over<br />

immigration without providing a moral<br />

justification for restricting it is a deep<br />

injustice.<br />

Based on the assumptions, he<br />

provides three prima facie interrelated reasons<br />

why open border is necessary to achieve<br />

moral global equality. First, he argues that a<br />

state’s control over freedom of movement<br />

undermines individual autonomy. Under the<br />

premise that freedom of movement is a<br />

prerequisite to other freedoms such as<br />

freedom to live as one chooses and freedom<br />

from coercion, open borders will contribute<br />

to individual autonomy. This leads to the<br />

second reason for open borders: freedom of<br />

movement is essential for equal opportunity.<br />

An individual’s entitlement to equal<br />

opportunity stems from the second basic<br />

assumption that all human beings are of equal<br />

moral worth and therefore deserve equal<br />

access to political and social organization that<br />

do not impede their chances for a better life<br />

based on a morally arbitrary standard such as<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 33


an inherent birthright. This notion of equal<br />

moral worth and the individual’s entitlement<br />

to equal opportunity entails the final reason:<br />

they are a means of realizing equal freedom<br />

and equal opportunity and also desirable end<br />

in itself 142 . In other words, if the global poor<br />

avail themselves of such opportunity by<br />

moving to the ‘wealthier’ states such as the<br />

United States, then permitting universal<br />

freedom of movement would substantively<br />

alleviate global inequality.<br />

THE PROBLEM WITH CARENS’S OPEN<br />

BORDER POLICY<br />

The three reasons raise interrelated<br />

questions that cast doubt on the capability of<br />

open borders to generate equality within and<br />

across borders. The problem with Carens’s<br />

view of citizenship is that, by dominantly<br />

focusing on individual autonomy and only<br />

guaranteeing a chance of equal opportunity, it<br />

fails to generate any obligation for realizing<br />

distributive justice.<br />

In order to arrive at this conclusion,<br />

the first question should be: why are rich<br />

states obligated to uphold the individual<br />

autonomy of those outside their jurisdiction<br />

above privilege of their own citizens? Put<br />

differently, it is hard to see how open borders<br />

could solve the problem of global inequality<br />

by respecting absolute individual autonomy. If<br />

prioritizing the individual autonomy of<br />

outsiders does not serve the interest of<br />

citizens within a state’s border, should the<br />

state still honor the ideas of individual<br />

autonomy and freedom of movement? In<br />

arguing for individual autonomy, Carens<br />

argues that when a political community as a<br />

whole has dominion over immigration, the<br />

right and liberty of its citizens and aliens alike<br />

are critically limited. He provides a case to<br />

illustrate how border restriction infringes the<br />

autonomy of both citizens and non-citizens:<br />

142 Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The<br />

Case for Open Borders,” 228.<br />

Suppose a farmer from the<br />

United States wanted to hire<br />

workers from Mexico. The<br />

government would have no<br />

right to prohibit him from<br />

doing this. To prevent the<br />

Mexicans from coming would<br />

violate the rights of both the<br />

American farmer and the<br />

Mexican workers to engage in<br />

voluntary transactions 143<br />

According to this example, states’ exclusive<br />

immigration policies interfere with both an<br />

outsider’s freedom of movement and an<br />

insider’s economic freedom to hire any<br />

worker of their choice. Libertarians are right<br />

to suggest that a state’s discretionary control<br />

over immigration is inconsistent with<br />

individuals’ having unlimited rights in this<br />

domain. However, border controls concern<br />

the interest of political community as a whole,<br />

not just benefit a few individuals. An<br />

individual would have the right to freely move<br />

across borders or hire foreigners if individual<br />

rights were always general and absolute, but a<br />

person’s right to free movement does not give<br />

one the absolute right to another person’s<br />

house without permission. Applied to states,<br />

why should it be assumed that freedom of<br />

movement gives an individual the right to<br />

enter a country’s territory without first getting<br />

the permission from that political community?<br />

In an attempt to answer this challenge,<br />

Carens concedes that freedom of movement<br />

should be constrained at some point. He<br />

claims, however, that “restrictions on freedom<br />

of movement require some sort of moral<br />

justification, that is, some argument as to why<br />

the restriction on freedom is in the interest of,<br />

and fair to, all those who are subject to it” 144 .<br />

Although a state’s obligation to provide<br />

143 Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The<br />

Case for Open Borders,” 226. <br />

144 Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The<br />

Case for Open Borders,” 277<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 34


justification for its restrictive actions toward<br />

its own citizens is usually presumed to be a<br />

legitimate demand, why is a state required to<br />

provide such service to non-members,<br />

especially if they are uninvited outsiders? Also,<br />

it is not hard to find cases that illustrate the<br />

reasons for restrictions are valid only under<br />

condition that they serve the interest of the<br />

lawful residents --citizens. For example,<br />

imagine that two intruders want to enter a<br />

house and help themselves to the food inside.<br />

It seems odd to argue that the owner of the<br />

house would have to first provide a moral<br />

justification before repelling them. In<br />

extension, why must a state morally justify its<br />

attempt to keep uninvited foreigners out of its<br />

political community? One defense could be<br />

that the citizens of a state have no tangible<br />

(literal) ownership over the state’s territory<br />

unlike the legitimate owner of a private<br />

property. However, this response fails to hold<br />

at the counter argument that a state’s<br />

constituents possess the relevant (figural)<br />

moral dominion over their political<br />

community. The point of this argument is that<br />

if individual autonomy of aliens cannot be<br />

justified as superior to the state’s interest in<br />

restricting its borders, then it logically follows<br />

that the state is not entitled to provide equal<br />

opportunity to aliens when such policy does<br />

not serve its interests.<br />

This leads to the second question: are<br />

open borders capable of achieving global<br />

equality? I argue that it is insufficient to<br />

generate global equality because open border<br />

itself holds no power to implicate equal<br />

opportunity provided by redistributive system.<br />

Carens argues that restrictive border controls<br />

undermine the equal moral worth of<br />

individuals by securing privileges to the<br />

citizens of wealthy states while impeding<br />

citizens of poor states from escaping their bad<br />

fortune. One has to be free to move to where<br />

the opportunities are in order to take<br />

advantage of them. Therefore, freedom of<br />

movement is a prerequisite for the equality of<br />

opportunity. Carens seems to believe that<br />

freedom of movement will make all privileged<br />

opportunities available to everyone around<br />

the world who chooses to move, therefore<br />

achieving the kind of universal distributive<br />

justice required to address global inequality. Is<br />

Carens’s definition of equal opportunity<br />

sufficient to match the importance he places<br />

on the protection of equal moral worth of<br />

individuals? If his definition of equal<br />

opportunity provided by open borders is<br />

insufficient, then, his argument falls apart.<br />

Open borders cannot effectively<br />

address the fundamental problems of<br />

entrenched poverty that causes people to<br />

migrate. Global inequality should be to<br />

address by focusing on underlying conditions<br />

and expunging extreme poverty entrenched<br />

within poor states. Open borders provide an<br />

escape route from poverty rather than fixing<br />

the root problems.<br />

In his defense, Carens claims that the<br />

argument for open borders makes a crucial<br />

contribution to the advancement of<br />

international equality because it makes it<br />

harder for rich states to claim that they bear<br />

no responsibility for the persistence of<br />

inequality and the plight of the poor. Open<br />

borders are important because they force rich<br />

states to abandon passivity and inaction<br />

towards global inequality and meet the<br />

necessary distributive justice. However, if it is<br />

passivity and inaction of the states that are<br />

supposed to be redressed toward global<br />

inequality, it is doubtful that open borders are<br />

sufficient as the sole mechanism for<br />

distributive justice. The inequality within rich<br />

states can be as large as the inequalities among<br />

states. With persisting and gross inequality<br />

within the state, merely letting outsiders freely<br />

enter the country in question will not solve<br />

the problem of lack of equal opportunity.<br />

Rather, it could only exacerbate the inequality<br />

within the border.<br />

Even if not, then does it really take<br />

away the problem of passivity and inaction?<br />

In The Lost Immigration Debate, Mae M. Ngai<br />

provides an example of open border<br />

exacerbating the problem of inequality. With<br />

relatively flexible border controls, the<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 35


American Southwest became a frontier zone<br />

where Mexicans were welcomed as cheap and<br />

disposable labor but not as members of the<br />

United States polity. If the government fails to<br />

or is unwilling to support immigrants from<br />

falling into further poverty or being subject to<br />

exploitation, the claim that open borders<br />

uphold individual autonomy and equal moral<br />

worth cannot be substantiated. In order for<br />

the state to escape blame upon its passivity<br />

and inaction toward global inequality and<br />

uphold individual autonomy towards a<br />

universal distributive justice, then, the state<br />

needs to do a lot more than just to open its<br />

borders. Without extensive welfare and liable<br />

policies, border policies cannot generate the<br />

distributive justice that is essential to<br />

achieving any kind of equality.<br />

The best form of equal opportunity<br />

that can be generated from such a<br />

commitment would be a laissez-faire system in<br />

which every man stands for himself.<br />

However, the purpose of distributive justice is<br />

not to foster free markets but to attend to the<br />

need of the less well-offs. The fact that those<br />

who avail themselves of freedom of<br />

movement end up being disposable labor<br />

force within the adopted market, or are<br />

confined to undesirable jobs brought in by<br />

international capital, speaks against the idea<br />

that the market will work towards a corrective<br />

moral force. Considering the moral<br />

importance Carens advocates, the choice<br />

between indentured servitude abroad and<br />

sweatshops at home are not the kind of<br />

equality he envisions. This invokes more<br />

extensive commitments concerning global<br />

justice, towards world federalism. And a new<br />

question arises: are states obligated to institute<br />

global distributive justice policies even at the<br />

expense of the significance of borders that<br />

bind citizens together as a collective that<br />

facilitates distributive justice within the state?<br />

The question underlies the problem that open<br />

borders might be in conflict with distributive<br />

justice. Carens vaguely hints at the conflict:<br />

I was wrong. I have found that,<br />

faced with the choice between<br />

extending the right of free<br />

movement across borders and<br />

challenging the moral status of<br />

internal free movement as a<br />

human right, some people are<br />

willing to throw internal<br />

freedom of movement under<br />

the bus. They say… that<br />

perhaps freedom of movement<br />

within the state is not so<br />

important after all, not really<br />

something worthy of<br />

designation as a human rights<br />

145<br />

Here, Carens regretfully admits that<br />

democratic citizens who are committed to<br />

liberal principles may choose to revise their<br />

pledge when pushed to accept the premise<br />

that the norm they are already committed to<br />

entails open borders. Most troubling of this<br />

phenomenon is that by revising their<br />

commitment to the principles, citizens may<br />

reject the obligations to their fellow<br />

countrymen in extension. Although the quote<br />

is about people’s reluctance to view fellow<br />

citizens’ right to free movement as a<br />

legitimate right when challenged to accept the<br />

free movement of aliens as a basic human<br />

right, this can be applied to distributive<br />

justice. In The Moral Dilemma of U.S.<br />

Immigration Policy, Stephen Macedo argues that<br />

over the last forty years, American<br />

immigration policies and practices have<br />

become more accommodating to the less<br />

well-off abroad by instituting relatively flexible<br />

border policies. It could be argued that it has<br />

caused a significant cost in terms of social<br />

justice at home, including worsening income<br />

disparities in the United States. Steven A.<br />

Camarota argues that recent immigration<br />

contributed to employment loss among<br />

145 Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The<br />

Case for Open Borders.”<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 36


Americans 146 . He points out that labor force<br />

participation among African American males<br />

with low levels of education, the major group<br />

in job competition with unskilled immigrants,<br />

has fallen steeply correlated with (but not<br />

necessarily being caused by) higher<br />

immigration rates. Furthermore, it might be<br />

argued that high levels of immigration by<br />

unskilled laborers may also have lowered<br />

public support for social welfare. When<br />

pushed to recognize that liberal principle of<br />

moral equality and individual autonomy calls<br />

for an open border for equal opportunity and<br />

global equality, citizens may wholly reject the<br />

importance of distributive justice to escape<br />

from such commitment.<br />

In summary, although Carens’s<br />

demand to prioritize equal moral worth<br />

adheres to the liberal principle of individual<br />

autonomy, considering that border policy<br />

serves not just the interest of a few individuals<br />

but that of the society as a whole, its absolute<br />

applicability deems unwarranted. Also, even if<br />

a state opens its border under the recognition<br />

that individuals are entitled to freedom of<br />

movement, open border is insufficient to<br />

provide equal opportunity beyond the scope<br />

of the opportunity to reside in the state; this is<br />

clearly illustrated by the vulnerability of aliens<br />

to economic exploitation. Therefore, if Carens<br />

desires to provide an institutional and social<br />

mechanism that can guarantee equal<br />

opportunity that honors equal moral worth of<br />

every individual, a much more extensive and<br />

coercive set of policies is needed. Such<br />

policies, however, place too much burden and<br />

unwarranted obligation on citizens of the<br />

wealthy states. This may lead to complete<br />

rejection of redistribution itself. In<br />

conclusion, open borders fail to achieve<br />

equality because, in order for equality to be<br />

realized, distributive justice is required and<br />

distributive justice cannot formulate among<br />

cosmopolitan citizenship.<br />

WHY DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE REQUIRES<br />

REPUBLIC CITIZENSHIP<br />

As illustrated through the criticisms of<br />

open borders, liberal cosmopolitan citizenship<br />

not only fails to legitimatize distributive<br />

justice at a global level, it also endangers<br />

distributive justice within states. It can be<br />

concluded that the realization of distributive<br />

justice and the pursuit for equality depend on<br />

the right kind of citizenship and the proper<br />

degree of obligations and rights it entails. In<br />

order to achieve distributive justice,<br />

republican citizenship is a necessary<br />

condition, as defined by David Miller and<br />

Stephen Macedo 147 . Republican citizenship<br />

demands distributive justice for compatriots.<br />

The discussion of these points strengthens the<br />

case for the need for a bordered republican<br />

citizenship in order to achieve any kind of<br />

distributive justice.<br />

Miller’s republican conception of citizenship<br />

In arguing that practice of citizenship<br />

must be confined within the boundaries of<br />

national political communities, Miller<br />

challenges that transnational or global forms<br />

of citizenship have failed to meet the<br />

conditions under which genuine citizenship is<br />

possible. His ultimate challenge against the<br />

more cosmopolitan forms of citizenship is<br />

that while they adhere to the liberal<br />

conception of citizenship focused on citizen<br />

rights and state obligations, they disregard the<br />

republican conception of citizenship.<br />

Republican citizenship requires an active<br />

citizenry that “takes part along with others in<br />

shaping the future direction of his or her<br />

146 Steven Camarota, “Immigrant Employment<br />

Gains and Native Losses, 2000-2004” in<br />

Debating Immigration, ed. Carol M. Swain<br />

(Cambridge University Press: Cambrdige,<br />

2007).<br />

147 Macedo does not refer to his view of<br />

citizenship as republican citizenship, but the<br />

similarity of Miller’s and Macedo’s views make<br />

their models compatible with each other. For<br />

simplicity sake’s, “republican citizenship” here is<br />

an umbrella term.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 37


society through political debate” 148 . The<br />

responsibilities of republican citizenship<br />

extend beyond the liberal conception of<br />

citizenship in that it requires a sufficient<br />

measure of what the older republican tradition<br />

describes as the “public virtue.” Miller claims<br />

that there are four components of republican<br />

citizenship. The first two pertain to liberal<br />

conception while the second two are<br />

distinctively republican:<br />

First, the republican citizen<br />

securely enjoys a set of equal<br />

rights, which are necessary both<br />

in order to carry out private aims<br />

and purposes and in order to play<br />

her public role … Many rights<br />

have this dual aspect: rights to<br />

property and free speech, for<br />

instance can be seen both as<br />

enabling people to pursue their<br />

individual plans of life and<br />

personal ideals, and as<br />

preconditions for active<br />

citizenship. Second,<br />

corresponding to these rights is a<br />

set of obligations: to respect the<br />

law…to pay taxes in the interest<br />

of social justice, to serve on juries<br />

when called on to do so, and so<br />

on. 149<br />

While the rights and obligations outlined by<br />

the first two components involve some<br />

requirement for public roles, they are<br />

predominantly focused on guaranteeing<br />

individual liberty and equality at the expense<br />

of minimal public obligations. However,<br />

republican citizenship requires much more<br />

arduous commitments than passive<br />

compliance:<br />

Third, being willing to take active<br />

steps to defend the rights of<br />

148 David Miller, “Bounded Citizenship,” in<br />

Cosmopolitan Citizenship, 62.<br />

149 Ivi.<br />

other members of the political<br />

community, and more generally<br />

to promote its common<br />

interests…under this heading, the<br />

citizen is someone who is ready<br />

to volunteer for public service<br />

when the need arises...Fourth and<br />

the last, the republic citizen plays<br />

an active role in both the formal<br />

and informal arenas of politics. 150<br />

The last two components are demanding in<br />

that they require citizens to actively perform<br />

political and sub-political tasks. Even if such<br />

actions lack personal incentives, citizens<br />

should be motivated to act accordingly for the<br />

sake of commitment to the community and<br />

their citizenship. Furthermore, such<br />

expressions should aim at promoting the<br />

common good. Motivation to achieve the<br />

common good involves a will to set aside<br />

personal interests and ideals in the interests of<br />

achieving democratic consensus. His<br />

argument for active political participation in<br />

the later two argument focuses on fostering<br />

common good and mutual interest. This<br />

logically necessitates a mechanism for<br />

redistribution that fosters a level of equality<br />

among its members. Political communities’<br />

commitment to distributive justice leads to<br />

the establishment of “standards to regulate<br />

the major institutions of taxation, inheritance,<br />

social provisions, wage policies, education,<br />

and so forth that help determine over time the<br />

relative level of income, wealth, and<br />

opportunity available to different groups” 151 .<br />

Such system of redistribution achieves far<br />

greater equality and opportunity for the<br />

society as a whole than Carens’s open<br />

borders, which focus on individual autonomy<br />

for the sake of equal moral worth<br />

150 Ibid., 63.<br />

151 Stephen Macedo, “The Moral Dilemma of US<br />

Immigration Policy,” in Debating Immigration<br />

ed. Carol M. Swain (Cambridge University<br />

Press: Cambridge, 2007), 69.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 38


guaranteeing only superficial (or laissez-faire)<br />

definition of equal opportunity.<br />

Macedo’s civic view<br />

Elaborating on Miller’s account of<br />

citizenship, Stephen Macedo examines how<br />

the moral obligation of citizenship fostered<br />

through co-participation in governance of a<br />

bounded political community compels<br />

distributive justice. He coins the term “civic<br />

view” to justify his conception of citizenship.<br />

The cosmopolitan conception of citizenship<br />

emphasizes the moral arbitrariness of borders<br />

and the universality of states’ obligation to<br />

globalization’s have-nots. On the contrary,<br />

civic view argues that borders do hold moral<br />

significance that generates special obligations<br />

toward its citizens. Borders carry moral<br />

significance because they constitute a<br />

bounded system of collective self-governance.<br />

Although Macedo does not refer his “civic<br />

view” to republican citizenship, his meaning<br />

of citizenship also highly depends on the<br />

practice of public virtue, making the view<br />

compatible with the republican citizenship<br />

outlined by Miller.<br />

Macedo argues that all individuals are<br />

born into a political community composed of<br />

various associations including religious<br />

communities and families. These associations<br />

shape individuals’ interests, identities,<br />

relationships and opportunities. Through<br />

engagement with various associations,<br />

members of the political community<br />

collectively create, coercively impose, and live<br />

within the political order. In turn, the political<br />

order provides the basic values that<br />

pervasively shape the lives of those who<br />

reside within it. The mutual bilateral<br />

relationship between the state government<br />

and its members allow the government to<br />

function as a self-governing political<br />

community. Citizens, as collective agents,<br />

bestow legitimacy unto the government so<br />

that its actions would reflect and represent the<br />

policy decisions of the citizens as a whole. As<br />

a legitimate government, the state is trusted to<br />

exercise an authoritative role in resolving<br />

conflicts and making decisions on behalf of<br />

the citizens. These functions include “entering<br />

into treaties, making alliances, declaring war,<br />

and conducting various undertaking under<br />

[citizens’] name” 152 . Governmental legitimacy<br />

as representative of its citizens is significant in<br />

that it underlies a strong sense of shared<br />

obligation for mutual concern and respect.<br />

Citizens collectively govern each other for the<br />

common good., and create binding political<br />

institutions that determine distributive<br />

patterns of opportunity and reward for all.<br />

This sense of mutual governance creates<br />

binding obligation to the welfare of fellow<br />

compatriots.<br />

Returning to the challenge posed by<br />

cosmopolitan citizenship discussed above<br />

regarding the injustice of repelling outsiders<br />

without moral justification, distributive justice<br />

requires some form of republican citizenship<br />

that holds individuals responsible for<br />

fostering active political community from the<br />

meanings and significance of citizenship<br />

discussed by Miller and Macedo. The liberal<br />

conception of citizenship endorsed by Carens<br />

only focuses on the individual autonomy and<br />

right to equal privileges, and hence fails to<br />

promote a commission to the mutual<br />

governance of citizens and the advancement<br />

of common welfare in a political community.<br />

As Macedo argues, every individual is born in<br />

a political community: one cannot act with<br />

absolute freedom and demand for unearned<br />

rights, as if one lives in a arbitrary state absent<br />

of mutual concern for others who actually<br />

hold governing power over their shared<br />

territory. A political community generates a<br />

communal concern and special obligations<br />

amongst its members, which in turn promote<br />

a strong commitment to distributive fairness.<br />

REPUBLICAN CITIZENSHIP CANNOT BE<br />

ACHIEVED WITH OPEN BORDER<br />

152 Macedo, “The Moral Dilemma of US<br />

Immigration Policy,”74<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 39


In order to achieve any kind of<br />

equality, duty to distributive justice must be<br />

generated through republican citizenship.<br />

Carens’s prescriptions fail to achieve this.<br />

Cosmopolitan citizenship cannot formulate<br />

distributive justice because international<br />

governance fails to present “a comprehensive<br />

system of laws and institutions that regulate<br />

and shape all associations,” which in turn<br />

promotes civic obligations 153 . Although there<br />

are multilateral institutions such as the United<br />

Nations that do provide some norms of<br />

international governance, the subject covered<br />

by such institutions are limited and do not<br />

hold individuals accountable for each other’s<br />

public virtue. Macedo concludes that it is<br />

unreasonable to make “people responsible for<br />

the welfare of others without also making<br />

them responsible for their governance” 154<br />

In the view of traditional republican<br />

polity, the importance given to cultivating<br />

public virtue that places public responsibilities<br />

before private interests unusually required a<br />

fairly small city-state to foster strong patriotic<br />

loyalty. In the Discourse on Political Economy,<br />

Rousseau argues:<br />

Do we want people to become<br />

virtuous? If so, let us begin by<br />

making them love their<br />

homeland. But how will they<br />

come to love it, if their<br />

homeland means nothing<br />

more to them than it does to<br />

foreigners, and if it grants to<br />

them only what it cannot<br />

refuse to anyone? 155<br />

153 Macedo, “The Moral Dilemma of US<br />

Immigration Policy,” 69.<br />

154 Macedo, “The Moral Dilemma of US<br />

Immigration Policy,” 74.<br />

155 Rousseau, Jean Jacques. “Rousseau<br />

Rousseau's Political Writings: Discourse on<br />

Inequality, Discourse on Political Economy, On<br />

Social Contract”. (Norton: New York, 1987),<br />

70.<br />

Rousseau claims that a state cannot ask its<br />

citizens to love their country if it does not<br />

provide special benefits and rights exclusive to<br />

its people. While Rousseau envisioned citizens<br />

gathering around a round table face-to-face,<br />

expressing their commitment to the general<br />

will, 156 his demand for a mechanism that<br />

fosters and accommodates citizens’ duty to<br />

their state and fellow compatriots is still valid.<br />

Although this extreme view of public virtue is<br />

neither practical nor desirable, modern<br />

societies must also generate a sufficient degree<br />

of trust and loyalty that republican citizenship<br />

requires through active civic engagement and<br />

distributive justice. Then, it logically follows<br />

that state borders are morally significant in<br />

producing republican citizenship. In other<br />

words, republican citizenship and distributive<br />

justice cannot be achieved with an open<br />

border policy.<br />

Michael Walzer insists that states, by<br />

nature, depend upon closure in order to<br />

protect the sense of relatedness and mutuality<br />

that a membership community requires 157 . He<br />

rejects that distributive justice can be operated<br />

through open borders since values are shared<br />

within particular political communities, not<br />

across them. A country is understood to<br />

operate with common meanings and shared<br />

ways of life, which its members are entitled to<br />

preserve. Hence, he argues that social goods<br />

should be distributed according to criteria<br />

internal to their social meanings, and these<br />

shared social meanings are located within a<br />

particular political community. However, the<br />

problem of Walzer’s view is that he weighs<br />

156 Rousseau’s political society is one in which<br />

every individual gives themselves fully to the<br />

community, body and soul, in order to invent a<br />

true body politics: the General Will. A discussion<br />

of the General Will is beyond the scope of this<br />

argument; it is stated here merely to illustrate the<br />

need for a mechanism that would accommodate<br />

loyalty and trust amongst citizens in order to<br />

realize republican citizenship.<br />

157 Michael Walzer, “Exclusion, Injustice, and the<br />

Democratic State,” Dissent, vol. 40:1 (1993)<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 40


too much on the maintenance of cultural<br />

distinctiveness and prevalent shared<br />

meanings. Shared meaning is a goal of public<br />

argument and deliberation to sustain a<br />

political system rather than the cause for<br />

political obligation to whom citizens owe<br />

justice. That is, only by sharing a system of<br />

binding law, one can be admitted as a member<br />

of political community with whom citizens<br />

create a shared meaning or publicly justified<br />

principles of justice. Rather than extending<br />

distributive justice only to those who share<br />

meanings, people who share a system of<br />

binding law that works toward shared<br />

meaning through deliberation and public<br />

argument reserve the right to distributive<br />

justice. Although Walzer develops a strong<br />

argument for a closed border based on the<br />

notion of shared national identity, his<br />

emphasis on a shared national identity based<br />

on existing distinct characteristics evades the<br />

essence of republican citizenship.<br />

Nonetheless, Walzer’s argument is critical in<br />

providing an insight to why republican<br />

citizenship can be achieved with restrictive<br />

borders. Applied to republican citizenship,<br />

Walzer’s argument makes a strong case in<br />

which individuals who share the strong<br />

commitment to creating binding political<br />

institutions based on obligation of mutual<br />

concern and respect should determine the<br />

distributive patterns of opportunities and<br />

reward for all.<br />

Citizenship depends on reciprocity.<br />

Although minimal domestic protection of the<br />

rights of the citizen is required by the liberal<br />

concept of citizenship that endorses open<br />

borders, it is illustrated through the argument<br />

that citizenship is better served by active<br />

public engagement and mutual obligation<br />

within states’ borders than the creation of<br />

transnational bodies who are likely to dilute<br />

the quality of republican citizenship. “Free<br />

citizenship” undermines the mutual trust and<br />

assurance that make responsible citizenship<br />

possible.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

Distributive justice requires republican<br />

citizenship through several steps. Carens’s<br />

open border policy is incapable of justifying<br />

the importance of individual autonomy over<br />

the interest of citizens as collective agents.<br />

Although the liberal concept of citizenship<br />

endorsed by Carsens rightly addresses that<br />

equal moral worth of individuals requires<br />

universal concern and respect, it is hard to see<br />

why the interest of non-members should be<br />

given the same degree, or even a priority of<br />

concern as that of citizens, especially when<br />

borders concern the welfare of the political<br />

community in question. Therefore, states do<br />

not hold an obligation to uphold absolute and<br />

indiscriminating concern for individual<br />

autonomy, especially when it is against the<br />

interest of its citizens. In adhering to the<br />

protection and promotion of their citizens’<br />

welfare, states should be able to enforce<br />

border controls even if it is against the interest<br />

of the hopeful migrants. States are rarely<br />

responsible to grant moral justification for<br />

such border restrictions. Furthermore, simply<br />

opening up the borders is insufficient to<br />

address the global inequality. An open border<br />

does not automatically grant equal<br />

opportunity to those who have crossed that<br />

border. In order to effectively address the<br />

problem of global inequality and equal<br />

opportunity, a system of redistribution is<br />

required. Open border may grant the freedom<br />

to engage in the free market. However, such<br />

laissez- faire opportunity will not solve the<br />

initial problem of eliminating morally arbitrary<br />

privileges of the well-offs to promote more<br />

equality. The concept of citizenship cannot<br />

solely be defined based on economic<br />

framework. If obligation to distributive justice<br />

is pushed to the international level it might<br />

become weary of the magnitude of their<br />

responsibility, the citizens of the rich states<br />

might throw their commitment to<br />

redistribution under the bus even for their<br />

fellow compatriots. Re-conceptualizing<br />

Carens’s claim that natural citizenship in a<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 41


developed state is a morally arbitrary privilege,<br />

the need for distributive equality should not<br />

demand ‘the lucky few’ to pay for their good<br />

fortune by compensating for the other’s bad<br />

fortune, whom they do not share social,<br />

political and/or economical interests.<br />

Therefore, open borders not only fail to<br />

resolve global inequality, but also endanger<br />

citizens’ distributive obligations.<br />

Distributive justice requires republican<br />

citizenship, something that Carens’s open<br />

borders fail to set an obligation for among a<br />

state’s citizens. Republican citizenship, as<br />

discussed by Miller and Macedo, states that<br />

citizens share strong common obligations to<br />

civic engagement and public virtue based on<br />

mutual concern, respect, and justification.<br />

Under republican citizenship, the<br />

responsibility for others’ governance and<br />

special obligation for fellow citizens forms a<br />

strong commitment to distributive justice.<br />

Rousseau and Walzer’s proposals for<br />

closed borders further illustrate that<br />

republican citizenship cannot be achieved by<br />

an open border. Although Rousseau and<br />

Walzer’s arguments are not without their<br />

flaws, they provide strong arguments that<br />

open borders endanger the mutual trust and<br />

assurance that create responsible citizenship.<br />

In sum, the discussion strengthen the<br />

argument that only republican citizenship can<br />

formulate distributive justice and that<br />

republican citizenship cannot be achieved<br />

with open borders, but can only be achieved<br />

with relatively restrictive border controls.<br />

On a final note, distributive justice<br />

pertaining solely to a bordered political<br />

community does not claim that fellow<br />

countrymen is more valuable than that of<br />

outsiders, but only that political and social<br />

institutions formulated by republican citizens<br />

create a special obligation to their particular<br />

political community. Restrictive borders are<br />

not necessarily in conflict with liberal<br />

obligation to alleviate global inequality. The<br />

problems of universal injustice can be<br />

addressed through different means, such as<br />

charity work or collaborative action through<br />

multilateral governance. It is possible that<br />

states may attend to the need of the outsiders<br />

upon first strengthening citizenship and<br />

inculcating civic virtue within national<br />

boundaries.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 42


Issues of Legality and<br />

Legitimacy<br />

The Responsibility to Protect<br />

and NATO’s intervention in<br />

Libya<br />

Lesley Connolly<br />

T<br />

he United Nations (UN) Security<br />

Council Resolution 1674 of 2006, the<br />

Responsibility to Protect (R2P) doctrine,<br />

represented a significant development in<br />

humanitarian intervention and international<br />

diplomacy. By passing this resolution, the UN<br />

affirmed, “each individual State has the<br />

responsibility to protect its populations from<br />

genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and<br />

crimes against humanity.” 158 Before such a<br />

resolution, the international community was<br />

legally bound by the grip of Article 2(7) of the<br />

UN Charter, which stipulated “no<br />

interference in the domestic affairs of<br />

member states.” 159<br />

This change took place at a time when<br />

there was a transforming power balance<br />

within the International Community. With the<br />

end of the Cold War came the rise of interstate<br />

conflict and warfare, including violence<br />

within the borders of countries such as<br />

Somalia, Rwanda, and Bosnia. There was a<br />

widespread disagreement over how states and<br />

international organizations should react to<br />

these situations. 160 There was a growing<br />

public discontent with the increasing disregard<br />

for international humanitarian law by many<br />

heads of states, as well as of the direct<br />

158 The United Nations General Assembly, 2005<br />

World Summit Outcome, A/60/L.1, Article 138,<br />

15 September 2005.<br />

159 Charter of the United Nations, Chapter VII,<br />

Article 2(7)<br />

160 Global Centre for the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, “Implementing the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, The 2009 General Assembly Debate:<br />

An Assessment”, GCR2P Report, August 2009.<br />

targeting of civilians and relief personnel, and<br />

in general, the increasing use of force to fuel<br />

conflict. 161 As the former Secretary-General<br />

of the UN, Javier Perez de Cuellar, stated,<br />

“We are witnessing what is probably an<br />

irreversible shift in public attitudes towards<br />

the belief that the defense of the oppressed in<br />

the name of morality should prevail over<br />

frontiers and legal documents.” 162 The<br />

passing of the R2P utilized the notions of just<br />

warfare and enabled states who felt morally<br />

responsible to stop the committing of<br />

widespread violations of human rights against<br />

people in a nation, whether it be their nation<br />

or another sovereign state, to take action.<br />

The application of R2P in the North<br />

Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO)<br />

intervention in Libya in 2011 was the first<br />

time the R2P had been used publically.<br />

However, this intervention, allegedly based on<br />

the notions of ethical warfare, has been<br />

criticized for stretching the application of the<br />

R2P doctrine to serve ulterior interests. The<br />

central question this paper is looking at is<br />

whether the application of the R2P to the<br />

NATO intervention in Libya was both legal<br />

and legitimate and if it has positively furthered<br />

the debate on humanitarian intervention. This<br />

paper will evaluate the legitimacy of the<br />

NATO intervention in terms of whether it<br />

was acceptable in terms of the standards and<br />

expectations held for actions undertaken by<br />

international actors within the international<br />

community.<br />

The Responsibility to Protect<br />

In 2001, The International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty Report,<br />

entitled The Responsibility to Protect, declared<br />

that: “Sovereign states have a responsibility to<br />

protect their own citizens from avoidable<br />

catastrophe- from mass murder and rape,<br />

161 Thomas G Weiss, “Principles, Politics and<br />

Humanitarian Action,” in Ethics and International<br />

Affairs, Vol 13 (1999).<br />

162 Christopher Greenwood, “Is there a right of<br />

humanitarian intervention?” The World Today,<br />

Vol 43, No 2 (1993).<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 43


from starvation- but that when they are<br />

unwilling or unable to do so, that<br />

responsibility must be born by the broader<br />

community of states. ” 163 164 This report<br />

emphasized that prevention is the key to<br />

avoiding humanitarian disasters, and, with this<br />

end in view, it urged states to consider a range<br />

of less coercive measures before resorting to<br />

force. 165 Four years later, at the 2005 UN<br />

World Summit, the R2P doctrine was adopted<br />

by the UN as Security Council Resolution<br />

1674 of 2006. The heads of states and<br />

governments unanimously affirmed that “each<br />

individual State has the responsibility to<br />

protect its populations from genocide, war<br />

crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes against<br />

humanity.” 166 They further agreed that the<br />

international community should assist states<br />

in exercising that responsibility and in<br />

building their protection capacities. When a<br />

state fails to protect its population from the<br />

four specified crimes and violations, it is<br />

confirmed that the international community<br />

was prepared to take collective action in a<br />

timely and decisive manner through the<br />

Security Council and in accordance with the<br />

Charter of the UN. 167<br />

There are three pillars to the process<br />

of R2P. Pillar I: the protection and<br />

responsibility of the State; Pillar II:<br />

International assistance and capacity-building,<br />

and Pillar III: Timely and decisive response. 168<br />

163 The Security Council Resolution 1674 of<br />

2006<br />

164 It is this mandate which reaffirmed the<br />

provisions of paragraphs 138 and 139 of the<br />

Responsibility to Protect Report.<br />

165 The Security Council Resolution 1674 of<br />

2006<br />

166 Ibid.<br />

167 Ibid.<br />

168 The three pillars of the responsibility to<br />

protect, as stipulated in the Outcome Document<br />

of the 2005 United Nations World Summit<br />

(A/RES/60/1, paragraphs 138-140) and<br />

formulated in the Secretary-General's 2009<br />

Pillar I refers to a state’s responsibility to<br />

protect its population and country from<br />

genocide, war crimes, crimes against<br />

humanity, and ethnic cleansing. Pillar II is the<br />

commitment of the international community<br />

to assist states in meeting the obligations of<br />

protection of its people from genocide, war<br />

crimes, and crimes against humanity. It seeks<br />

to draw on the cooperation of member states,<br />

regional and sub- regional arrangements, civil<br />

society and the private sector, as well as on<br />

the institutional strengths and comparative<br />

advantages of the UN system. Prevention,<br />

building on pillars one and two, is a key<br />

ingredient for a successful strategy for the<br />

responsibility to protect. Pillar III refers to a<br />

situation where a state has failed to protect its<br />

citizens from mass atrocity and peaceful<br />

measures are not working. When this<br />

happens, the international community has the<br />

responsibility to intervene at first through<br />

diplomacy, and then through coercive means<br />

but only use military force as a last resort. 169<br />

The issue of intervention- both<br />

humanitarian and military- is a contentious<br />

one within the debate over R2P. The R2P<br />

doctrine is not merely a new name for<br />

humanitarian intervention and is not a<br />

sanction for the immediate use of force.<br />

Humanitarian intervention is about the right<br />

of states to act coercively against others to<br />

stop atrocities whereas the R2P doctrine is<br />

about protecting civilians. 170 The doctrine<br />

endorses the use of force in extreme<br />

situations only and there is a set of criteria,<br />

drawing from the Just War Theory, which<br />

need to be fulfilled. These principles states<br />

that there must be:<br />

Report (A/63/677) on Implementing the<br />

Responsibility to Protect.<br />

169 The United Nations General Assembly, 2005<br />

World Summit Outcome, A/60/L.1, Article 138,<br />

15 September 2005.<br />

170 Global Centre for the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, “Implementing the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, The 2009 General Assembly Debate:<br />

An Assessment,” GCR2P Report, August 2009.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 44


Just Cause Threshold must be employed.<br />

Military intervention should only be<br />

undertaken for human protection purposes<br />

and is an exceptional and extraordinary<br />

measure. To be warranted, there must be<br />

serious and irreparable harm occurring to<br />

human beings, or imminently likely to occur<br />

such as large-scale loss of life and large scale<br />

‘ethnic cleansing.’ 171<br />

The Precautionary Principles state that<br />

intervention must have the purpose of halting<br />

or averting human suffering. The use of force<br />

must be the last resort. Military intervention<br />

can only be justified when every non-military<br />

option for the prevention or peaceful<br />

resolution of the crisis has been explored,<br />

with reasonable grounds for believing that<br />

lesser measures would not succeed. Lastly,<br />

proportional means must be employed. The<br />

scale, duration, and intensity of the planned<br />

military intervention should be the minimum<br />

necessary to secure the defined human<br />

protection objective. 172<br />

The Right Authority must endorse the<br />

intervention and the Security Council is the<br />

supreme body to authorize and authorization<br />

should in all cases be sought prior to any<br />

military intervention action being carried out.<br />

173<br />

However, when the R2P was passed these<br />

criteria were not formalized as part of the<br />

doctrine and therefore, at present, the official<br />

guideline to justify military intervention is that<br />

the use of force should only be used in the<br />

most extreme cases. 174 However, the United<br />

Nations Charter does stipulate guidelines on<br />

the use of force and military intervention.<br />

Article 2(4) of the United Nations Charter<br />

171 The Responsibility to Protect, 2001, Report<br />

from the International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty.<br />

172 Ibid.<br />

173 Ibid.<br />

174 Gareth Evans, “UN targets Libya with<br />

pinpoint accuracy,” The National Times, March<br />

24, 2011.<br />

establishes that states should not use or<br />

threaten force against other states: “All<br />

members shall refrain in their international<br />

relations from the threat or use of force<br />

against the territorial integrity or political<br />

independence of any state, or in any other<br />

manner inconsistent with the Purposes of the<br />

United Nations.” 175 There are some<br />

exceptions to this provided in Chapter VII<br />

Articles 39 and 51, which state that the<br />

collective use of force is allowed, and is<br />

controlled entirely by the UN Security<br />

Council and should only be used in Selfdefense<br />

- in response to an attack. 176<br />

The use of force in the NATO<br />

intervention in Libya was the first application<br />

of the R2P doctrine, but has been very<br />

contentiously viewed. The main issue of<br />

contention is that the application of R2P was<br />

seen, by the international community, as being<br />

stretched to justify the use of force when<br />

other means had not been ruled out.<br />

The military intervention in Libya<br />

The 2011 Libyan Civil War was an armed<br />

conflict in the North African country of<br />

Libya, between Colonel Muammar Gaddafi<br />

and the liberation forces. The conflict<br />

officially started on February 15, 2011 with<br />

approximately 200 people demonstrating in<br />

front of the policy headquarters in Benghazi<br />

following the arrest of human-rights activist<br />

Fathi Terbil. The protest grew to 800 and was<br />

eventually violently broken-up by the police.<br />

This was the start of what turned into a<br />

nationwide revolution to oust the Gaddafi<br />

government.<br />

On February 26, 2011, days after the<br />

first attack on Bengazi by the Gaddafi forces,<br />

the UN passed UN Security Council<br />

Resolution 1970 which invoked that ''the<br />

Libyan authorities [had the] responsibility to<br />

protect its population”, condemned the<br />

violence against civilians, demanded it to end,<br />

175 Charter of the United Nations, Chapter I,<br />

Article 2(4)<br />

176 Charter of the United Nations, Chapter VII,<br />

Article 36 & Article 51<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 45


and enforced sanctions, an arms embargo, and<br />

the threat of International Criminal Court<br />

prosecution for crimes against humanity upon<br />

the Gaddafi regime. 177<br />

On March 12, the Arab League met<br />

with the UN and asked them to pass a ‘no-flyzone’<br />

over Libya and recognize the rebel<br />

movement as the legitimate government in<br />

the country, as an attempt to try to stop the<br />

violence and attacks on civilians. The Arab<br />

League hoped the move would increase the<br />

pressure on the United States and European<br />

nations to act in response to the conflict that<br />

had erupted in the country. 178 As a result of<br />

this call for help, on March 17, 2011, the UN<br />

Security Council passed UN Security Council<br />

Resolution 1973. The resolution was adopted<br />

under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, and<br />

demanded the immediate establishment of a<br />

ceasefire in Libya and a complete end to the<br />

violence and attacks against civilians.<br />

Originally the resolution imposed a no-fly<br />

zone 179 over Libya, strengthened the arms<br />

embargo already placed upon the country,<br />

imposed a ban on all Libyan-designated<br />

flights, imposed an asset freeze on assets<br />

owned by Libyan authorities, and established<br />

a panel of experts to monitor and promote<br />

sanctions implementation. However, the<br />

United States of America (USA) refused to<br />

ratify the resolution until it went further than<br />

just a ‘no-fly-zone’ alone, and only ratified the<br />

resolution once it included the clause “all<br />

177 Global Centre for the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, “Implementing the Responsibility to<br />

Protect, The 2009 General Assembly Debate:<br />

An Assessment”, GCR2P Report, August 2009.<br />

178 Richard Leiby and Muhammad Mansour,<br />

“Arab League asks U.N. for no-fly zone over<br />

Libya”, The Washington Post, March 12, 2011.<br />

179 A No-Fly Zone is an area in which aircrafts<br />

are not permitted to fly. Such zones are usually<br />

set up in a military context and usually prohibit<br />

military aircrafts of a belligerent nation from<br />

operating in the region.<br />

necessary measures to protect civilians and<br />

civilian-populated areas.” 180<br />

On March 19, 2011, a multi-state<br />

coalition implemented this resolution with the<br />

start of a military operation in Libya. This<br />

coalition was initially made up of primarily<br />

UK and French forces with the command<br />

shared with the USA. However, it soon<br />

expanded to include 19 states, among them<br />

Belgium, Canada, and Spain. NATO took<br />

control of the embargo on March 23, 2011,<br />

named Operation Unified Protector. This decision<br />

was taken after a meeting of NATO members<br />

to resolve the disagreements over whether<br />

military action should include attacks on<br />

ground forces. The decision of using NATO<br />

created a two-leveled power structure<br />

overseeing the military operations. A NATOled<br />

committee was in charge over politically<br />

overseeing the situation, whilst NATO alone<br />

was responsibility for the military action. 181<br />

The NATO military intervention<br />

included patrolling the skies over northern<br />

Libya, which would limit, if not completely<br />

eliminate, the regime’s ability to employ<br />

airpower against its population. Air-to-air<br />

missions included executing combat air<br />

patrols to counter Libyan air force assets. The<br />

exact number of serviceable aircraft is<br />

unknown, but the general assessment was that<br />

most were in various stages of disrepair. 182 It<br />

was questioned, by the international<br />

community, whether to institute a ‘no-drivezone’,<br />

however, it was felt that it would be too<br />

hard to identify who was part of the pro-<br />

Gaddafi regime and who was against it, thus it<br />

was not used. 183<br />

As of March 31, 2011, the intervention<br />

encompassed all international operations in<br />

180 CBS News, “CF-18 jets to help enforce Libya<br />

no-fly zone’, CBC News Online, March 17, 2011.<br />

181 Jason Hanover and Jeffrey White, “U.S. and<br />

NATO Intervention in Libya: Options, Risks, and<br />

Benefits”, The Washington Institute, February<br />

28, 2011.<br />

182 Ibid.<br />

183 Ibid.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 46


the country. NATO support was vital to the<br />

rebels’ victory over the forces loyal to<br />

Gaddafi. The operation officially ended on<br />

October 31, 2011, after the rebel leaders,<br />

formalized in the National Transitional<br />

Council, declared Gaddafi dead on October<br />

20, 2011 and Libya was officially liberated on<br />

October 23, 2011.<br />

The legality and legitimacy surrounding the<br />

application of R2P in Libya<br />

This section will unpack the<br />

intervention in terms of what was stipulated in<br />

the UN Resolution 1973, the principles of the<br />

R2P, and the guidelines within the UN<br />

Charter for the Use of Force looking at both<br />

the legality and legitimacy of the actions. In<br />

terms of the legality of the intervention, this<br />

paper evaluates to what extent it upholds UN<br />

Resolution 1973, what is dictated by the R2P,<br />

as well as what is upheld by the UN Charter.<br />

This is a relatively straightforward application<br />

of the facts behind the NATO intervention<br />

and the laws in place.<br />

The question of legitimacy is much more<br />

challenging to define and measure. John<br />

Locke defines legitimacy in his Second<br />

Treatise of Government in 1689 as a type of<br />

authority that is wanted, chosen, and seen as<br />

right in the eyes of the people of that country.<br />

184<br />

However, in regards to humanitarian<br />

intervention, the same definition of legitimacy<br />

does not necessarily apply. In regards to<br />

humanitarian legitimacy, there is a dominant<br />

discourse among humanitarian actors of what<br />

is considered correct. One could even say that<br />

the Code of Conduct for the International<br />

Red Cross and the Red Crescent Movement<br />

and the NGOs Disaster Relief could be<br />

considered the dominant code of<br />

humanitarian legitimacy. Not every NGO has<br />

signed this code, however, the principles it<br />

embodies are considered plausible, important,<br />

and not deeply controversial. 185 The difficulty<br />

184 Alan Buchanan, “Political Legitimacy and<br />

Democracy” Ethics, Vol 112, No 4 (July 2002).<br />

185 Jennifer Rubenstein, “The Distributive<br />

Commitments of International NGOs”, in<br />

is that the notion of legitimacy is an evolving<br />

and changing dimension and it changes<br />

depending on the situation one is in, therefore<br />

often an organization has to define what is<br />

legitimate in that situation specifically.<br />

THE RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT<br />

The Responsibility to Protect stipulates<br />

that when “national authorities manifestly<br />

[fail] to protect their populations from<br />

genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and<br />

crimes against humanity,” 186 the international<br />

community should step in, and this is, in<br />

theory, what the NATO-driven intervention<br />

did. However, when we unpack the criteria<br />

for intervention, we find more challenges to<br />

the legality and legitimacy within this<br />

application.<br />

Just Cause Threshold<br />

The just cause threshold stipulates<br />

that military intervention should only be<br />

undertaken for human protection purposes<br />

and is to be used only in exceptional and<br />

extraordinary measures. To be warranted,<br />

there must be serious and irreparable harm<br />

occurring to human beings, or imminently<br />

likely to occur such as large-scale loss of life<br />

and large scale ethnic cleansing. 187 In the case<br />

of Libya, there is no contention that the<br />

Libyan people were under threat by the<br />

Gaddafi regime. The International Committee<br />

of the Red Cross concluded that “it is<br />

apparent that Libya is now in a state of civil<br />

war.” 188 The UN stated that the conflict<br />

Humanitarianism in question: politics, power,<br />

ethics, ed. Michael N. Barnett, Thomas George<br />

Weiss (United States of America: Cornell<br />

University, 2008).<br />

186 The United Nations General Assembly, 2005<br />

World Summit Outcome, A/60/L.1, Article 138,<br />

15 September 2005.<br />

187 The Responsibility to Protect, 2001, Report<br />

from the International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty.<br />

188 Richard Leiby and Muhammad Mansour,<br />

“Arab League asks U.N. for no-fly zone over<br />

Libya”, The Washington Post, March 12, 2011.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 47


already had killed more than 1,000 people and<br />

forced more than 250,000 people to flee the<br />

country 189 and even Gaddafi himself directly<br />

threatened Benghazi’s residents, saying that<br />

the army was on its way and that “we will<br />

show no mercy and no pity.” 190 It cannot be<br />

denied that international aid was needed. In<br />

addition, it was the Arab League who called<br />

for the intervention and, according to the<br />

British Ambassador to the UN, Sir Mark Lyall<br />

Grant, “If you get a regional organization<br />

pressing for a particular course of action in<br />

the council, then that has a disproportionate<br />

influence.” 191 Based on this, one can believe<br />

there a legal just cause for the intervention<br />

into Libya.<br />

However, there are several issues of<br />

contention with how the international<br />

community reacted to the situation in Libya,<br />

which raises questions about its legitimacy. To<br />

start with, Patrick Stewert, a Council of<br />

Foreign Relations specialist, has argued that<br />

the international community has not applied<br />

the principles of intervening under a just<br />

cause when there is a threat to people<br />

universally. There has been no intervention in<br />

countries undergoing great human<br />

catastrophes, such as in the Ivory Coast in<br />

2011, or in response to the violent and bloody<br />

protests in Yemen, Bahrain, and most<br />

controversially no united, Security Council<br />

endorsed, intervention in Syria since the<br />

conflict emerged in 2012 192 . Likewise, the<br />

resolution was not implemented to stop Israel<br />

from bombing Gaza in late 2008 and early<br />

2009, which resulted in a loss of at least 1,400<br />

Palestinian lives, mostly civilians. 193 Thus, as<br />

much as the intervention may have been<br />

executed with just cause of protecting a<br />

threatened people, one has to question if there<br />

were ulterior intentions behind the decisions<br />

to invade in this case.<br />

The notion of an ulterior reasoning<br />

for the intervention has been raised several<br />

times by the world oil and business press<br />

suggesting that a central motivation was oil.<br />

Libya is the 12 th largest exporter of oil in the<br />

world, and the largest supplier in Africa. 194<br />

Several of the world’s major oil companies<br />

have invested in Libya, including ENI of Italy,<br />

Total of France, Conoco-Phillips of the US,<br />

and BP of Britain, among many others. At the<br />

time of the popular uprising against Gaddafi,<br />

there was considerable anxiety in oil circles<br />

about the possibility of generalized political<br />

breakdown and chaos, with attendant threats<br />

to oil supplies and investments and this<br />

concern was noted repeatedly in the world oil<br />

and business press.<br />

Further, as time passed, there was a<br />

growing sentiment within the United Nations<br />

that the civilian protection operation in Libya<br />

had been expeditiously co-opted by Western<br />

supporters of regime change. It was felt that<br />

NATO was no longer acting solely as a<br />

defensive shield for populations at risk, but as<br />

the Libyan rebels’ air force. India’s<br />

Ambassador to the UN, Hardeep Singh<br />

Puri, described NATO as the “armed wing”<br />

of the Security Council and argued that the<br />

objective in Libya had shifted from protecting<br />

civilians in Benghazi to overthrowing the<br />

regime in Tripoli. 195<br />

189 Ibid.<br />

190 Simon Adams, “Libya and the Responsibility<br />

to Protect: Results and Prospects” Global Policy<br />

Online, March 28, 2014.<br />

191 BBC World News, “Why the UN acted over<br />

Libya and Ivory Coast- but not Syria”, BBC<br />

World News, May 15, 2011.<br />

192 At the time of writing this paper, there had<br />

been no international intervention endorsed by<br />

the United Nations in Syria.<br />

193 Marjorie Cohn, “Stop Bombing Libya”, The<br />

Huffington Post: World Edition, March 21, 2011.<br />

194 Christoph Hasselbach and Nicole Goebel,<br />

“Disruption to Libyan oil supply highlights need<br />

for EU energy diversification”, DW Online, 3<br />

January 2011.<br />

195 Simon Adams, “Libya and the Responsibility<br />

to Protect: Results and Prospects” Global Policy<br />

Online, March 28, 2014.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 48


This argument seems to uphold<br />

further when one looks at what was requested<br />

by the Libyan opposition when they originally<br />

called for intervention. Originally, what the<br />

Libyan opposition, as well as the Arab League,<br />

asked for was a “no-fly-zone” which<br />

Resolution 1973 did provide. However, it is<br />

hard to argue that the Arab League wanted a<br />

foreign military intervention. In fact, the Arab<br />

League criticized the definition of protecting<br />

civilians that NATO used. “What has<br />

happened in Libya differs from the goal of<br />

imposing a no-fly zone and what we want is<br />

the protection of civilians and not bombing<br />

other civilians,” Arab League secretary general<br />

Amr Mussa stated. 196 The intervention did<br />

not meet the expectations that Libyan people<br />

had - it was more severe and caused more<br />

harm and destruction than was necessary.<br />

Thus, looking at the legality of a just<br />

cause principle, on paper there was a just cause to<br />

protect the people of Libya and the<br />

intervention, although destructive, did save<br />

lives. However, whether this was the real<br />

motivation behind the intervention and<br />

whether the international community acted<br />

with full transparency about their motives,<br />

makes the legitimacy behind the just cause<br />

questionable.<br />

The Precautionary Principles<br />

The Precautionary principles stipulate that a<br />

military intervention must have the purpose<br />

of halting or averting human suffering. The<br />

use of force must be the last resort. Military<br />

intervention can only be justified when every<br />

non-military option for the prevention or<br />

peaceful resolution of the crisis has been<br />

explored, with reasonable grounds for<br />

believing lesser measures would not have<br />

succeeded. Lastly, proportional means must<br />

be employed. The scale, duration, and<br />

intensity of the planned military intervention<br />

should be the minimum necessary to secure<br />

196 Zesham, “Arab League criticizes NATO<br />

strikes on Libya”, Zesham Blogspot Online,<br />

March 20, 2011.<br />

the defined human protection objective. 197<br />

This is further stated in the UN Charter,<br />

which states that the use of force should only<br />

be used as a last resort and must be endorsed<br />

by the United Nations.<br />

In terms of the justification behind<br />

the use of force in Libya, there has been wide<br />

criticism throughout the international<br />

community. Former Australian Foreign<br />

Minister and a principal author of the<br />

Responsibility to Protect concept, Gareth Evans<br />

argues that “the international military<br />

intervention in Libya is not about bombing<br />

for democracy or Muammar Qaddafi's head.”<br />

Evans suggests, “it has only one justification:<br />

protecting the country's people.” 198 However,<br />

Evans goes on to say that, “military action<br />

expressly designed to kill Gaddafi or force<br />

him into exile, to ensure rebel victory in a civil<br />

war, or to achieve a more open and<br />

responsive system of government in Libya is<br />

simply not permissible under the explicit legal<br />

terms of UN resolution 1973. Nor is it<br />

permissible under the moral first principles of<br />

the Responsibility to Protect doctrine.” 199<br />

However, it is true that the removal of<br />

perpetrators of mass atrocities can be a<br />

permissible outcome, but this motivation<br />

should not become the objective of such<br />

interventions. The R2P is mandated to protect<br />

civilians and this is what was intended with<br />

Resolutions 1970 and 1973 permitting<br />

intervention into Libya. However, this notion<br />

was stretched to justify actions, which were<br />

not necessarily imagined under the intentions<br />

of the resolutions. 200<br />

Furthermore, it is clear that the use of<br />

force was not a last resort measure. Marjorie<br />

Cohn argues that ‘all necessary measures’<br />

197 The Responsibility to Protect, 2001, Report<br />

from the International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty.<br />

198 Gareth Evans and Mohamed Sahnoun, “The<br />

Responsibility to Protect”, Foreign Affairs, Vol<br />

81, No, 6 (December 2002).<br />

199 Ibid.<br />

200 Ibid.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 49


should first have been about exploring<br />

peaceful measures to settle the conflict and, in<br />

the case of Libya, these peaceful means were<br />

not exhausted before western powers began<br />

bombing Libya. 201 In Libya, a peaceful<br />

agreement between parties had not been<br />

sought; sanctions had been applied, travel<br />

bans placed, and assets frozen, but<br />

negotiations had not been tried. In fact,<br />

NATO actually dismissed a delegation of<br />

African Union members 202 sent to start<br />

negotiations with Libya from the country<br />

before they could have achieved any results.<br />

203<br />

To elaborate on this point, this article<br />

argues there are a series of other measures,<br />

which could have been used prior to force in<br />

Libya. These include opening borders and<br />

appropriate facilities to allow Libyan civilians<br />

to flee regime violence. Considering various<br />

governments created exit routes through<br />

charter flights and land crossings for their<br />

own citizens, it should have been, not only<br />

possible, but also morally correct to create an<br />

exit mechanism for Libyans. Second, all<br />

available means for providing direct<br />

humanitarian assistance on the ground to the<br />

Libyan population should have been utilized,<br />

including aid convoys to eastern Libya<br />

through Egypt and to western Libya through<br />

Tunisia. Third, Gaddafi’s assets and those of<br />

remaining elements of the regime should have<br />

been frozen and later used to promote<br />

reconciliation and development of the future<br />

government. Fourth, governments with ties to<br />

Libya should have immediately severed all<br />

military ties, withholding delivery of material<br />

and cancelling all outstanding contracts.<br />

Finally, an arms embargo should have been<br />

imposed preventing the sale or delivery of<br />

military equipment or personnel (including<br />

201 Marjorie Cohn, “Stop Bombing Libya,” The<br />

Huffington Post, March 21, 2011.<br />

202 This delegation was made up from South<br />

Africa, Mauritius, Uganda, Mali and the<br />

Democratic Republic of Congo<br />

203 Marjorie Cohn, “Stop Bombing Libya.”<br />

foreign mercenaries) to the Libyan state<br />

security forces. Sanctions that targeted<br />

military material, services, and the movement<br />

of reinforcements from among foreign<br />

mercenaries should have been used. Sanctions<br />

that go beyond these aims would run the risk<br />

of causing more harm to civilians than to the<br />

regime. 204 Yet, instead of trying these tactics,<br />

the R2P was used as a justification for rapid<br />

military intervention.<br />

Lastly, the notion of proportionality<br />

has been another area of contention in the<br />

case of Libya when looking at “does the ends<br />

justify the means,” or, in other words, was the<br />

attack and suffering proportional to the force<br />

used. The NATO intervention and sevenmonth<br />

conflict left Libya with thousands of<br />

people dead, material damage, completely<br />

destroyed towns, and left the country without<br />

a functioning government. 205 In the sevenmonth<br />

conflict, NATO had launched 9,700<br />

strikes in an attempt to “dismantle the pro-<br />

Qaddafi military and militias.” 206 As can be<br />

expected, within these strikes, there were a<br />

significant number of civilian casualties.<br />

NATO admitted “a missile strike hit a civilian<br />

home in the Libyan capital of Tripoli today,<br />

killing a number of civilians including at least<br />

two toddlers. Though far from the first strike<br />

to kill civilians in the Libyan War, it is the first<br />

that NATO officials have admitted to.” 207 It<br />

is unknown the total number of civilians killed<br />

in the air strikes, but many questions have<br />

204 Ash Bâli and Ziad Abu-Rish, “On International<br />

Intervention and the Dire Situation in Libya”,<br />

Jadaliyya Online, February 23, 2011.<br />

205 Simon Adams, “Libya and the Responsibility<br />

to Protect: Results and Prospects” Global Policy<br />

Online, March 28, 2014.<br />

206 C.J. Chives and Eric Schmitt, “In Strikes on<br />

Libya by NATO, an Unspoken Civilian Toll”, New<br />

York Times, December 17, 2011.<br />

207 Jayshree Bajoria. “Libya and the<br />

Responsibility to Protect”, Council for Foreign<br />

Relations, March 24, 2011.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 50


een asked about the targets of the NATO<br />

strikes. 208<br />

The country, as it stands, has no functioning<br />

government and approximately 370,000<br />

people of concern, including internally<br />

displaced persons, refugees, and migrants as<br />

of December 2014. 209 The migration crisis<br />

plaguing Europe at the moment is a result of<br />

the intervention in Libya which lacked a longterm<br />

strategy for improving the lives of the<br />

Libyan people. As stated by Chives and<br />

Schmitt, “in Libya, NATO’s inattention to its<br />

unintended victims has also left many<br />

wounded civilians with little aid in the<br />

aftermath of the country’s still-chaotic change<br />

in leadership.” 210<br />

Considering the use of force in the<br />

intervention was not a last resort nor did it<br />

seem in line with what the Libyan people<br />

wanted or was executed with as minimal<br />

damage as possible, the legality and legitimacy<br />

of the use of force are questionable within<br />

this intervention especially.<br />

THE RIGHT AUTHORITY<br />

The R2P resolution states that the<br />

right authority must endorse the intervention<br />

and the Security Council is the supreme body<br />

to authorize and authorization should in all<br />

cases be sought prior to any military<br />

intervention action being carried out. 211 It is<br />

clear that the United Nation endorsed the<br />

intervention into Libya. As noted above, there<br />

is contention over the application of the use<br />

of force and interpretation of the mandate,<br />

but, in essence, the ‘right authority’ did<br />

208 C.J. Chives and Eric Schmitt, “In Strikes on<br />

Libya by NATO, an Unspoken Civilian Toll”, New<br />

York Times, December 17, 2011.<br />

209 “Libya Country Page”,<br />

http://www.unhcr.org/pages/49e485f36.html<br />

[accessed 09 November <strong>2015</strong>].<br />

210 C.J. Chives and Eric Schmitt, “In Strikes on<br />

Libya by NATO, an Unspoken Civilian Toll”, New<br />

York Times, December 17, 2011,<br />

211 The Responsibility to Protect, 2001, Report<br />

from the International Commission on<br />

Intervention and State Sovereignty.<br />

endorse the intervention. However, one issue<br />

is the fact that even though the UN was asked<br />

to intervene in the conflict in Libya, it is hard<br />

to tell who exactly asked for this intervention<br />

and who was against it; there was very little<br />

clarity in the situation about who the enemy<br />

was. In addition, the request to intervene did<br />

come from Libya, as stated above, but the<br />

strategy of the intervention was not in-line<br />

with what was requested - a no-fly zone and<br />

relief for humanitarian suffering.<br />

Thus, when reflecting on all these<br />

points and the language behind the UN<br />

Resolution 1973, the legality and legitimacy of<br />

the intervention does come into question. The<br />

intervention, as endorsed by the United<br />

Nations, should have been driven by<br />

humanitarian intentions, aiming to save the<br />

people from being further harmed by Gaddafi<br />

forces. The idea of regime change and the<br />

removal of a leader was not within the<br />

mandate from the UN nor was the use of<br />

force explicitly mentioned. It is clear that the<br />

intervention and conflict has left the country<br />

destabilized and destroyed to a large extent.<br />

Overall, it is also apparent that the<br />

legality of the intervention does meet some of<br />

the conditions of a legal intervention, but<br />

certain aspects of its application are<br />

questionable. However, in regards to the<br />

legitimacy, it is clear - the intervention was<br />

illegitimate and the actions taken were not in<br />

line with the best interest of the Libyan<br />

people or to prevent a destabilizing<br />

humanitarian situation, but were taken to<br />

remove a leader and incite regime change.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

Ultimately, it is fair to conclude that<br />

the intervention in Libya was more legal than<br />

it was legitimate, but the legality of the use of<br />

force is questionable at best. Added to this,<br />

the legitimacy of the intervention in terms of<br />

upholding principles of honesty and<br />

transparency in action is lacking entirely. As<br />

Patrick Stewert argues, “there is bound to be<br />

selectivity and inconsistency in the application<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 51


of the responsibility to protect norm given the<br />

complexity of national interests at stake in<br />

U.S. calculations and in the calculations of<br />

other major powers involved in these<br />

situations.” 212<br />

There has been widespread criticism<br />

of the intervention, especially given the<br />

current status of the country and lack of a<br />

long-term strategy from NATO. Gaddafi was<br />

killed on October 20, 2011, the war was<br />

officially declared over on October 23, 2011,<br />

and NATO forces left Libya on October 30,<br />

2011, and yet there is growing lawlessness and<br />

deadly disputes between fractious militias in<br />

the country.<br />

More immediately, however, the<br />

contrast between the Security Council’s<br />

response in Libya and its inability to take<br />

timely and decisive action with regard to mass<br />

atrocities in nearby Syria has been an issue of<br />

contention. The application of the R2P in<br />

Libya was thought to set a precedent for<br />

intervention to save people persecuted by<br />

their own state and allowed the international<br />

community to avoid situations such as<br />

Rwanda in 1994. However, its application has<br />

not been consistent and the current lack of<br />

intervention in Syria to protect the Syrians is<br />

an illustration of how the NATO intervention<br />

has not contributed to the development of<br />

good norms and practiced in humanitarian<br />

intervention.<br />

Ultimately, it can be concluded that<br />

the NATO intervention did take advantage of<br />

the UN Resolution 1973 and did manipulate<br />

the scope of the Responsibility to Protect.<br />

However, the intervention has contributed to<br />

the debate on effective humanitarian<br />

intervention by raising some serious questions<br />

for the international community about how<br />

and when to apply the Responsibility to<br />

Protect as well as when force can be<br />

authorized and the necessity for long-term<br />

strategies to any intervention.<br />

212 Jayshree Bajoria. “Libya and the<br />

Responsibility to Protect”, Council for Foreign<br />

Relations, March 24, 2011.<br />

JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 52


JPI: <strong>Fall</strong> <strong>2015</strong> Issue 1

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!